Federalist Society logo

2023 National Lawyers Convention

Originalism on the Ground

November 9 — 11, 2023


All tickets are now sold out.

November 9 – 11, 2023

The 2023 National Lawyers Convention took place Thursday, November 9 through Saturday, November 11 at the Mayflower Hotel in Washington, DC. Over three days, the Convention featured four Showcase Sessions discussing the Convention Theme of "Originalism on the Ground", eighteen breakout sessions sponsored by the Practice Groups, the Fifteenth Annual Rosenkranz Debate, the Twenty-Second Annual Barbara K. Olson Memorial Lecture, and the 2023 Antonin Scalia Memorial Dinner.

FeesLodgingCLE Information


2023 Antonin Scalia Memorial Dinner

NEW LOCATION!
The Washington Hilton
1919 Connecticut Ave NW
Thursday, November 9, 2023
Reception - 6:00 p.m.
Dinner - 7:00 p.m.
(ticketed event) BLACK TIE OPTIONAL
SOLD OUT!


Twenty-Second Annual Barbara K. Olson Memorial Lecture

Featuring

Bari Weiss, Founder & Editor, The Free Press

The Mayflower Hotel 
1127 Connecticut Avenue NW
Friday, November 10, 2023
5:00 p.m.
(ticketed event)
SOLD OUT!


Fifteenth Annual Rosenkranz Debate

The Mayflower Hotel
1127 Connecticut Avenue NW
Saturday, November 11, 2023
12:30 p.m.
SOLD OUT!


Annual Hon. Robert H. Bork Memorial Lecture

The Mayflower Hotel
1127 Connecticut Avenue NW
Saturday, November 11, 2023
4:30 p.m.
SOLD OUT!


Showcase Sessions Discussing the Convention Theme:

"Originalism on the Ground"

  • Originalism on the Ground: Roundtable
  • Whither Precedent?
  • Originalism on the Ground: Panel
  • How Originalist Is the Supreme Court?

Practice Group and Special Sessions

  • Do States Enjoy a Special Solicitude?
  • Hyperextension? Federal Financial Agencies & Cryptocurrency Regulation
  • A Creature of Statute: American Antitrust Law
  • Defend the Constitution, Save the Planet: The Role of Public Interest Groups in Shaping Environmental Law
  • Originalist Perspectives on Ethics and the Supreme Court
  • The Judiciary's Federalist Revival
  • After Dobbs and Samia: The Potential Implications of Applying a Dobbs Lens to the Supreme
  • Religious Liberty in the Work-and-Market-place
  • SFFA and Beyond
  • The Administrative State, Its Supporters and Its Discontents 
  • Originalism and the Communications Act of 1934
  • Fair Elections in an Era of Partisanship
  • FISA Section 702 Revisited: Originalist Interpretations and Constitutional Constraints
  • The Injunction Function: Is IP Law Promoting Markets for Innovators and Creators? 
  • Nightmare on Half Street? Free Speech and the NLRB
  • The Future of DEI in Business
  • Second Amendment: Will the Supreme Court Adhere to Bruen (and Originalism) in Rahimi and Beyond?
  • Mere Natural Law

 


Lodging

The Mayflower Hotel is sold out of rooms at the Federalist Society's contracted rate. There may be hotel rooms available at the Mayflower at a higher rate; please check directly with the Mayflower at 202-347-3000.

Other nearby hotels that currently have availability are:

Washington Hilton (location of Annual Dinner on Thursday, 11/9)

 

  


 

Convention Fees

The 2023 National Lawyers Convention is now sold out. 

Individual Day** 
Non-MemberSOLD OUT
Active Member SOLD OUT
Student Non-Member SOLD OUT
Student Active Member                                                SOLD OUT


**Individual day purchase includes that day’s sessions, CLE, and lunch.  It does not include social events. CLE materials will be available electronically. A hardcopy of materials can be provided upon request after the Convention, make sure to request CLE Materials in hardcopy form on the CLE sign-in form during the Convention.

Social Events 
Antonin Scalia Memorial Dinner
Non-Member
SOLD OUT
Antonin Scalia Memorial Dinner
Active Member
   SOLD OUT
Barbara K. Olson Memorial Lecture & Reception
Non-Member
    SOLD OUT
Barbara K. Olson Memorial Lecture & Reception         
Active Member
SOLD OUT

CANCELLATION FEE OF $100 AFTER MONDAY, OCTOBER 30.
NO REFUNDS WILL BE GIVEN AFTER MONDAY, NOVEMBER 6.


 


Back to top
9:00 a.m. - 9:15 a.m.
Welcome

2023 National Lawyers Convention

Topics: Federalist Society
Grand Ballroom
The Mayflower Hotel
1127 Connecticut Avenue NW
Washington, DC 20006

Event Video

Description

Featuring:

  • Hon. Dean A. Reuter, Senior Vice President & General Counsel, The Federalist Society

Speakers

Event Transcript

Hon. Dean A. Reuter:  Welcome in, everyone. If people could find a seat, please. I know we have lots of people in the hallway, but we’re going to go ahead and get started, if we could.

 

Welcome and thank you all for being here. Thank you so much. I am Dean Reuter, Senior Vice President and General Counsel of The Federalist Society. It is my pleasure to welcome you to our proceedings at this year’s convention. I want to also welcome everyone watching on the live stream or on video, as the case be. I also want to thank, in addition to you here in the room, thank our donors for their support, without whom, I suppose, we’d be hosting this meeting in a field somewhere. So thanks to those donors, large and small.

 

And thanks in advance — I never get to do this with a lot of people in the room — but thanks in advance to our staff, the staff of The Federalist Society, and it’s really not thanks in advance. They’ve been working on this for months, so thank you to them for their efforts. [Applause] A couple of logistical items. If you’re seeking CLE credit, you need to use the QR code to sign in at this point in time, and then, sign out with the same QR code. Sign in every morning, and sign out every evening. Otherwise, you’ll create some problems for yourselves.

 

Also, we have, again, this year, the folks from the Remnant Trust and their collection of rare documents. I don’t know if folks were able to visit the exhibit last year, but it really, really is splendid, and I recommend you take a moment. There are some breaks in the schedule. It’s on the second floor in the South Carolina Room. And if you were there last year, you were probably awed.

 

There is a collection of new and additional documents this year. I shouldn’t say “new” documents. They’re new “old” documents. And really, where else can you go and actually hold a 1350 copy of Magna Carta. Upstairs on the second floor is where you can do that. And you have -- you get to hold, interact with these documents, take pictures with them, tweet about it. So that’s the business items.

 

As to the introduction, a wise man once told me that a good introduction is both brief and clever, so I will at least try to be brief. Our theme this year is “Originalism on the Ground,” and that is the focus of our first Showcase Panel. This, I think, is the largest roundtable panel discussion we’ve ever had. There are more -- you could land a plane on this table probably. The fact is there are more jurists now that are more receptive than ever to originalism and textualism.

 

Now, that might give some of us in the audience in the room a sense of satisfaction or even a sense of accomplishment, a sense of even finality, well done. We’re done. But to paraphrase Churchill, this does not mark the end of any originalism project, not even the beginning of the end of the original project. Rather, we’ve come, perhaps, to the end of the beginning of the original -- originalism project. This project really is just taking off. So this is not the time to pause or suspend discussion and explication of originalism, our research and scholarship on originalism. We need to carry forth. This is the time to move forward and to carry on, and so, we shall.

 

And that, this talk about originalism, does remind me of a brief story. And it relates to the meaning of words, indeed the very meaning of originalism. Some very good friends of mine had two sons, Charlie and Ryan, both toddlers at the time of this story. Now, Charlie was the younger of the two, and he had a medical condition that required daily injections. So it was a daily struggle for the parents who had to administer these shots, sometimes in the arms, sometimes in the thigh. And anyone here with children or anybody here who was a child, you know that there’s nothing enjoyed quite so much by a toddler as an injection by needle.

 

Well, one day, Charlie was particularly resistant to his injection. And the regular compromises and bribes weren’t working, so his mother got creative and offered Charlie a new compromise. She said, “Charlie, you can have your shot anywhere you want it.” And Charlie thought just briefly and said, “I want my shot in Ryan.” [Laughter] So his mother had said he could have his shot anywhere he wanted. She meant, of course, his arm or his thigh. That’s the context.

 

But she had said, “Anywhere.” And if you look up the word, “anywhere,” in the dictionary, you’ll find out that Charlie was probably within his rights to answer as he did. But of course, originalism is something more than just original public meaning of a single word or even a single phrase. It’s more nuanced and more complicated than that. And those nuances and complications will be central to our Showcase Panel discussions at this convention, beginning with this first Showcase Panel.

 

For this roundtable, we’ve assembled experts from different parts of the law and public policy world to give various perspectives on utility and state of originalism. We’ve included practicing lawyers, judges, academics, public interest folks. Because I’ve asked our moderators throughout the convention to be brief in their introduction of panelists, I will also be brief in introducing our moderator, almost abrupt, in fact. Your program lists Judge Kevin Newsom as our moderator, but he’s encountered an emergency. He’s just fine, but he can’t be with us today. So Judge Joan Larsen is subbing in as a participating moderator for Judge Newsom, and I owe her a special thanks for that.

 

Judge Larsen, known to many of you, I expect, sits on the U.S. Court of Appeals on the Sixth Circuit. And before taking the bench, she was a long-time member of the University of Michigan Law School faculty. So for our discussions today, she’ll bring at least two important perspectives. I have to let you know. I can’t let this go without mentioning that she graduated first in her class at Northwestern University Law School, so she and I have in common the fact that we both spent some time at Northwestern Law School. [Laughter] I don’t think they had class ranks when I was there. I wasn’t informed about that. [Laughter] But with that, I will call the panel and Judge Larsen forward, please.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Welcome, everybody, to the first panel of the 2023 National Lawyers Convention. I am really excited to be here and to help moderate this discussion with a fantastic lineup of speakers. This year’s convention is focused on originalism. And when I look at the topics that will be debated over the next few days, I know it’s going to be a terrific conversation. For example, there are panels focusing on how originalism touches on particular topics, like federalism, religious liberty, and criminal law.

 

But today, we’re going to kick off our discussion with a broader lens. We’re talking about originalism on the ground, meaning how do we do originalism? And I think this topic has both normative and descriptive dimensions. So how is originalism actually being done in the real world, and also, how should it be done? And it’s also both theoretical and practical. How would we do originalism in an ideal world, and how can we do it in the world we actually inhabit with limited resources and constraints on our time?

 

And finally, we should ask how can we, as attorneys, academics, and judges, do a better job at facilitating the use of this important tool? So to bring you this topic, I have the pleasure of introducing just an all-star lineup of judges, lawyers, and academics, representing both the federal and state perspectives on this topic. Their full bios are in your program. So I’ll be brief, and I’m going to introduce our panelists in alphabetical order; although, that’s not the order in which they will appear.

 

So first, at the far end of the table, we have Paul Clement. [Applause] Paul is no stranger to The Federalist Society, as you can tell from the round of spontaneous applause. Paul served as the 43rd Solicitor General of the United States and has argued more than 100 cases before the U.S. Supreme Court. Paul is obviously a formidable litigator, but he also has an academic pursuit. And he’s so interested in that academic pursuit that he’s actually going to leave us early to go teach his class at Georgetown Law Center, so when he leaves us early, please know it’s not something that one of us said. [Laughter]

 

Next, we have the Honorable Britt Grant of the U.S. Court of Appeals for the Eleventh Circuit. Judge Grant brings not only the perspective of the Federal Court of Appeals but can also bring us a view from the states. Before her appointment to the Federal Court, Judge Grant was Justice Grant of the Supreme Court of Georgia, and before that, she was General Grant but not that one. She was Georgia’s Solicitor General.

 

The Honorable Jim Ho sits here to my left. Judge Ho serves on the U.S. Court of Appeals for the Fifth Circuit. Before taking the bench, he was a partner and co-chair of the Appellate and Constitutional Law practice group of Gibson, Dunn & Crutcher. Judge Ho, too, can share some views from the states, having served three years as the Solicitor General of Texas. And back when Judge Ho was just a baby lawyer, I had the pleasure to work with him in the Justice Department.

 

Our next speaker brings a view from the academy. Professor Bernadette Meyler is the Carla and the -- Carl and Sheila Spaeth Professor of Law at Stanford Law School. And I just butchered that, and having come from the academy, I know that it is very important to say the names of the endowed chairs correctly, so I’m going to say it again: the Carl and Sheila Spaeth Professor of Law at Stanford Law School. Professor Meyler is a scholar of British and American constitutional law and of law and the humanities. Her current book project will be of great interest to those in the audience, entitled, Common Law Originalism. It looks at various eighteenth-century common law meanings of various constitutional terms and phrases and, I take it, expresses some skepticism over our ability to lay hands on a single determinate meaning for much of the Constitution.

 

Next, we have a voice from the states. We have with us the Honorable Jason Miyares, Attorney General of the Commonwealth of Virginia. General Miyares was elected Attorney General in 2021 and, from 2015 to 2021, served in the Virginia House of Delegates. He also brings the perspective of a local county prosecutor, having started off in the Assistant Commonwealth Attorney for the City of Virginia Beach.

 

Finally, we have Elizabeth Wydra. She is the President of the Constitutional Accountability Center. In that role, she is a frequent litigator and a contributor to our national conversation on the Constitution. She joined CAC from private practice at Quinn Emanuel in San Francisco, and she, too, spent some time as a teacher, a supervising attorney, and teaching fellow at the appellate litigation clinic at Georgetown Law School.

 

So with that terrific lineup and this large panel, we have decided to dispense with the traditional format of opening statements and get right to some questions. So I will pose some questions for our panelists. Hopefully, somebody will take the lead in answering them, but others should feel free to jump into the conversation. And if time permits, we will open the questions, of course, for the audience at the end.

 

So I thought we might start with some methodological questions. And for the most part, when people talk about originalism today, we’re talking about the search for the original public meaning of the Constitution. That contrasts with an earlier vision of originalism, which focused more on a search for the intent of the Framers. But if we’re looking for original public meaning, I think we should ask the question, “What does that actually mean? Whose meaning are we seeking, and how broad is that lens?” And I think Elizabeth Wydra might have some perspectives on that topic.

 

Hon. Elizabeth Wydra:  Yeah.  Thank you so much. Thank you so much, Judge Larsen. And thank you so much, everyone here, for joining us this morning, and thank you for Dean inviting me to be here to talk about this really interesting subject with such an esteemed panel. I think that that question is still something that is being debated and disputed and explored. I come from an organization that focuses on originalism, and while we are nonpartisan, we are avowedly progressive. So when I take a look at whose voices perhaps should be included in the search for original public meaning, my lens seems to be broader than, for example, the lens that was included in Justice Alito’s Dobbs opinion or Justice Thomas’s Bruen decision.

 

And I think that it’s a challenge to us litigators to make sure that we are presenting a broad variety of voices whose opinions about the original public meaning matter. It’s a challenge to the academy, for sure, to discover, uncover the thoughts and debates of groups that have not always been the focus of historical analysis. There’s been some really fantastic recent work about the way that Native Americans understood the original public meaning of various constitutional provisions.

 

There is work out there already about how when the Reconstruction Amendments — Thirteenth, Fourteenth, and Fifteenth Amendments — were being ratified, the very rigorous debates that were going on in the African American community. And I think far too often the decisions that we see reflect the views on original public meaning of the, perhaps, most powerful group of people at the time. We are, understandably, looking back 100 years, so if you think whose voices are going to be recorded more frequently, those are probably the easiest to access. But it doesn’t mean we shouldn’t try harder because if you think about who was going to be deeply impacted, for example, by the Fourteenth Amendment, the people who had been freed after the Fourteenth Amendment from -- after the Thirteenth Amendment from enslavement certainly had a very substantial stake in what the Fourteenth Amendment meant: what kind of freedom that they had been granted in the Thirteenth Amendment, what that would mean, what the contours of that freedom would mean.

 

So to me, when I’m looking at original public meaning, looking at black newspapers from the time, looking at the way that the -- there were conventions of black activists and freed African Americans. Their debates and their views on the original public meaning certainly should be included in that lens. And, I think, as we have scholars doing more of this work, doing more of this excavation, then I think that conversation will only become richer and probably more reflective and representative of the true original public meaning of all of the folks whose views and voices should count.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Yeah. Sure. Professor Meyler.

 

Prof. Bernadette Meyler:  Yeah. I would just love to add a bit to what Elizabeth was saying, which I think is part of -- looking at the different voices also is about what kinds of governmental materials are examined in an originalist investigation. So if a court is looking primarily at, say, state statutes, then the court might be excluding a number of voices that weren’t represented at the time of the enactment of those statutes. Whereas, if we think about looking at legal practices or, say, common law meanings, that may actually allow for the inclusion of more voices than looking at state statutes because even enslaved persons often appeared before the judiciary, that there are ways of excavating different voices through, say, the common law tradition that might not be apparent within the, say, state statutes or the work of representative bodies. So I think that being attentive to what kinds of governmental sources are used as well as looking at the kinds of newspaper sources and other sources that Elizabeth was mentioning is another way of opening up the conversation when you’re looking at different voices that are part of a conversation about original meaning.

 

Hon. Britt Grant:  I’ll add one thing, too, if I might. Excuse me. I think original public meaning has become the main lens of originalism, but to Dean’s point, I don’t think that originalism as a scholarly or judicial enterprise has been completed as a project. And I’ve recently heard presentations about original methods originalism or original law originalism, and I think it’s important as we continue this project to be open to new ideas about how we can best interpret the Constitution or even statutes. I think that’s an important thing to consider.

 

When we think of originalism, we often think of just the Constitution, but in my experience, both at the state courts and at the federal court, sometimes I was looking at statutes from the 1800s to try to figure out what appellate procedure from 1964 in Georgia really meant. And so, I think it’s important to really keep our eye on all of the options for originalism as an interpretive method and to keep open, keep reading scholarship, thinking through all this -- all those different aspects of it.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Paul.

 

Hon. Paul D. Clement:  So I’d just like to, in a couple of the earlier remarks, just sort of concur in part and dissent in part. I’m not a judge, but I still like to think I can do that. [Laughter] I completely agree with Elizabeth that when you’re interpreting the Fourteenth Amendment, that taking into account the understanding of the original public meaning in the African American community’s absolutely essential. I’ve used that to argue that actually the Freedmen and the Freedmen Bureaus had a robust understanding that the Fourteenth Amendment was going to protect their Second Amendment rights. And that’s exactly what they understood was part of the protection that they were getting through the adoption of the Fourteenth Amendment. And I do think, more generally, sometimes, The Federalist Society folks, we love to look at sort of Madison and Hamilton, and we’re not as interested in the Reconstruction Amendments, and I don’t know why that would be the case.

 

The Reconstruction Amendments are hugely important to the extent that they are the vehicle through which the Bill of Rights is incorporated against the states. There’s a robust debate about what original public meaning matters: 1789 or 1868, and I don’t know how that’s ultimately going to be resolved. But personally, I think, 1868’s got to be hugely relevant, and I think some of the leading Reconstruction-era senators are folks that we ought to have -- I don’t know -- panels named after or something. I think we should really be focused on that because it’s a huge part of our constitutional history, so I totally agree with that.

 

I guess where I dissent in part is I think the project of consistently trying to unearth something that was obscure even in 1789 has really limited utility. In the context of arguing the Bruen case, the folks on the other side unearthed a third reporter of Knight’s case that was a little bit different from the two standard widely circulated reports of that decision and tried to make something of it. But there’s -- if there’s an obscure report of a case in three libraries in England and no evidence that that report ever made it to this side of the Atlantic, who cares? The idea is we don’t care about what people were thinking in 1789 just for the sake of identifying somebody that had a goofy view of an otherwise fairly clear provision in the Constitution. What we’re -- I think the point of the project is to try understand what the people who were ratifying the Constitution and discussing the Constitution -- and I’ll spot Elizabeth this: I don’t think we only care about the people who could vote in the ratification process. I think we care about everybody in the body politic on this side of the Atlantic.

 

But if you come up-- if some great scholar comes up with some private diary of somebody in their own idiosyncratic view of something, I don’t care about that. That doesn’t seem at all relevant to the project, so I do think we got to -- you got to keep in mind the whole endpoint of the project in deciding which sources you’re going to credit and which sources really move the needle.

 

Hon. Elizabeth Wydra:  I think that you’d probably fail the public part of the public meaning if it’s someone’s private diary, but I think we just have to be, I think, very cautious about noting what things might be obscured by the fact that certain historians have been doing historical work and haven’t been interested in certain voices versus what is obscured because it’s in someone’s drawer next to their bed. And so, when you’re talking about entire tribes, for example, debating parts of the Constitution that are very much relevant to their daily lives, that isn’t something that’s gotten a lot of attention because -- partly because some of the scholarly work is just beginning, but that is the type of thing that I’m saying is really important to include and making sure that -- there’s a lot of criticism, I think, of the project that people pick and choose what works best for them on both sides. And by being more inclusive with these voices, I think, we can have a richer view and more accurate view of original public meaning and also see the places where there is contestation, where there might be several different original public meanings and having to have the judges -- ya’ll have a hard job sometimes. It’s not always just super easy, one answer, and that’s going to be something that should be presented to the judges for them to interrogate themselves.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Judge Ho.

 

Hon. James C. Ho:  So just to dive into this nice exchange we’re seeing, I like information, the more data, the better, just because I’m interested and want to sort to get -- make sure I’m getting the best arguments on all sides. So in that spirit, I certainly have no concerns and would agree with Elizabeth that I want to hear about everything. Having said that, I think we would want to be sensitive, of course, to are we seeing a situation where different communities have different meanings of words. Is it sort of -- there’s ordinary meaning that the community understands, and a particular community that sees it as a term of art. Is it genuine dispute over words having different concepts, or is it really just different communities having different policy preferences? Without knowing the details of some of the cases we’re talking about here because I wasn’t involved in those, I would be curious to see to what extent the differences are differences of meaning or -- versus differences of policy preferences.

 

I like Dean’s story about the toddlers and the fear of the shots. I’ll confess it reminds me of my own kids. Allyson and I have wonderful children and, frankly, somewhat weird children. These are the only kids you’ll ever meet who do not like their birthdays because they are worried about going to the doctor for the annual exam and getting shots. I’m not kidding. They literally tell us they don’t like their birthdays for that reason. So I appreciate the story on a personal level.

 

Of course, the answer to the proposed interpretive fight in that story is does the child actually believe that anywhere means anywhere, anybody’s body, or does context make clear that it’s anywhere on his body? And so, again, he may want to say he that has a different community definition, but I do -- but I wonder if it’s more motivated reasoning than an actually good faith debate about the meaning of words.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  All right. So since we have an expert on Bruen here, Bruen introduced something that might be -- I’m not sure if it’s new, but it certainly became prominent in Bruen, and that is a discussion of this phrase, “text, history, and tradition.” And so, one thing we might want to think about is what do each of those individual items — text, history, and tradition — play in a proper originalist analysis. Tradition is the one that really stands out on the list, and Judge Newsom, who was originally going to moderate this panel, wrote in a concurrence to his own excellent opinion. He wrote a concurrence to the opinion in which he has a footnote, which raises this question.

 

He said, “It’s never been clear to me what work tradition is supposed to be doing in the tripartite “text, history, and tradition” formulation. To the extent that tradition is meant to stand in for the original, i.e. historical, public meaning of the words on the page, it’s duplicative. And to the extent that it is meant to expand the inquiry beyond the original public meaning, say, to encompass latter-day-but-still-kind-of-oldish understandings, it misdirects the inquiry.” So I guess I’ll just throw out Judge Newsom’s musings and let you all muse. Anyone want to comment on what role tradition is serving?  Paul?

 

Hon. Paul D. Clement:  I’ll take a crack at it, not that I really think it has a lot to do with having argued Bruen, but I do think this is an emerging trend. I think that that also -- when the Court noted the death of the Lemon test and talked about what would replace it, it also talked about text, history, and tradition. So this is obviously -- it’s kind of a throughline in a lot of areas of the law, and so, it would be nice if history and tradition were not like a doublet that really had no independent meaning. It seems like if the Supreme Court telling us three things, we ought to try to differentiate the last two. I think one way of thinking about it is that you could think of history as being the things that predate the relevant time period, like the Framing, if we’re talking about that, and then the tradition being what follows the Framing to the point where the Court is reaching the interpretive question. And maybe I’m sort of very, very gently taking a little bit of issue with Judge Newsom’s framing. It’s never a great idea for a lawyer. But to me, I --

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  He’s not here.

 

Hon. Paul D. Clement:  Yeah, well. That helps. That helps. But maybe a good illustration is something like the practice of legislative prayer, and does that violate the Establishment Clause? And you could look at the practice in England in the Parliament or the practice in Congress and the Articles of Confederation, and I think that you would say that’s history. And then, you would look at the fact that Congress had a chaplain in the First Congress, and all the same people that were proposing the Bill of Rights and the Establishment Clause, in particular, didn’t think there was anything problematic about having a chaplain. And then, you look at the fact that the Second Congress and the Third Congress and the Fourth Congress and the Fifth Congress and the Sixth Congress, etc., etc. all had the same thing. And then, in the 1970s, the Supreme Court is asked to say does this unbroken practice violate the Establishment Clause. Has there been a sort of lurking Establishment Clause violation going back to the Framing of the country?

 

And it seems to me that there is -- that it is perfectly appropriate for the Court to look at that tradition and to simply say, well, that stuff happened after the Framing, so it doesn’t really inform the original public meaning. I guess I would disagree, which is to say, first -- you could probably spot me the first twenty Congresses because that’s a bunch of people who might have been alive and well at the time of the Framing, but then, there is a certain humility that kicks in at a certain point. And there’s almost like a sibling resemblance with something like the major questions doctrine where just when you’re -- and whether you buy sort of the full-blown majority view or the Justice Barrett concurrence view, I think there’s a strain of judicial humility that sort of says, gee whiz, if somebody’s coming in and telling me something that has been going on a long, long time and nobody’s thought it either violated this constitutional provision or violated this statute, that is something that ought to be a strike against the person saying that this well-established practice has really violated the law all around. I don’t think it -- I think there’s probably a reason it’s third on the list. But it seems to me there is something there that’s different from history and probably does have an important role to play in interpretation.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Thoughts? Comments?

 

Hon. Britt Grant:  I think I would generally agree with that, and I would say that whether we look at tradition as a reflection of settled understandings that, as Paul says, maybe judicial humility would suggest thinking really hard before we interrupt those settled understandings or some sort of liquidation throughout time. We’ve seen Founders discussing liquidation, and there are a lot of debates about what that means. But maybe that’s an idea where, even if it wasn’t entirely clear at the beginning, if we can see that there is a tradition of interpreting something a specific way, then maybe that’s something that we could pay attention to as well. So it’ll be interesting to see, as this doctrine develops and extends in other areas, whether we reach any consensus on what tradition means with respect to those two things.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Bernadette -- Professor Meyler? Sorry.

 

Prof. Bernadette Meyler:  Yes. No, that’s okay. So I think that I see it going back a little bit further to the Washington against Glucksberg test for the Fourteenth Amendment due process inquiry and that their tradition is playing a role and a tradition of protection of particular rights. And I think that, in that context, we might wonder whether evolving tradition or a more static tradition is what should be looked to and whether -- and also how broadly a tradition can be defined. Is it a tradition of protecting parental rights per se or protecting the rights of a non-marital father? So I think that those are some of the issues that I see coming up with respect to tradition. It’s the question of how broadly a particular tradition is defined and also whether you’re looking to an unbroken tradition since the Founding or looking to the evolution of tradition.

 

And that’s where I might distinguish it a bit from what Paul Clement was saying about major questions because, in that context, it’s not just something that’s new that might be called into question under certain understandings of tradition but rather something that’s evolved away from the original meaning. So I think that sometimes there could be a conflict between, say, precedent or -- and I know there’s another panel on precedent -- and original meaning where the tradition that has evolved through precedent might have deviated from what people now think would be the original meaning of a particular clause.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Right. And I think an example of that might be if you think about the Crawford case. So we had a long tradition of substituting hearsay rules for confrontation. We did that for a very, very long time, and the Supreme Court, in Crawford, said, “No. We have to look at confrontation and what the original meaning of that is. And it’s not the same as the hearsay rules.” And so, despite the fact that there was a long tradition, we went -- we reverted to the original public meaning.

 

Hon. James C. Ho:  Well, I wonder whether that suggests what I assume to be true but -- and not controversial but would welcome people to disagree. When we talk about text, history, and tradition, what I’m assuming we really mean is text. Text is what we’re looking at, whether you call it textualism or originalism. That’s what we’re interpreting as lawyers and judges. It’s to the extent where the text has -- is ambiguous. It’s capable of different of meanings -- competing communities, what have you, where we then look to other tools, whether it’s dictionaries or history or tradition or canons of interpretation or anything else.

 

You mentioned Glucksberg, and whether it’s Glucksberg or Bruen, I think, frankly, we’re all sort of eagerly awaiting to see what the Supreme Court tells us it means when it refers to history and tradition. Glucksberg seems to be the standard, revived and recodified in Dobbs. Tradition could, theoretically, include a lot of things. It does include economic liberty. You referred to parental rights. If we’re serious about tradition in addition to text, that opens up a whole new area of analysis, or is tradition subservient to text, which might take us to a different path. And I think the Supreme Court presumably will tell us at some point.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  So maybe the test, as you would propose it, is text as informed by history and tradition?

 

Hon. James C. Ho:  I assume that’s what we’re doing, but I’m waiting for the Supreme Court to teach us, so I can do what they’re telling us to do. It’s not always easy to do what they want us to do.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Fair. Speaking of -- that’s a perfect segue. So let’s talk about precedent. So what role does an originalist analysis preserve for precedent? Do we think of precedent as part of originalism, as sort of being baked into Article III’s reference to the judicial power? Or is precedent antithetical to a true consistency -- consistent commitment to originalism? Do the practitioners on the panel think differently about this than the judges? Anybody want to talk about precedent? Nobody wants to talk about precedent. Okay. So the Supreme Court -- I’ll talk about precedent.

 

Hon. James C. Ho:  It’s like Bruno.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  So the Supreme Court has told us -- for those of us on the panel who are middle managers, right, appellate judges, we have to do what our nine bosses tell us, and we try very hard to faithfully follow what they tell us. And one thing that they have told us very clearly -- you might call this -- I like to call it the Agostini principle. Some people call is the Rodriguez [inaudible 00:50:39] principle. But one thing they’ve told us very clearly is that when there is a case that is directly on point, even if we the lower court judges look around and think, “Gosh, the foundations of this precedent have been undercut. It doesn’t seem consistent at all with the way that the Supreme Court is telling us to approach cases.” Now, the Supreme Court has told us, “You are to apply our precedent when there’s a case directly on point, and we, the Supreme Court, will overrule our own precedence. Thank you very much, lower court judges, for your input.”

 

So I try to do that because that’s what they told me to do. But one thing that I think about often is whether that’s consistent with the judicial role. If you think that a case is wrongly decided, if it’s a case that wasn’t decided using an originalist methodology, if you think it’s a case that you’re pretty sure the Supreme Court would overrule, what do you do as a lower court judge? So I can toss that out to the other judges, or I can keep talking, but it’s probably more interesting to hear from you.

 

Hon. James C. Ho:  I’ll take a quick stab at it. So this is one of these eternal debates that I have with -- I’m sure many judges have with law clerks, which is -- the argument will be, “Judge, you didn’t swear an oath to uphold Supreme Court precedent. You swore an oath to uphold the Constitution. So does that suggest that you get to do whatever you want in terms of interpreting the Constitution?” It’s an interesting argument.

 

It’s obviously trying to look at the words of the oath, and it’s a view that’s held by, to my knowledge, not a single member of the federal judiciary, [laughter] for any number of obvious reasons. It’s a hierarchal; we don’t want to be fired; we don’t want to overturned, etc., etc. Or if it’s anything else, you’re just kind of bumping your head against the wall. Right? The Supreme Court’s going to do what it’s going to do, and we have to follow it.

 

The way I’ve tried to reconcile it — and I often cite Judges Bumatay and Bush because they’ve written a lot on this topic — is we’re duty-bound to -- if you believe in originalism, which I just sort of think of as lawyering, then we’re duty-bound to be faithful to the text and original understanding of whatever words we’re supposed to be interpreting to the maximum extent permitted by a faithful reading of Supreme Court precedent. Now, obviously there are some words there that require further fleshing out, and I’m interested in sort of seeing how we flesh these out in future cases, but the point’s -- to me, the main things are maximum extent consistent with a faithful reading of precedence. That’s sort of how I try to wrestle with it at a sort of abstract level, and now, we have to sort of implement that in subsequent cases.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Does that mean that you would read a precedent -- the strict command is when there is a case directly on point. And does that influence how broadly or narrowly you read the precedent?

 

Hon. James C. Ho:  I think that’s what the word, “faithful,” is doing. Right? So you could say, “Well” — to use a very silly, stupid example — “the facts of that case -- that Supreme Court were done on a Tuesday. This is on a Wednesday. Obviously, that’s not faithful.” And so, you have to figure out what is the precedent. What is the rule that is being imposed on us by that Supreme Court decision?

 

And we try to be faithful to it, but we don’t have to extend it to situations that go outside of it. I fully acknowledge that leaves a lot of open discussion for what does it mean to be faithful, and as I said, that’s -- one sort of modest thought that I’ve seen fleshed out is you don’t want to make the law completely illogically by making it -- by distinguishing in ways that are utterly unprincipled. And so, that might be an initial take on that.

 

Hon. Britt Grant:  I think the question for us is very different than, of course, the question for the Supreme Court. Right? So I think they -- I think the question that they deal with is, to my mind, the most difficult one in originalism, which is where is that line between sticking with precedent, and it’s -- in certain cases, you know you have to overturn it. Right? We all know the classic cases that I won’t list here, but I think for us, as circuit judges, it’s a different question. I think I agree with Judge Ho about reading -- I won’t resay what he said either, but I think sometimes, though, there’s a kind of administrative rule to precedent that we also forget about.

 

I think the Eleventh Circuit has a unique background in this because, having split from the Fifth Circuit, the court made a very conscience decision to adopt all the precedence of the Fifth Circuit for our own. So in almost every single Eleventh Circuit case, you’ll see a footnote citing Bonner v. City of Prichard. I’m maybe messing that up, and I see it so much. But the point was the fact that a panel of this court may come out differently on one issue one time was not worth all of the upset to people’s understanding, lawyers’ understanding, litigants’ understanding of how they needed to put their behavior forward. So I think, as a -- on kind of the smaller issues, I think precedent becomes very important as an administrative matter. And then, on the more publicly divisive issues, I think it’s really interesting to see how we can apply some of those same tools in a thoughtful way and make sure that we’re fulfilling our duty to the Constitution and as intermediate appellate court judges as opposed to the ultimate deciders on the Supreme Court who, as you say, give us certain instructions about what to do.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Right. So I wonder to what extent that Agostini principle influences the way that lawyers think about presenting arguments to intermediate appellate courts. So if you’re a litigator and you think, “Look, this case is governed by precedent; it’s a constitutional question, but it’s governed by precedent,” are you just going to argue the precedent and then save the originalist fire for the U.S. Supreme Court? Or do you think about, “Well, maybe there’s an opening here; maybe there’s a way to read the case narrowly, the precedent narrowly,” and convince the panel that there’s an opening?

 

And part of this -- I wonder about this because, having been on the federal court now for, I don’t know, five years, maybe six years, we get very little briefing in our court that engages actual originalist methodology. There’s a case the Supreme Court just heard called Culley v. Marshall. I think that was last week. It involves the forfeiture of automobiles and whether you have a right to a pre-termination hearing when your vehicle is forfeited. Our court had decided a merits case on that. I was not on that panel, but the case was presented to a panel I was on earlier, the same question, and we dismissed at the motion-to-dismiss stage, so we didn’t reach the merits.

 

But in that litigation, there was no originalist briefing whatsoever of -- the litigation, as I recall, involved should we apply one of two doctrinal tests made up by the Supreme Court, the -- a balancing due process -- Mathews v. Eldridge balancing test or the Barker v. Wingo, also balancing test, out of the Speedy Trial Clause. And that’s the way the case was framed. I’m listening to the oral arguments last week, thinking, “Oh, I know what this case is about,” and they’re talking about, “Well, should we follow the historical analysis presented to us by this group of amici or by this group of amici?” And I thought, “Wow. It really would have been helpful to have some group of amici. That might have really been a nice thing.”

 

So, I guess, the question is as somebody litigating in the appellate courts, do you present your originalist case? Should you present your originalist case, or should you just hold your fire for the Supreme Court when all the guns will come out, and they’re going to get the best advocacy, and they can come to the best conclusion that way?

 

Hon. Jason Miyares:  I think it has been an interesting transformation, particularly in the state courts, what we have seen, where they’re now -- traditionally, they have outsourced and not used federal interpretation to interpret their state statutes. I think we’ve seen the opposite in the last several years, almost a revolution. I know that we have a case in Virginia, the West Point School Board case, where we actually made the argument to our solicitor, Andrew Ferguson, I think, quite robustly, looking at the Virginia statute of religious freedom and also looking at the -- both the original intent and the tradition of that. That was originally introduced in 1779 in the Virginia General Assembly at the genesis of Thomas Jefferson carried by a young, quiet delegate from Orange County, James Madison, with vehement opposition by a very vocal member of the General Assembly named Patrick Henry. And the origins of that really was that Patrick Henry had introduced legislation that was going to seek state support for the newly minted Episcopal Church in Virginia. Problem is almost every other Christian sect was horrified by this, and there was some vehement opposition.

 

And so, when we looked at -- when our solicitor argued it, we pointed out — in Virginia and it was reaffirmed; it was actually passed in 1786 by the General Assembly, and it was reaffirmed in 1971 — that the Virginia statute provide much more robust protections than the First Amendment Free Exercise Clause. And so, I thought we were able to make, I think, a pretty compelling argument, looking at the history of that, of the very explicit language that nobody should be burdened by practicing their religious beliefs by the state. And I’m not going to necessarily get into the facts of the West Point case because, candidly, it’s still pending in front of the Supreme Court. But I thought that was a great example of both using originalism and the precedent of what our case law was in a new setting in state court, which previously hadn’t really been done before.

 

Hon. Paul D. Clement:  Yeah. And Judge Larsen, I think from the perspective of federal court practice, at least the way I would answer the question, is it depends. And it depends where you are in the litigation. Are you trying -- where is the precedent? Is this a case where you really think you can maneuver around a Supreme Court precedent? If you are -- if the whole point of the litigation is to get a Supreme Court case overruled and the lower cases are hemmed in by the Agostini approach, then I don’t think there’s any point in pretending that those courts can overrule Supreme Court precedent. I think, in those circumstances, there’s one of two playbooks, and I’ve seen people do it both ways.

 

There’s a playbook that, I think, Mike Carvin used in trying to get the overruling of Abood back in front of the Court after the Court had signaled it, and he basically went into district court and said, “Hello. I lose under Abood. Please rule against me very quickly.” And then, he went to the Ninth Circuit and said, “Hello. We lose under Abood. Please rule against us very quickly.” And then, he filed the cert petition and got cert granted.

 

So that’s one approach. But you got to be pretty confident, a, that there’s no wiggle room, and, b, that there’s going to be a cert granted at the end of the rainbow. And so, if you’re litigating in a situation where it’s not that clear, you’ll try to get around it. You might use originalism. But I guess, this gets to a broader question, which is -- one reason you might do that as a litigant is one of the things that I think is a legitimate move for court of appeals judges, notwithstanding the Agostini principle, is there is this thing called the concurring opinion. I know Judge Ho’s used those from time to time.

 

And I don’t think there’s anything wrong with basically a judge saying, “I’m totally bound to apply the Supreme Court precedent, but I’m going to tell you in my concurring opinion why I think it’s wrong and why I think it would be useful if the Supreme Court revisited it.” And I think that’s both legitimate and, frankly, important because one downside of the Agostini principle is -- it’s great, and it’s orderly, but then, it doesn’t provide a great signaling device to the Supreme Court of the United States as to when they should reconsider their precedence. And they turned down a lot of cert petitions in my experience, so having something like a concurring opinion to point to can be really helpful.

 

Then, let me just say one other thing, which is -- so I think your point, Judge Larsen, really points to the -- kind of a broader phenomenon, which is one thing that’s a little weird about our system is that cases look a lot different in the court of appeals typically than they do in the Supreme Court of the United States. And that’s kind of weird in a system that’s supposed to be about that vertical review. And part of it is inevitable. The average court of appeals case probably has four or five issues in it, and they have to cover all those in the word limit. And then, it gets up to the Supreme Court, and there’s just a single issue there. The number of amici is generally smaller. I guess my thought, though, is if I were a court of appeals judge, I would, in cases that I think had a good chance of getting to the Supreme Court, I would try to narrow that gap.

 

And again, I think there are legitimate ways to do that. One example is that the -- if you have cases where it’s almost inevitable that the Supreme Court is going to call for the views of the solicitor general and be quite interested in what the solicitor general has to say, if I were a lower court judge, I would call for the views of the government -- the relevant government agency myself. Otherwise, it seems like you’re setting yourself up for failure because the Supreme Court’s going to be looking at something that’s very influential to them that you didn’t even give yourself a chance to look at. And similarly -- and maybe the judges on the panel would disagree with me, but I think if you’ve got a case where you really think this could go to the Supreme Court and you think there’s important historical literature that amici could bring to bear and the parties have dedicated all of three paragraphs to the argument, I don’t think there’s anything legitimate -- illegitimate, rather -- about a supplemental briefing order that invites the participation of amici.

 

Again, maybe you think that’s overreaching. Maybe you think that violates the strict Silberman-esque view of the Article III courts are stuck with the briefing of the adversarial parties, no matter how lousy. But I tend to think that’s a legitimate move, and it narrows that gap because I would think it’s very frustrating, as a court of appeals judge, to have the Supreme Court deciding an issue where, by the time it gets to the Supreme Court, it just is unrecognizable.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  That’s actually one of the first things now Chief Judge Sutton said to me when I came on the court is, “There’s a lot of things you’re going to learn about what it’s like to be a court of appeals judge, and one of those things is you’re going to decide a bunch cases, and they’re going to get upstairs, and you’re not -- you’re going to say, ‘Oh, wow. I didn’t know that’s what this case was about.’”

 

Hon. Elizabeth Wydra:  So I just want to apologize. One of the briefs that Justice Barrett was talking about in the Culley oral argument was indeed filed by the Constitutional Accountability Center, so I apologize for not filing that brief in your case.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Accepted.

 

Hon. Elizabeth Wydra:  Yes, it is truly a resources bandwidth question. But it’s -- that is, I think, a :real issue for the lower court cases because -- and it could be solved, as Paul suggests, by inviting amicus participation, but good originalism takes time, and it takes expertise, and particularly, on the left, there are not that many of us who are practicing it. And CAC is small but mighty, but we can only do so many cases. And I like my fellow colleagues to be able to sleep some time. And so, being able to write briefs that have that rigorous, credible originalist analysis takes a lot of work.

 

And so, it’s one thing when it’s in the Supreme Court, but it’s another trying to cover all the ground of the courts of appeals. And I think that’s a real challenge for judges because then are you trying to do it yourself. Are you asking for amicus participation? As a litigator, I want to give you the best argument, so I would like for my side -- whatever side I’m advocating for to be giving you those arguments. But that is not always possible in every case.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Yeah. Professor Meyler.

 

Prof. Bernadette Meyler:  Yeah. I was very curious about everyone’s take on whether or not to invite amicus participation at the appellate level, but I also wanted to introduce another element, which is just that I think some Supreme Court cases are directly lower courts, especially district courts, to actually engage in more originalist inquiry, especially if you think about the aftermath of Bruen, that in order for the government to kind of demonstrate that there were analogous statutes at the time of the Fourteenth Amendment, that, in a way, they’re going to have to already be doing originalist analysis at the district court level. And I’m also curious about how people feel about the expenditure of time on originalist analysis in that context as well.

 

Hon. James C. Ho:  So just to follow up, there are two things that have been said that I -- that are interesting to me. One is the resource limitation issue, and the other is the amici aspect. So on resource limitation, I was actually a litigator, an appellate litigator, longer than I’ve been a judge, and what strikes me as resource limitations are a huge issue on both fronts. In practice, obviously, it’s the limitations of your client. Some clients want to do full [inaudible 59:07]; other clients won’t. I think Paul is absolutely right. It depends on the nature of the case. The lawyer has to make the call about what’s valuable.

 

The resource limitations issues is also very serious in the judiciaries, particularly court of appeals. As practitioner, let’s say you argue, what, one case a month, one every other month, more than that. Whatever the number is, it’s some handful of cases that you’re getting involved with on a per-year basis. That provides you a decent -- hopefully, a decent amount of time, assuming your client’s willing, to really get in deep to make sure you’ve maximized every aspect of whatever legal issues are presented in your case. On the Fifth Circuit, we do 20 arguments per sitting, per month, seven sittings a month, and that’s just the argue cases in addition to all the other matters that we have to deal with. And so, the resource limitations are very serious, and so, we are essentially looking to lawyers to present briefs that are hopefully well-written and cover the waterfront.

 

And the way I think of it is if it’s not in the briefs and we think it’s important, we can dive in ourselves and try to -- obviously, we have party-presentation issues and forfeiture issues and whatnot, but as long as you presented the issue, we could theoretically do our own additional -- make sure you found all the cases and all the right authorities. But what I struggle with is every single minute I spend diving deeper on one case is time I’m taking away from every other case on my docket, never mind my family and my sleep. And so, I think the resource limitations on both sides of the bench, the podium and on the bench, are important aspects of this issue.

 

As to amici, I like amici. I liked it when I was a practitioner. I think they can be helpful. Obviously, the “Me Too” type of amicus brief where you’re just repeating what somebody else says, that not terribly helpful. It’s just a waste of space. But when it’s a good amicus brief, that can be wonderful.

 

And it’s not necessarily that the practitioner -- the party lawyer has messed up. Maybe they’ve omitted something, but maybe the amici has an angle that it’s more awkward for a particular party to present. I was involved in a case, one of these pre-Bostock-type cases where we invited amici, one particular amici, to argue because neither side had argued that Title VII doesn’t apply to certain classifications. So we invited amicus to do that. Having said that, I get nervous about doing that too much. I’m not sure why. Maybe it’s the silver mask view of the world. I certainly would be wary about playing favorites, signaling where a court is.

 

In the case that I mentioned where we did it, it was literally because we had one side of the case not represented. And so, we needed somebody to literally fill in a position. It’s sort of like when the Supreme Court invites somebody when the government confesses error. It’s that sort of thing. You just want the adversarial process. Beyond that, I’m -- put me as not sure.

 

Hon. Jason Miyares:  And I would say, just from the attorney general’s perspective, what we have seen is, particularly when you’re looking at amicus, you have state AG offices that are very under-resourced, and often times, they will look to team up with states with larger AGs office that maybe are aligned philosophically. And essentially, it’s a way to pull our resources together, which we do all the time, whether it’s a multi-state investigation. But we’ve found that repeatedly, what I have seen — it’s actually one of the things that has surprised me in my role is how much coordination there is with the other comparable state AGs and their SGs in working together on amicus briefs, almost like assigning homework assignments, of, “Can you help state X on this matter?” And everybody does each other a kind of solid when they need assistance themselves. And I have found it invaluable because what you’re able to do is you’re to engage more and maximum your resources, and you’re really able to help some of these states that have very, very small SG offices and able to really assist them, to provide resources. So I view it as invaluable.

 

Hon. Britt Grant:  I’ll add two things. First, to follow up on his comments, when I moved from private practice to the state attorney general’s office, I almost immediately within six months thought, “Wow, if at least a few of these cases that I was, I wish that we had reached out to relevant attorney general offices to ask them if they would be interested in filing an amicus brief to tell them about this case that was going to really affect the states in very particular ways.” And the courts didn’t have the states’ perspectives, and I think it might have made a difference in at least one and maybe two cases that I can think of right off the bat.

 

So I would say don’t ask states -- as he says, there are resources issues. Don’t ask states just willy-nilly but really think through. If you’re litigating an issue that’s going to make a big a difference to the states, it’s going to have an impact on state laws, even if it’s a federal case, then don’t hesitate to try to find those connections, try to reach out to the attorney general’s office, and let them know about the case. They may or may not be able to get involved, but I think the states do have a very important perspective in our system that -- thankfully, the states are litigating more and more and filing amicus briefs more and more. But I think it’s an area that still has room for additional growth.

 

And the other thing I’ll say about the adversarial process is so many of our doctrines are designed around the adversarial process. Right? Standing has been a really big question in the Supreme Court and the circuit courts lately. And I think when we think about doing it all on our own, we forget that so much of our system is designed around the idea that litigants will have the right incentives when they have a problem to really try to figure out the best arguments in favor of their position. And as judges, we’re just not always situated to figure out the best arguments in favor of one position and to realize that there are arguments on the other side, maybe from perspectives that we haven’t considered. And so, to my mind, briefing is really important and really helpful almost any time you’re digging into one of these questions. And I hope that, in both state and federal courts, we’ll start to see more of it as lawyers become aware that a lot of judges are thinking about these things in different and expansive ways.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  So we’ve been talking a lot about -- almost exclusively, about originalism as it’s practiced in federal court. We have here a former state Supreme Court justice. We have the attorney general of a state. General Miyares touched on this already a little bit, but I wonder whether there’s something different about doing originalism when you’re talking about interpreting a federal constitution, which the wrap on originalism that you hear on the -- from its critics is, ‘Oh, the federal Constitution is old, and it’s impossible to amend, and therefore, the judges need to update it.” That would be the critique.

 

I wonder whether that same -- those same concerns exist in most of the states, not all, for those of you on the Eastern seaboard. For those of you from Massachusetts with your Constitution of 1780, okay, I yield. But I come from a state which ratified its most recent constitution in 1963, so it’s not old, and it’s not hard to amend. It’s super easy. You can amend the Michigan Constitution -- not super easy but comparatively easy. You can amend the Michigan Constitution by initiative. We saw it happening in states just yesterday. And so, I wonder whether the arguments against originalism have less weight in state courts, and I wonder whether there’s anything different about doing originalism when we’re talking about a state constitution.

 

Hon. Jason Miyares:  At least from my perspective, Jefferson called the states the laboratories of democracy, and I find it fascinating that you’re having this kind of, not revolution, but a rethinking — Judge Sutton and others that have really pointed at using originalism in our state constitution. Obviously, Virginia and Massachusetts and others have a unique history of our own, just given the both depth and breadth and the history. But I think it’s absolutely a useful tool. Every state amends their constitution differently, as we all know. Obviously, Ohio does it by referendum. You have to have a requisite number of petition signatures to get it on a ballot, and then, it’s simply 50 percent of the voters.

 

In Virginia, it has to be passed by the General Assembly, both the House and Senate. It never goes to the governor’s desk. There has to be an intervening election of the Virginia House of Delegates, and then, the newly constituted General Assembly has to vote on the exact same measure, the exact same wording, cannot change so much as a comma. And then, if it passes, then it has to go to be ratified by the voters that November. So the Virginia Constitution is more difficult to amend than, say, the Ohio Constitution, but obviously, we have an amendment process that probably some would say would be easier than amending the federal Constitution.

 

I view it as an absolute tool that should be used at the state appellate level. I don’t think you should outsource it to a federal interpretation. I think you should look at -- I think you should have your state judges be looking at both the history, tradition, and the original meaning of the text because our constitution is relatively new in Virginia. And so, I think we’re in a totally different place than maybe what other people think, but from my perspective, I view it as an absolute useful tool, and I’d like to see more judges using it in Virginia, applying it to our state constitution and state law.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Go ahead. Professor Meyler.

 

Prof. Bernadette Meyler:  A thought about using originalism in the state context. So I think one of the reasons, potentially, for the move to original public meaning rather than original intent is the fact that we have no official notes of the federal convention that established the Constitution. We have Madison’s notes on the Convention, but it was not supposed to be recorded. So there’s a way in which there is a lack of contemporaneous information. We have to derive insights from a retrospective account or from very piecemeal accounts of various participants.

 

Of course, that’s not exactly the case with the Reconstitution Amendments. We can look at the Congressional record for those. But I think that that influences a bit the tone of originalism within the federal context, and I think that the fact that, in a lot of state contexts, we do have availability of deliberations about the constitution perhaps might lend itself towards having more argument about what the meaning of particular clauses of a state constitution might be based on the original intent rather than original public meaning.

 

Another consideration, though, I think does have to with the referendum process. And I know, coming from California, there are a number of fairly poorly drafted measures that have been put on the ballot, and it’s not entirely clear that the public explanations given for them were accurate or really reflected what the language actually says, and the drafting itself isn’t really very easy to pin down. So I think that that raises some complications. What exactly were voters voting on? And it raises some questions about how to kind of interpret a clause like that. And I think that that is somewhat different from the federal context where amendments go through a much more rigorous and much more lengthy process. And so, you would have a lot more material to go on in terms of determining what the original public meaning of a federal amendment was.

 

Hon. Elizabeth Wydra:  I think that’s a really great point about the availability of sources and clear sources for some of these analyses because if we don’t do a rigorous analysis, then it’s not really helpful to the judges. One area in which Constitutional Accountability Center has been able to participate in state courts, even with resource limitations, is many state constitutions incorporate by reference either the text explicitly or the values of the Fourteenth Amendment or the Declaration of Independence. And so, we’ve been able to file in state cases under state constitutions that include that reference because we have done the originalist work on those amendments and the principles and values of the Declaration of Independence.

 

Hon. Britt Grant:  You see in state constitutions, I think, interesting interpretive principles, and legal fiction sometimes start to take place. And one thing that you said reminded me. On Georgia constitutional amendments, the rule -- obviously, the amendment is typically longer than you can have on the ballot, and the rule that the Georgia Supreme Court put in place decades ago is the description on the ballot has to be enough to let the voter know which constitutional amendment they’re voting on under the legal fiction, that that will allow everyone to think back to the time when they personally and individually before the vote reviewed the text of the constitutional amendment in full to determine whether they wanted to vote for it. So it’s interesting.

 

In Georgia, too, there’s a rule that we -- if you -- if the Georgia Supreme Court had an interpretation of a provision and then the constitution was amended on a large-scale basis and that provision stayed, then the view is that the writers of that particular constitution were aware of this Georgia Supreme Court opinion and did not intend to change it in any way. So that’s locked that provision in, almost in perpetuity. And so, I think some things are certainly easier because we have more modern language, especially with the amendments, but some things are a little bit harder because of these interpretative conventions and some of the difficulties with the direct-to-the-people voting that we’ve discussed. So I think there are things that are easier, things that are harder, but I don’t think that it -- I don’t think it makes it more defensible to do it because I think it’s our duty as judges to interpret what the law is. And whether you’re at the state or the federal level, the Constitution, until it’s changed, is the law, and it’s our job to figure out really what that said and to give our best effort and use all the tools that we have.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Okay. So we’ve talked about federal courts, and we’ve talked about state courts. And I don’t want to put too much burden on Professor Meyler, but I don’t think we should neglect the academy. And so, I have two broad questions. The first is probably directed specifically to Professor Meyler, which is she’s an actual legal historian, and so, one question I have is how does a historian approach originalism, the process of divining the public meaning of a particular constitutional provision. And does that differ from the way that courts and judges might do that, or is it the -- basically, the same project? So that’s my first question. And then, I guess, the second question would be are the law schools helping. Are they helping us to -- helping our -- the students to become practitioners who can deploy these tools?

 

Prof. Bernadette Meyler:  Great. Well, thank you so much for giving me that opportunity. So I would say that historians -- and I’m not a PhD in history. I’m a PhD in English, so I think of myself as doing work on kind of interpretation as well as history, although my work was in early modern England. And I think that one way in which historians approach originalism may be differently than lawyers or practicing lawyers does have to do with the resource question that came up earlier because, I think, we have more opportunity to delve in-depth into particular provisions over a longer period of time. We can do archival research that might take a very long time.

 

I had a project that dealt with the New Jersey decisions, pre-Constitution, of the various local courts in New Jersey. And it turned out that the archives and records in New Jersey couldn’t find the materials for a year, but then, that was fine because my project could take two years. That would not be okay on an appellate court level. So I think that that’s one way in which there is a big difference.

 

Another difference, I think, has to do with one of purpose. Right? So my colleague, Jonathan Knapp (sp), has recently written a book on originalism and history. We are -- he is bringing forward various ways in which historians would critique the practice of originalism for contemporary purposes and looks at a variety of different factors of why there might be a different objective in unearthing the history as opposed to applying it today. And one of the main issues really has to do with context, right, so that if we’re bringing to light some original meaning of a clause from 1789, then we may be taking it out of the context in which it was created. There may be -- according to Jonathan’s account, a written constitution meant something different in the 18th century than it does today. By deracinating the -- a provision from the general constitutional context, we’re misunderstanding it.

 

Now, I think that it’s important, nevertheless — and this is sort of my interpretive lens — to try to create some form of continuity between the moment of the Founding and today, that we can’t just take it as an alien document that was one thing then and is another thing now so that there is a need to engage in interpretation in the same way as we would try to interpret Shakespeare today and have a relevance for Shakespeare today. But I do think that because historians have more, say, time on their hands to engage in the effort that there’s going to be a survey of more sources. There’s going to be more openness to a less determinant meaning. Right? So I think that a lot of the clauses, if you look at a lot of the original materials from the colonies as well as from England, you see that there isn’t necessarily one determinant meaning that can be pinned down of the common law background of the Constitution. I think that’s not as much of a problem for historians as for judges who are trying to apply the Constitution in the present.

 

And on the front of our law schools helping, I think it’s an interesting question of what exactly the law school pedagogy is now. So teaching a first-year law school discussion seminar on histories of legal education and if you look from Langdell, who founded the American legal education system through the present, there is a remarkable continuity, actually, of what are the required first-year classes, and based on Langdell, we focus almost entirely on cases. Right? And that’s the -- case method was kind of sanctified in the late 19th century as the way that we approach teaching law students. And I think that some originalists, certainly my colleague Michael McConnell is among these, have kind of brought in more original sources in teaching the Constitution. I bring it in in my classes sometimes. And in other classes, we have deep dives into history.

 

There’s more interdisciplinarity, so I think that more historians are teaching in law schools by one count of one my colleagues. At a meeting recently, he thought we have nine legal historians on the faculty. So there’s an effort to kind of bring in more of those perspectives. But I think that actually, in the last 150 years, law schools have changed less than we might think and that the case method is still the dominant method and that that means that precedent rather than original meaning tends to be what’s focused on.

 

Hon. Jason Miyares:  I think there is an enormous crisis in higher ed in general, but I also think, in law school, you have a suffocating level of political correctness and progressive orthodoxy that has a view of originalism as immoral, and therefore, they won’t teach it, or if they do teach it, they play lip service. And think of the utter shock for so many of these law school graduates that suddenly are encountering judges that have that as part of the expectations. And I think you have a real crisis right now. You have elite law schools, in particular, that are preaching diversity in everything but thought. There is simply almost virtually no ideological diversity whatsoever. And I think that is creating a real, real problem right now.

 

We have a robust intern program in the AG’s office, so we get students from both Ivy League schools and state schools in Virginia. And I will tell you the conversations that I’ve had with so many of those young students who are incredibly bright that are interning in our office -- the only word I would use to describe how they are seeing America, in general, is disdain, utter disdain. And they are really struggling right now with self-censure ship. The leave of fear that these students have on these campuses is palpable, and it is not conservative professors. And so, I -- it is one of the most troubling, long-term trends that I see right now for this country, in general, when over 50 percent of those ages 18 to 24 say, for example, that Hamas is justified in slaughtering innocent men, women, and children, and less than a third say they have a love of America. I don’t think that happened by chance, and I think, unfortunately, what you’re seeing in our undergrad campuses, I would multiple it even higher in so many of our elite schools. So I think they are not equipping students to come out properly trained in how to look at originalism because, like I said, they view originalism as immoral. And I think it is a real troubling long-term trend in higher ed right now.

 

Hon. Paul D. Clement:  And just one thought on this. Look, I love legal historians as much as the next person, but I don’t think the solution to this problem is adding legal historians to law school faculties. And part of it is, I think, we’re -- by the time we start focusing on originalism and the work of legal historians — and again, I don’t mean to denigrate that; that’s -- there’s a reason that’s always been a discipline, even back in the ‘70s, when the Supreme Court didn’t give a fig about originalism — but it really is a little bit separate. And I think that the way that -- the best thing a historian could do is -- could unearth some new thing that nobody else knew was not part of the original public meaning, or a lot of what of legal historians spend their time doing is coming up with a revisionist history so everything we thought we knew about something gets turned on its head. And I would imagine there’s a few people in academia whose whole project in legal historian -- in legal history is really to defeat originalism and show that you can come up with a counter-history to everything. And that’s why I have to get back to the project, and I think Judge Ho had it exactly right when he said the project is text informed by history and tradition.

 

And so, I think we may be overmystifying originalism to the point where, oh, no mere lawyer can do this and you need a legal historian to do this. And if that’s the case, then I kind of think that either the Supreme Court took a wrong turn or we all took a wrong turn by going getting our Juris Doctors instead of our PhDs in history. But I don’t think either the Court or this group has taken a wrong turn. I think we just got to get back -- that, yes, history and tradition is important to inform the text. Part of the reason that Justice Scalia was on about this project was to constrain the discretion of judges and to give them clear targets to shoot at that are consistent with life tenure and judicial modesty. And part of the reason that you want to have more focus on text, history, and tradition is in lieu of an intermediate scrutiny rubric where any judge can come up with any result they possibly want.

 

So I just think it’s important to kind of demystify this a little bit, and the -- in a sense, the question is not, “Let’s get to the absolute best historical account of some incident,” but it’s really just -- it’s a little less daunting. It’s just, “Okay, there are these words. These words are our Constitution. They were ratified at a particular time.” If there’s a particular ambiguity, the history can help. If there is an unbroken tradition that goes back to the Framing and somebody’s telling you that, “That’s actually been unconstitutional since 1789, just nobody but me was smart enough to figure it out until now,” those are all things you should be skeptical about. But it's not that hard a project, and at the end of the day, it all gets back to the text anyways.

 

Hon. Elizabeth Wydra:  And I think, just to follow up on what Paul said -- maybe I’m just agreeing with him because I only have a JD and not a PhD in history as well, but I think it’s also just what we’re teaching about the Constitution. What I do in my daily work is very focused on the Reconstruction Amendments, but I think so many folks, when they think about the Constitution or when they think about originalism, they think of the Constitution as it existed in the 18th century. And even law students, I think, do not have a -- to the extent they even get an education on the 18th century founding of the United States Constitution, they have even less of an education on what many have called the Second Founding that happened after the Civil War. And that doesn’t have to be ideological.

 

Honestly, teaching the Constitution should be something that is cross-ideologically embraced. You can critique it, of course. You can embrace it. But I think, certainly, knowing it is powerful as a lawyer, as an American. And I think that it’s also very interesting to look at the way in which the amended Constitution really writes across the face of our national charter our story of national progress in addition to constitutional progress. And so, I think including that in more law school constitutional law classes would be incredibly useful.

 

And then, of course, to second Paul’s point about it isn’t this mysterious PhD practice -- but I think it’s also interesting to students to see the ways in which you apply what can seem like distant history to very current debates. And I know when I speak with students about how a Fourteenth Amendment originalist argument relates to reproductive justice, they find that very interesting and, similarly, with other issues. So I would love to see more Constitution education on that front in law schools, and it wasn’t really there when I was at Yale, so Yale, call me.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  All right. So I thought we might take some questions from the audience, if people have questions. I’ve now said, “Questions,” twice, and I’m going to say it again. It should be a question. That ends with a question mark. There are microphones. If you can make your way to the microphone, then we can hear you. And also, one more thing, tell us who you are.

 

Coach Weinhaus: Hi. Coach Weinhaus for Yeshiva University, or UCLA, and Abusive Discretion. The panel did an excellent job, exploring sources of methods of originalism, and Mr. Clement evoked judicial humility. And I’m curious how do we, as a society, identify judges who will be able to stay true to originalism and then, keep choosing, I guess, to limit their own power through other forms of discretion?

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Well, I think the confirmation process is designed to do that. The appointment and confirmation process is designed to do that. I think that when presidents are selecting judges, they are certainly entitled to ask about methodology, not about approaches to particular questions but certainly about what the judges’ political -- not political philosophy -- judicial philosophy, not political leanings, are. So I think that’s the process we have in place for dealing with that question.

 

Hon. Jason Miyares:  I would say this -- your question’s about -- where society’s impact on this. I think it’s going to be very, very difficult for, from a larger perspective of where society is -- I was reading a social scientist who’s talking about the decoupling of purpose in society, and he was not a conservative. He made this observation. I thought this was fascinating. He said, “We are the first society in human history, in all of human history, to reject the wisdom of those that have come before us.” It is a complete phenomenon in Western Europe and North America.

 

And if you go to Africa, if you go to Asia, if you go to Latin America, they have reverence for those that have come before and their wisdom. And it is only a recent phenomenon in the last several decades, the last 30 or 40 years, in which Western society has made the determination in a lot of, I would say, elite institutions that we’re going to simply reject those that have come before us because they have nothing to offer us. I think that permeates in almost everything that you see in a larger society, so I think that it is -- it’s -- our originalist judges, given what I’ve just described is having in academia -- I think it will get probably more difficult moving forward. Even though you have seen, I think, originalism become much more broadly accepted in a variety of legal circles, I also think it is also going to be more challenging.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  All right. It’s hard to see over here, but we have a question -- oh, it’s Roger Pilon.

 

Roger Pilon:  Yes. Yes, it is, from the Cato Institute. Thank you, Judge Larsen. My question is whether Judge Ho’s clerks may have been right when they asked whether even appellate judges should take their oath more seriously to the Constitution rather than to precedent. And I give you the important case of 1995, U.S. v. Lopez, where old Judge Harwood [sic], on the Fifth Circuit, entertained the argument from a young public defender in that case who had the effrontery to say that the Commerce Clause does not authorize Congress to enact the Gun-free School Zones Act. That power belongs to the state of Texas. But for the fact that Garwood said, “He’s right,” that case probably would not have made it to the Supreme Court. But in so doing, Harwood [sic], who, of course, was around in 1937, said, “Maybe the Court got it wrong on the Commerce Clause in 1937.”

 

Hon. James C. Ho:  So if the idea is that Judge Garwood’s opinion in -- at the Fifth Circuit level in Lopez was a defiance of Supreme Court precedent, I’ll be candid. I’m interested in that. I’m going to go look at that. I was not aware that it was literally defying Supreme Court precedent. That’s inconsistent with all the cases we talked about in terms of Agostini and Rodriguez. The Supreme Court has told us repeatedly not to anticipate.

 

Roger Pilon:  Well, professors had to rewrite their casebooks after the Supreme Court upheld Harwood [sic] --

 

Hon. James C. Ho:  Well, sure, in the sense that the Commerce Clause had not been used to impose limits on federal power until Lopez and Morrison and what have you. But that’s different from saying that Lopez is literally irreconcilable with cases like Wickard, and if I recall, the Supreme Court itself reconciled those opinions. So like I said, I’m always open-minded, always open to being proven wrong. If there is an argument that Lopez was correctly decided as an originalist matter but completely insubordinate, from a Supreme Court precedent matter, that’s news to me, and I’m -- certainly would be interested in learning more about that.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  All right. We’ll go over here to the left.

 

Hon. John Curry:  Okay. Thank you. Judge John Curry from Chicago. Judge Ho, you pointed out that sometimes there’re somewhat politically motivated textualism arguments, and they may be rooted in some community or some political object. Clearly, in the progressive field, let me sort of sketch out what we see. The academy will generate some sort of progressive perspective, and that may mean changing language, using language in a different way. Then, the general media picks it up, and then, the politicians pick it up, so we have a new meaning, which is really rooted in the left or progressive point of view. And then, that’s used as a fulcrum for arguing a case, saying, well, this is what the text in this law or the Constitution says, and it really means this.

 

And I think the example you gave that, well, that could be shown to be originating in a community as opposed to really what the text is about, the original public meaning of the text. Wouldn’t you think it would be a good idea when this occurs to -- for a judge or an advocate in a brief to actually point out, “This is the root. They’re arguing this is what this means, but this is where it rose from. It started out at the University of California, Berkeley, and then, The New York Times picked it up, and then, certain political operatives have generated this. And that’s not truly the meaning that was in this statute.” I wonder if you think that approach would be useful. I think it would be useful to see that read so you get out the fact that this is not really an accepted public meaning but a politically motivated meaning.

 

Hon. James C. Ho:  Yeah. I would just say I think I sort of noted earlier I think we all agree that we’re always interested in more information. I think your question, if I understand it, sort of reminds me of what Justice Thomas has often said, which is -- I forget him metaphor about adding cars to a train but then asking the question, “Are we even going in the right direction?” So certainly, let me just use this as an opportunity to kind of comment on what Elizabeth said earlier, which is — and I agree with it — which is originalism properly done isn’t conservative, isn’t liberal. It’s just lawyering. And if that’s the goal, I do take it -- I do take some solace -- we were talking about the selection process in the first question. We now have a consensus at least in terms of what people say, which is the judicial function is, in fact, an originalist function.

 

Swearing an oath to follow the Constitution means you will actually follow the written Constitution. At this point, I’m not aware of anybody who openly defies that. How good we are -- each and every one of us is actually doing that and doing it faithfully and following Justice Scalia’s principle that a bad judge was -- a judge who always likes the results of their decisions is a bad judge. I think that’s a pretty good principle to go by, but originalism properly done is steadfastly neither progressive, conservative, liberal, whatever terminology you want to use.

 

Hon. John Curry:  Thank you.

 

Hon. Paul D. Clement:  Yeah. And the only thing I’d add is just, again, getting back to, I guess, what is my theme, which is originalism isn’t something separate. It’s just one mode of trying to get the text right. And so, the principles that you’re talking about in terms of dealing with history aren’t really any different from the principles that I think you’re supposed to use when you’re interpreting statutory text, and you look at a bunch of dictionaries, and there’s one outlying dictionary, and you try to figure out, well, what’s going on with that one outlying dictionary. And Justice Scalia wrote an opinion for the Court in the MCI against AT&T case that’s had a second life as part of the major questions doctrine. But at the time, it was famous because it was the first time that Justice Scalia just ripped a new one into Webster’s Third.

 

But what generated that scorn for Webster’s Third is he was looking at a whole bunch of definitions of the word, “modify,” and then, he sees one that just is completely out of whack with the others. And then, he went back and realized that, okay, Webster’s, when it put out its third dictionary, decided to stop trying to figure out what words actually mean and just tried to essentially assemble widespread misuse of words and make that one of the definitions. And so, based on that, he threw out one definition of modify that didn’t fit in with any of the others.

 

And I think, when you’re looking at history, if at a certain point -- it seemed like everybody understood that a term meant a certain thing, historically, but then, all of a sudden, a revisionist school comes along -- you have to be cognizant of that but not because you have to be a great historian, just because you have to approach the job of interpreting the text the same basic way when it comes to historical sources as with respect to just the basic text and how you’d interpret a statute.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Okay. Sorry. The light is in my eyes, so I can’t really see you, but you can speak up and tell us who you are and what your question is.

 

Bryan Bishop (sp):  Yeah. Hi. Right. I’m here. I’m Bryan Bishop from the Stephen Hopkins Center for Civil Rights in Rhode Island. And I’m wondering if you view dueling traditions, which perhaps are underappreciated in comparing the Roe and Dobbs decisions because people kind of go to the substance, and the penumbra is first. I’m wondering if dueling traditions are more a distraction from the originalist project or perhaps an invitation to broader subscription to the project.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  I’m not sure I quite understand the question. Dueling --

 

Bryan Bishop:  What I’m suggesting is that if we’re debating traditions and to an extent if that comes in in looking at our legal traditions, whether that might actually interest people who think that originalism has a conservative or a right-leaning valence. They might realize that tradition doesn’t necessarily always cut that way, that maybe we should play on the originalist field and try and tease these out. Or is that rather simply an excuse to overthrow originalism?

 

Hon. Elizabeth Wydra:  So I think it’s a really interesting question, and certainly, part of what I do every day is try to convince my fellow progressives that we can and should play on the originalist field, and we can often win on that field as a substantive principled matter but also, frankly, as a strategic matter, given the makeup of the Supreme Court and many of our appellate courts across the country. One thing I think that -- you mentioned Roe and Dobbs and dueling traditions, and I think that that case and the Fourteenth Amendment cases generally are really interesting because the Fourteenth Amendment was — not to use tech bro slang — but was intended to be a constitutional disruptor. The folks who were writing the Fourteenth Amendment wrote it and thought it would be a constitutional disruptor to many different aspects of our constitutional order, that it -- they intended to turn on its head the relationship between state and federal citizenship. So instead of having state citizenship primary, they thought that this, especially with birthright citizenship provisions, etc., federal citizenship would become more important in many key ways. Similarly, disrupting a tradition of discrimination and opposition, the most obvious of which is with respect to the horrible institution of slavery, but they also considered other ways in which people had been suffering conditions of unfreedom.

 

The Thirteenth Amendment guaranteed freedom in the United States, and the Fourteenth Amendment, in many ways, answered the question, “What does it mean to be free?” And in doing so, the drafters of the Fourteenth Amendment intended to disrupt many discriminatory traditions. So when you’re going to engage in a text and history analysis of a Fourteenth Amendment provision, to me, it’s important to take into account that your traditions you look at might in way be different because the text was put into the Constitution in order to disrupt many of these traditions. So that’s something that I think is -- we talk about a lot, and I’d like to see more people talk about it. So thank you.

 

Prof. Bernadette Meyler:  Yeah. I just want to add that I think that that’s true actually even of the original Constitution. You can look at the Suspension Clause and wonder how much of it is about enshrining what came before and how about deviating from that. But I think the other point I would make is that it’s not, say, just going to Roe and Dobbs but even going back to what Judge Larsen mentioned before, the Crawford case. I think a lot of the Sixth Amendment originalism decisions have been embraced by progressives as well as some conservatives. And so, there are plenty of ways to, I think, use originalism in different political valences or for different political ends as well.

 

Hon. Britt Grant:  If you look at, for instance, the Heller decision, both opinions in that case were deeply originalist, and one, of course, got more votes than the other. But I think that’s a really good example of “both sides of a question” digging into the original sources and trying to use those to discern the meaning.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  All right. We’ll take a question over here on my left.

 

Art Macomber:  Thank you. Art Macomber, Coeur d’Alene, Idaho. My question is really for the judges, and I’m wondering about the analytical framework. I think Mr. Clement said, okay, so you state with the text, and then, you have history and tradition. So the final two are kind of a swamp, and I see that, for the Founders, they were looking backwards. And I think if you don’t start with Magna Carta and move forward, you don’t really get an understanding of how -- we look backwards and see the Constitution. They were setting it up and looking forwards, given what happened in the past.

 

And my question is this I know you have subject-matter considerations, the First Amendment obviously different than the Third Amendment. Right? History and tradition on the Third Amendment is pretty well capped. But how do you, as a judge, approach this issue? What is the analytical framework for the history and tradition swamp that you engage in — step one, step two, step three? And if you could talk a little bit about that, it would be very helpful. Thank you.

 

Hon. Britt Grant:  I think it’s interesting, again, as a circuit judge, certainly, we have occasions to look at history and tradition, but again, I think, less so than the Supreme Court. So I think, for me, sometimes it comes up in what we might think of as smaller issues. I mentioned that a little bit before, issues that are not on the front pages of the newspaper. And I think that’s where you can look back and see earlier statutes. How did -- maybe even if you’re looking at habeas corpus, right, Magna Carta, and how did it go from there? What was the original understanding of habeas corpus at the Founding? How did that impact its development as we went through the 19th and 20th centuries?

 

Even those questions, I think, can sometimes inform, say, an EDPA issue that we’re dealing with today. And so, I think, that’s not an issue where you’ll necessarily have a brief that starts with Magna Carta, but I think, once you start to dig into the text and look at things that happen with statutes and try to understand what framework, even 20 and 30 years ago, people were working within. I think that you try to look at those questions at every step of the line. So to me, originalism doesn’t start and stop around the Founding era. It’s a developing process. When you look at the developing understandings as we have statutes that have gone through their own processes and their own development, I think it really help you understand, as a judge, what that text means when you look at the text that came before it and the practices that came before it.

 

Hon. James C. Ho:  I might just lightly try to merge the premise of your question with what Elizabeth said earlier. What I said earlier was I think there was at least some sense that one way to approach this is text. That’s what we’re doing. But it can be, can be, informed by history and tradition. But as Elizabeth points out, there are times when the drafters, whether it’s a constitutional amendment or a statute or what have you, there are times when the text is pathbreaking, right, when the whole point of a text is to go in a very different direction.

 

Now, obviously, you need to figure out when those situations exist and when they don’t, and we have certain kinds of interpretation. The one against lightly assuming variations of common law would be one example where we don’t assume a pathbreaking moment, but when the text does break a path, suggest a complete departure from the past, then, history, tradition obviously, presumably, could play a different role in that situation. So it’s just a matter of figuring out which situation you’re presented with.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  All right.

 

Will Trachman:  Hi. Will Trachman from Mountain States Legal Foundation.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Yeah.

 

Will Trachman:  We don’t write on a clean slate very much, not all of us are practicing before the Supreme Court. Is there an opinion on whether litigators can use originalism when there’s already a balancing test or a tier of scrutiny at play? So to say, well, this is not a compelling interest that would have been compelling to the Framers or in the original public meaning, or this wouldn’t have been narrowly tailored to the Framers. And separately, we have a case right now, representing a student who was prohibited from wearing the Gadsden flag as a patch on his backpack, and we’re arguing under the Tinker standard. So could we say, “Well, obviously, it wouldn’t have been a substantial disruption in the 1860s to wear a Gadsden flag on your backpack?” How does originalism interact with current balancing standards?

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Yeah. That’s a great question. First of all, I don’t think you’re going to get any of the judges on this panel to opine on your case. So we’re not going to do that. But I think, as a general matter -- look, if the Supreme Court has said, “Here’s a balancing test, and you have to apply the balancing test,” the judges, for the most part, are going to apply the balancing test. And if there are cases in the circuit or coming from the Supreme Court that cash out what that balancing test looks like, I think the judges are going to be inclined to say, “Well, this is how we’ve applied this before. The cases tell us that this factor on this factor. We look at these things, and your case looks exactly like that one or looks different than that one.” I think that’s what most judges are going to do as a first line.

 

That being said, if you can make a compelling case either that there’s an alternative to the balancing test that we ought to be taking very seriously, I don’t think any of us are going to not apply the balancing test we were told to apply. But it might provoke that concurrence that says, “Hey, you should replace that with something else.” And also, I think it’s an interesting proposition to say, “We should think about how this would have balanced out at the Founding.” If you’ve got that case that you can make, I think I share Judge Ho’s perspective. Bring us the information, and we’ll see how it cashes out. Again, I don’t know about your particular case so not commenting.

 

Hon. James C. Ho:  Yeah. Look, if you think you have an originalist argument, I would make it. Absolutely. I’m reminded of what Justice Scalia often said. Justice Scalia famously was pretty categorical, if not actually categorical, about legislative history, and yet, he would repeatedly tell lawyer audiences, “If you have a legislative history argument, you absolutely should make it.” He may not take it. He may not agree with it. But some of his colleagues might. Some of the judges on other courts might.

 

And so, I would view things from a practitioner’s standpoint in that lens. If you have -- presumably, you think you have precedent on your side. You should cite the precedent. But I would always be prepared -- if nothing else, at oral argument, we also train, whether it’s me or me mooting other people in my office, have a backup argument. Have multiple arguments. You should win based on a precedent. You should win based on originalist analysis. You should win based on, frankly, policy arguments because some judges may pay attention to that.

 

Just frankly, to me — and this maybe goes back to the General’s comment about the state of legal education — is -- it just strikes me as woefully incompetent, educational malpractice, for law schools not to teach every tool in the tool book, if, in fact, your avowed object is to train legal professionals.  The problem—I think General is absolute right—is law schools aren’t doing that anymore, at least not -- maybe not -- categorical, many law schools -- certain law schools may be focused more on indoctrinating and sort of just wanting to inflict a certain sense of political change rather than doing what I thought they were doing, which is training future lawyers. And so, future -- lawyers of all kinds, including future lawyers, need to have every tool in the toolbox so that you can deploy for your clients. I would have thought that that would be uncontroversial, but apparently, that’s the controversy of the day.

 

Hon. Britt Grant:  I’ll say I think you should absolutely make originalist arguments, if you have them. And not only might it inspire concurrence, but it could inspire an “and also” in a majority opinion. There’s important scholarship from, say, Professor McConnell on how Brown v. Board wasn’t written as an originalist decision, but it certainly is very consistent with the original meaning. And so, I think all judges want to make their opinions as persuasive and rock solid as possible. And if there’re originalist arguments that point in the same direction, especially as whatever the result is of the balancing test that we’ve been instructed to use, then I think a lot of judges would be really excited to include those arguments in their opinions to fully bolster the decision.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Professor Meyler.

 

Prof. Bernadette Meyler:  Yeah. I think this is a very interesting question because a lot of recent Supreme Court cases have kind of called into question some of the tiers of scrutiny or other tests that have traditionally been applied since, say, the 1940s. And so, I think, one strategy might be to say, “Well, in Bruen, there seems to be a rejection of those kinds of tests, so maybe there’s some uncertainty about whether the Supreme Court is actually endorsing tests along these lines in other cases.” But then, also, I think there’s a counterargument about to -- maybe to the Supreme Court about rejecting these kinds of tests because I think, as Judge Ho had mentioned, there may be some evidence of the Founding about some forms of balancing. Right? If you think about Justice Marshall using a question about is it necessary or absolutely necessary -- what is the level of review.

 

And then, secondly, there is a question about how much originalism really also imports a particular method of judging. Does it include judicial practices from the Founding or not? And then, I think, third, there’s also a practical question about implementing doctrine in the lower courts, whether tests of -- balancing tests or other things are just more feasible for lower courts to implement as a routine matter. So I think there are some interesting arguments on either side.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  All right. Let’s move here to the -- my left.

 

Violet Grayson:  To what degree -- I’m Violet Grayson. I’m a practicing lawyer. And to what degree do you experience tension between originalism and textualism?

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  I’m sorry. There was just noise in the hallway. I couldn’t quite hear it.

 

Violet Grayson:  I said, “To what degree do you experience tension between originalism and textualism?”

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Oh.

 

Hon. James C. Ho:  I’ll just take a quick stab.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Yeah. Go ahead.

 

Hon. James C. Ho:  I’ve never seen any tension between the two concepts. Obviously, they’re two different words that are used. Typically, textualism is associated with statutes. Originalism is associated with the Constitution. But I don’t see them in tension. The way I have always thought about it, and this could be completely wrong, but just how I think about it is we talk textualism when it comes to statutes because statutes typically -- just read the text, and you can kind of figure out there are more words. There’s more detail. And so, you can kind of begin and end with text.

 

Whereas, constitutions, and certainly the federal Constitution, there are times when you have few words, and you need more to decide a particular dispute that’s in front of you. And so, you look behind the text to figure out, well, what do we mean. What did the Founders mean when they drafted these terms? But to me, it’s the same conversation we’ve been having earlier. We’re looking at text. If you need more than the text, you might need to be informed by things behind the text: history, tradition, dictionaries, what have you. But I think it’s all the same project. At least, that’s how I’ve always conceived of it.

 

Hon. Jason Miyares:  Yeah. I would -- kind of a different perspective. Prior to my service as Attorney General, I served in the General Assembly in the Courts of Justice Committee, and we used to always say, “We don’t vote on ideas. We vote on bills.” And it was all -- exactly to Judge Ho’s point, looking at how we were going to be changing the code, and the one thing we always stressed was there was going to be a judge, whether they’re in Fairfax or Galax, that is going to be trying to interpret how we have amended and changed the code of Virginia. And they are likely not going to have the benefit of watching what the meaning or the intent or the testimony of the patron of the legislation that’s seeking to change whatever section it is, 18.2, whatever section of the Virginia code. So I thought it was -- we always had the attitude that it was so critically important to make sure the text, the actual language -- and we argued over single dot and comma, as lawyers often do, precisely because we had the idea that a judge is going to have to read the plain language, and it needs to be crystal clear. And oftentimes, bad bills make bad law and then bad precedent.

 

Hon. Elizabeth Wydra:  And I would just add I think that’s a really interesting question because the idea with textualism is that you’re sticking to the text. Now, of course, sometimes, the text is -- needs greater context, or you can understand it better if you look to these other sources. And I normally think that that’s a great idea. One of the places where I do feel like there’s tension, however, sometimes, is when, through the originalist project, you’re using history or tradition to subvert the text or to make the words mean something perhaps other than you might think they mean based on the plain text of the constitutional provision, for example. And so, when that happens, I’m not saying it’s always wrong, but it certainly makes me pay a little bit more attention to what is actually happening in that instance. I think of this particularly with respect to the Fourteenth Amendment.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  All right.

 

Aaron Watt:  Good morning. Thank you to all the panelists for being here. My name’s Aaron Watt. I’m a 3L at Scalia Law School. I have a question about the originalist project. Someone else asked about sort of the order of operations, about starting with text. And I think back on my federal courts class about sovereign immunity. I think it’s a good example of something where it seems like we start from history and tradition, and we say we really didn’t mean to derogate from that.

 

I wonder if there are other places where it’s appropriate to start from the opposite direction as well. Are there rights that were so taken for granted up through English common law into the United States that it would be more appropriate to look to see what the foundational rights and to see if the law has derogated that? What are your thoughts?

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Is that a question about common good constitutionalism?

 

Aaron Watt:  I don’t think it is. Actually, I don’t support that perspective. But just from an originalist perspective, if what the people thought they were doing was incorporating rights, privileges, or immunities or whatever it was that they had taken for granted that existed, if that’s what the original Founders thought they were doing, is it appropriate to start from that place when evaluating just particular rights at least?

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  So maybe that’s a question about the Ninth Amendment. Maybe I’m not understanding the question. If we could take a particular constitutional provision, so the Confrontation Clause or the right to jury, as an example, so if we took the right to jury, how does that -- how does your question cash out there? Or are you asking, “Are there rights that the Founding generation would have understood to be a part of the set of natural rights,” for example, that they wanted -- that when they talked about the other rights retained by the people, that’s what they meant to enshrine? Those seem like two different questions, and I’m not quite sure which question you’re asking.

 

Aaron Watt:  Sure. And it’s hard for me to come up with a starting point in the text because, of course, then, I would have started from the text. This is part of why I wanted to --

 

[CROSSTALK]

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  And you didn’t -- the whole premise of your question is not to start with the text. Yeah.

 

Aaron Watt:  And it’s at least why I bring up sovereign immunity as an example. And so, I think about things like parental rights. Is that something that would have been taken for granted as a right? Where does that right originate from if it doesn’t originate from the text? And so, maybe my question isn’t clear enough quite to respond to, but I wanted to give you what I’ve got on it anyway.

 

Hon. James C. Ho:  I’m going to go with the fact that you’ve sort of hit sovereignty immunity twice, and I’m going to take that to be the premise of your question. And I just lightly disagree or at least offer a different take on your premise, which is to the extent you’re saying — and this is going to get nerdy really quickly — to the extent that your point is the Eleventh Amendment obviously talks about sovereign immunity in some ways but not in the broader way that we have in various settings -- diversity, which is a federal question, etc., etc. I don’t see that as anti-textual. I see that as the Eleventh Amendment reflecting drafters thinking that the Supreme Court got cases wrong. I think it’s Chisholm -- or I forget this area, now. It’s been a while since Fed Courts for me.

 

But it’s really not the text that’s doing the work, at least the text of the Eleventh Amendment. It’s the text of Article III, and the drafters, rightly or wrongly, thought, “You know what? Supreme Court, you got it wrong, so we’re going to lightly -- we’re going to overturn your case through the text of the Eleventh Amendment, but obviously, we’re restoring a broader conception of state sovereign immunity that we thought was already in Article III or perhaps the Tenth Amendment.” I think multiple Supreme Court justices have said it’s wrong to use the term, “Eleventh Amendment immunity,” other than in those cases where it’s actually about the Eleventh Amendment. It’s state sovereign immunity that preexists the Constitution and wasn’t overturned by Article III. So I might disagree with your premise and, therefore, stick with the text.

 

Hon. Elizabeth Wydra:  I think it’s hard to think of a time when you wouldn’t at least start with the text. Privileges or immunities, for example, in the Fourteenth Amendment, is a broad term, but if you look at the original public meaning, there was a very clear understanding -- at least, the general concepts that were included. Now, whether it’s the Corfield v. Coryell list of rights, whether it was the first ten amendments plus -- you look at the debates, and you can see that the -- you mentioned parental rights -- that the right to form a family was included in those ideas of privileges or immunities. So I think it would always be right to start with the text because there’s a reason why they used privileges or immunities as opposed to some other term of relating to rights or liberties.

 

Prof. Bernadette Meyler:  I think it’s an interesting question because even if you look at Article III, there isn’t an explicit provision for state sovereign immunity in Article III. Right? So you’re implying something into the text, and I think that I would go back to Judge Larsen’s comment about the Ninth Amendment, or even the Tenth Amendment, that there are these provisions of the Constitution that are fairly broadly phrased and that do imply invocation of some forms of structure or rights that were preceding the Constitution. And so, figuring out which provisions are against that backdrop and which aren’t is one of the, I think, tasks of interpretation, even if you’re starting with the text.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  All right. We have time for just a couple more questions, so let’s take one over here on the left.

 

Clarke Forsythe:  Clarke Forsythe, Americans United for Life. If the focus of originalism is the ratified text, which, if any, outside voices are relevant to the ratified text?

 

Hon. Britt Grant:  I think it depends on what you’re using them for. I’ll be interested to hear from our scholars to my left, but I think voices are not -- I don’t think that any voices are appropriately used to override the text. But to the extent that we can use different voices to better understand the text, then I think a lot of the comments from, really, all the panelists today have indicated that we can take those into account. I think Paul Clement had a lot of arguments about whether we should allow private voices to override public understandings, and I think that those questions are interesting. But I think, as long as we’re using them for the right reasons and placing them in the proper context, I think you can certainly consider and then put within the overall framework -- we’re happy to hear, I think, about a lot of voices and then give them whatever meaning they have, in terms of helping us understand the text, but not override the text.

 

Prof. Bernadette Meyler:  Yeah. I would say that, in my view, looking at the participants and debates, right, so a lot of these kinds of rights or provisions were subject of different debates or might have been subject to different laws in different colonies. So looking at the structure of those debates, I think, is particularly informative in understanding what the text means.

 

Hon. Elizabeth Wydra:  Yeah. When you’re looking at an original public meaning analysis, which is the dominant form of originalist analysis after you look at the text, then, of course, you are going to include voices other than just those who were the ratifiers because they are included in the public. But yes, obviously, it implies some level of publicity. So Paul’s private diary, I don’t think, would count unless excerpts of that diary were published à la Federalist Papers and distributed to the public. But we look at newspapers. We look at convention debates. And certainly, when I think about my particular area of expertise in the Reconstruction Amendments, there were a lot of these public conventions and debates. And so, there is really a rich history to be looked at there. And I think that as we get even more scholarship and have more sources, public sources, then that will be a really interesting rich debate.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Okay. We are very close to being out of time, but there are only two speakers at the mic, and I just -- I have such a benevolent heart. So I can’t just cut one of you off, so it’s the lightning round, quick question, and we’ll give you each a quick answer. And then, we’ll adjourn.

 

Gabrielle:  Well, thank you. I really appreciate the love and benevolence. My name is Gabrielle. I’m a third-year law student from University of Miami. And all I wanted to ask touches upon what Miyares has said about the hatred of originalism in law school, and he’s absolutely right. And I ask this question because I think it extends from this very formulaic argument that they produce that because the Founders were wrong — at least in so far as who was afforded certain substantive rights — or that history was wrong for a period of time, that they must be wrong about the actual interpretation or meaning or scope of the actual substantive rights themselves, so we should just do away with anything they thought of entirely.

 

And of course, that ignores the beautiful design of our Founding document that, when we do extend rights to all human beings, we don’t have to do away with the whole document, and we have the most successful governance experiment of all time. So my question is how do we respond to this vitriol from the other side? Just because we have historical mistakes, it doesn’t mean that we should dispose of this.

 

Hon. Jason Miyares:  Well, this is what I would say. This idea that the greatest critique of originalism is we got to ignore the dead hand of the past, and as I had one intern tell me that the general sentiment from some of their law professors is why would we want to study dead white men? And I think it takes away the richness of the basic of the Founding where if you look at James Madison, he was obsessed with two things: both anarchy and monarchy. And so, how do we frame a government in such a way that can respect both the rights of the individual and the face and the passions of the mob but also make sure that part -- that power is devolved. And I think the other thing it takes away, which I think law students often are not taught, is just how obsessed Madison was going to the Constitution Convention on why democracy fails. He spent so much time looking at both Ancient Greece and Ancient Rome on what caused them to fall, not just forming the government. How do we create a system of governing that absolutely can self-perpetuate itself? And I thought that is greatly missing.

 

And it is the first written constitution in all of human history that actually limits what government can do and empowers the individual. It’s never happened in all of recorded history. And the other thing that makes me is a sense that we got to ignore a dead white man, and it’s not quite applicable, but my -- people ask me, “What kind of name is Miyares?” I say, “Well, it’s southern.” My family fled Cuba, and my uncle, Angel Miyares, when he was arrested in Cuba and he went through the humiliation of a mock execution, one of the things that he appealed to was, “You have no right to do this because I have certain unalienable rights of life and liberty.” In other words, he was appealing towards something that was a university principle laid, of course, by our Founders. Obviously, the Declaration of Independence is kind of the birth certificate later on for the Bills of Rights. So I think it is a passionate need to expose the fact that these university principles that have been appealed to to man’s better nature in every gulag, whether they’re in North Korea or Cuba or in Russia, and the universality of it that applies to all races and creeds.

 

And the point that I make is -- and when Dr. King made his speech at the Lincoln Memorial, he didn’t appeal to Rousseau. Right? He said he was there to collect a promissory note made to every single American — past, present, and future — of life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness. He didn’t appeal to Confucius. He didn’t appeal to Rousseau. And if you look at simply -- when Dr. King taught at Morehouse College, do you know what he taught? Philosophy. Do you know what he assigned to his students? The greatest thinkers of Western Civilization. Look at the curriculum that Dr. King picked out and taught in his philosophy class at Morehouse College, and I think you should point to that, that there is a universal principle here that is oftentimes ignored and to tragic consequences on our college campuses, tragic consequences.

 

Gabrielle:  Thank you.

 

[Applause]

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Okay. So I hope you have a good one to take us out on.

 

Connor:  To quickly piggyback off of that question as well, my name’s Connor. I’m the President of the Student Chapter at William and Mary Law. What can students and young attorneys do to help circumvent that censorship on college campuses and in hiring practices? Many of us feel as if we have to choose between self-censorship and professional and even social suicide. So what can we do to bring in the next generation of originalist thinkers because I think a lot of us believe that we’re being -- we’re losing that platform. We exist, but the platform itself is shrinking and disappearing.

 

Hon. Jason Miyares:  I would just say real quick. Alumni should withhold their donations to their alma mater until they commit to ideological diversity, number one. [Applause] And I think -- and I do think that their -- and I’m a proud alumni of that same Federalist Society chapter at William and Mary. C.S. Lewis has a great line where he says, “The beginning of friendship is when you turn to somebody and say, ‘Oh, you too?’ I thought I was the only one.” Right? So I think there is both a power of the organizations like Federalist Society and others for people that have this originalist worldview to realize they’re not alone. And I think that’s critically important as well is to build up, continuing these different organizations that can foster and encourage the next generation.

 

Hon. Britt Grant:  I’ll say this: have debates in The Federalist Society. That’s, I think, one of the most fundamental principles of The Federalist Society is that there are important issues. Let’s hear both sides of them. If you’re not getting the originalist side at -- from the academics at your law school, have a debate. Invite people in. Let students hear. And I think more students will be persuaded, and they can feel like they can sneak in if they think the right side is also being represented. And maybe they’ll hear a different view and start to think about it more carefully.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Okay. We are a little bit overtime, but I have to read you some things that I was told I must read. So I’m going to do it, and then, you can thank our terrific panel. So if you are pursuing CLE, we’d like to remind you to make sure you sign in and sign out once per day. If you did not sign in ahead of this panel, please do so now via the QR code in the program and also available at registration. Additionally, we would like to remind you of the Remnant Trust’s Rare Documents Exhibit located on the second floor in the South Carolina Room. You can access the second floor using the elevators located next to check-in. If you are ever need -- in need of coffee or a power strip to charge your phone or your laptop or your iPad, I suppose, throughout the day, these are located at the Mezzanine Level, accessible by the front elevators. There are no panels directly following this one, so we’d like to announce that lunch will be served shortly in the main hallway. Thank you very much. We are adjourned.

 

9:15 a.m. - 11:15 a.m.
Showcase Panel I: Roundtable: Originalism on the Ground

2023 National Lawyers Convention

Topics: Constitution • Jurisprudence • Philosophy
Grand Ballroom
The Mayflower Hotel
1127 Connecticut Avenue NW
Washington, DC 20006

Share

Event Video

Listen & Download

Description

Trying to sort out what originalism means in practice requires integrating insights from all levels of the legal system, from academicians (both legal and historical), lawyers (from private practice, public interest, business, and government), and the bench (both trial and appellate and both state and federal). In this Roundtable, participants representing many of those elements of the legal culture offer insights on the current state of originalism in legal practice. Is there an identifiable "legal culture" to which originalism can be applied? If so, what should lawyers be doing that they are not doing? What should academics be doing that they are not doing? What should judges be doing that they are not doing?

Featuring

  • Hon. Paul D. Clement, Partner, Clement & Murphy, PLLC
  • Hon. Britt Grant, United States Court of Appeals, Eleventh Circuit
  • Hon. James C. Ho, United States Court of Appeals, Fifth Circuit
  • Prof. Bernadette Meyler, Carl and Sheila Spaeth Professor of Law, Stanford Law School
  • Hon. Jason Miyares, Attorney General, Commonwealth of Virginia
  • Hon. Elizabeth Wydra, President, Constitutional Accountability Center
  • Moderator: Hon. Joan Larsen, United States Court of Appeals, Sixth Circuit

Overflow: Chinese Room

Speakers

Event Transcript

Hon. Dean A. Reuter:  Welcome in, everyone. If people could find a seat, please. I know we have lots of people in the hallway, but we’re going to go ahead and get started, if we could.

 

Welcome and thank you all for being here. Thank you so much. I am Dean Reuter, Senior Vice President and General Counsel of The Federalist Society. It is my pleasure to welcome you to our proceedings at this year’s convention. I want to also welcome everyone watching on the live stream or on video, as the case be. I also want to thank, in addition to you here in the room, thank our donors for their support, without whom, I suppose, we’d be hosting this meeting in a field somewhere. So thanks to those donors, large and small.

 

And thanks in advance — I never get to do this with a lot of people in the room — but thanks in advance to our staff, the staff of The Federalist Society, and it’s really not thanks in advance. They’ve been working on this for months, so thank you to them for their efforts. [Applause] A couple of logistical items. If you’re seeking CLE credit, you need to use the QR code to sign in at this point in time, and then, sign out with the same QR code. Sign in every morning, and sign out every evening. Otherwise, you’ll create some problems for yourselves.

 

Also, we have, again, this year, the folks from the Remnant Trust and their collection of rare documents. I don’t know if folks were able to visit the exhibit last year, but it really, really is splendid, and I recommend you take a moment. There are some breaks in the schedule. It’s on the second floor in the South Carolina Room. And if you were there last year, you were probably awed.

 

There is a collection of new and additional documents this year. I shouldn’t say “new” documents. They’re new “old” documents. And really, where else can you go and actually hold a 1350 copy of Magna Carta. Upstairs on the second floor is where you can do that. And you have -- you get to hold, interact with these documents, take pictures with them, tweet about it. So that’s the business items.

 

As to the introduction, a wise man once told me that a good introduction is both brief and clever, so I will at least try to be brief. Our theme this year is “Originalism on the Ground,” and that is the focus of our first Showcase Panel. This, I think, is the largest roundtable panel discussion we’ve ever had. There are more -- you could land a plane on this table probably. The fact is there are more jurists now that are more receptive than ever to originalism and textualism.

 

Now, that might give some of us in the audience in the room a sense of satisfaction or even a sense of accomplishment, a sense of even finality, well done. We’re done. But to paraphrase Churchill, this does not mark the end of any originalism project, not even the beginning of the end of the original project. Rather, we’ve come, perhaps, to the end of the beginning of the original -- originalism project. This project really is just taking off. So this is not the time to pause or suspend discussion and explication of originalism, our research and scholarship on originalism. We need to carry forth. This is the time to move forward and to carry on, and so, we shall.

 

And that, this talk about originalism, does remind me of a brief story. And it relates to the meaning of words, indeed the very meaning of originalism. Some very good friends of mine had two sons, Charlie and Ryan, both toddlers at the time of this story. Now, Charlie was the younger of the two, and he had a medical condition that required daily injections. So it was a daily struggle for the parents who had to administer these shots, sometimes in the arms, sometimes in the thigh. And anyone here with children or anybody here who was a child, you know that there’s nothing enjoyed quite so much by a toddler as an injection by needle.

 

Well, one day, Charlie was particularly resistant to his injection. And the regular compromises and bribes weren’t working, so his mother got creative and offered Charlie a new compromise. She said, “Charlie, you can have your shot anywhere you want it.” And Charlie thought just briefly and said, “I want my shot in Ryan.” [Laughter] So his mother had said he could have his shot anywhere he wanted. She meant, of course, his arm or his thigh. That’s the context.

 

But she had said, “Anywhere.” And if you look up the word, “anywhere,” in the dictionary, you’ll find out that Charlie was probably within his rights to answer as he did. But of course, originalism is something more than just original public meaning of a single word or even a single phrase. It’s more nuanced and more complicated than that. And those nuances and complications will be central to our Showcase Panel discussions at this convention, beginning with this first Showcase Panel.

 

For this roundtable, we’ve assembled experts from different parts of the law and public policy world to give various perspectives on utility and state of originalism. We’ve included practicing lawyers, judges, academics, public interest folks. Because I’ve asked our moderators throughout the convention to be brief in their introduction of panelists, I will also be brief in introducing our moderator, almost abrupt, in fact. Your program lists Judge Kevin Newsom as our moderator, but he’s encountered an emergency. He’s just fine, but he can’t be with us today. So Judge Joan Larsen is subbing in as a participating moderator for Judge Newsom, and I owe her a special thanks for that.

 

Judge Larsen, known to many of you, I expect, sits on the U.S. Court of Appeals on the Sixth Circuit. And before taking the bench, she was a long-time member of the University of Michigan Law School faculty. So for our discussions today, she’ll bring at least two important perspectives. I have to let you know. I can’t let this go without mentioning that she graduated first in her class at Northwestern University Law School, so she and I have in common the fact that we both spent some time at Northwestern Law School. [Laughter] I don’t think they had class ranks when I was there. I wasn’t informed about that. [Laughter] But with that, I will call the panel and Judge Larsen forward, please.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Welcome, everybody, to the first panel of the 2023 National Lawyers Convention. I am really excited to be here and to help moderate this discussion with a fantastic lineup of speakers. This year’s convention is focused on originalism. And when I look at the topics that will be debated over the next few days, I know it’s going to be a terrific conversation. For example, there are panels focusing on how originalism touches on particular topics, like federalism, religious liberty, and criminal law.

 

But today, we’re going to kick off our discussion with a broader lens. We’re talking about originalism on the ground, meaning how do we do originalism? And I think this topic has both normative and descriptive dimensions. So how is originalism actually being done in the real world, and also, how should it be done? And it’s also both theoretical and practical. How would we do originalism in an ideal world, and how can we do it in the world we actually inhabit with limited resources and constraints on our time?

 

And finally, we should ask how can we, as attorneys, academics, and judges, do a better job at facilitating the use of this important tool? So to bring you this topic, I have the pleasure of introducing just an all-star lineup of judges, lawyers, and academics, representing both the federal and state perspectives on this topic. Their full bios are in your program. So I’ll be brief, and I’m going to introduce our panelists in alphabetical order; although, that’s not the order in which they will appear.

 

So first, at the far end of the table, we have Paul Clement. [Applause] Paul is no stranger to The Federalist Society, as you can tell from the round of spontaneous applause. Paul served as the 43rd Solicitor General of the United States and has argued more than 100 cases before the U.S. Supreme Court. Paul is obviously a formidable litigator, but he also has an academic pursuit. And he’s so interested in that academic pursuit that he’s actually going to leave us early to go teach his class at Georgetown Law Center, so when he leaves us early, please know it’s not something that one of us said. [Laughter]

 

Next, we have the Honorable Britt Grant of the U.S. Court of Appeals for the Eleventh Circuit. Judge Grant brings not only the perspective of the Federal Court of Appeals but can also bring us a view from the states. Before her appointment to the Federal Court, Judge Grant was Justice Grant of the Supreme Court of Georgia, and before that, she was General Grant but not that one. She was Georgia’s Solicitor General.

 

The Honorable Jim Ho sits here to my left. Judge Ho serves on the U.S. Court of Appeals for the Fifth Circuit. Before taking the bench, he was a partner and co-chair of the Appellate and Constitutional Law practice group of Gibson, Dunn & Crutcher. Judge Ho, too, can share some views from the states, having served three years as the Solicitor General of Texas. And back when Judge Ho was just a baby lawyer, I had the pleasure to work with him in the Justice Department.

 

Our next speaker brings a view from the academy. Professor Bernadette Meyler is the Carla and the -- Carl and Sheila Spaeth Professor of Law at Stanford Law School. And I just butchered that, and having come from the academy, I know that it is very important to say the names of the endowed chairs correctly, so I’m going to say it again: the Carl and Sheila Spaeth Professor of Law at Stanford Law School. Professor Meyler is a scholar of British and American constitutional law and of law and the humanities. Her current book project will be of great interest to those in the audience, entitled, Common Law Originalism. It looks at various eighteenth-century common law meanings of various constitutional terms and phrases and, I take it, expresses some skepticism over our ability to lay hands on a single determinate meaning for much of the Constitution.

 

Next, we have a voice from the states. We have with us the Honorable Jason Miyares, Attorney General of the Commonwealth of Virginia. General Miyares was elected Attorney General in 2021 and, from 2015 to 2021, served in the Virginia House of Delegates. He also brings the perspective of a local county prosecutor, having started off in the Assistant Commonwealth Attorney for the City of Virginia Beach.

 

Finally, we have Elizabeth Wydra. She is the President of the Constitutional Accountability Center. In that role, she is a frequent litigator and a contributor to our national conversation on the Constitution. She joined CAC from private practice at Quinn Emanuel in San Francisco, and she, too, spent some time as a teacher, a supervising attorney, and teaching fellow at the appellate litigation clinic at Georgetown Law School.

 

So with that terrific lineup and this large panel, we have decided to dispense with the traditional format of opening statements and get right to some questions. So I will pose some questions for our panelists. Hopefully, somebody will take the lead in answering them, but others should feel free to jump into the conversation. And if time permits, we will open the questions, of course, for the audience at the end.

 

So I thought we might start with some methodological questions. And for the most part, when people talk about originalism today, we’re talking about the search for the original public meaning of the Constitution. That contrasts with an earlier vision of originalism, which focused more on a search for the intent of the Framers. But if we’re looking for original public meaning, I think we should ask the question, “What does that actually mean? Whose meaning are we seeking, and how broad is that lens?” And I think Elizabeth Wydra might have some perspectives on that topic.

 

Hon. Elizabeth Wydra:  Yeah.  Thank you so much. Thank you so much, Judge Larsen. And thank you so much, everyone here, for joining us this morning, and thank you for Dean inviting me to be here to talk about this really interesting subject with such an esteemed panel. I think that that question is still something that is being debated and disputed and explored. I come from an organization that focuses on originalism, and while we are nonpartisan, we are avowedly progressive. So when I take a look at whose voices perhaps should be included in the search for original public meaning, my lens seems to be broader than, for example, the lens that was included in Justice Alito’s Dobbs opinion or Justice Thomas’s Bruen decision.

 

And I think that it’s a challenge to us litigators to make sure that we are presenting a broad variety of voices whose opinions about the original public meaning matter. It’s a challenge to the academy, for sure, to discover, uncover the thoughts and debates of groups that have not always been the focus of historical analysis. There’s been some really fantastic recent work about the way that Native Americans understood the original public meaning of various constitutional provisions.

 

There is work out there already about how when the Reconstruction Amendments — Thirteenth, Fourteenth, and Fifteenth Amendments — were being ratified, the very rigorous debates that were going on in the African American community. And I think far too often the decisions that we see reflect the views on original public meaning of the, perhaps, most powerful group of people at the time. We are, understandably, looking back 100 years, so if you think whose voices are going to be recorded more frequently, those are probably the easiest to access. But it doesn’t mean we shouldn’t try harder because if you think about who was going to be deeply impacted, for example, by the Fourteenth Amendment, the people who had been freed after the Fourteenth Amendment from -- after the Thirteenth Amendment from enslavement certainly had a very substantial stake in what the Fourteenth Amendment meant: what kind of freedom that they had been granted in the Thirteenth Amendment, what that would mean, what the contours of that freedom would mean.

 

So to me, when I’m looking at original public meaning, looking at black newspapers from the time, looking at the way that the -- there were conventions of black activists and freed African Americans. Their debates and their views on the original public meaning certainly should be included in that lens. And, I think, as we have scholars doing more of this work, doing more of this excavation, then I think that conversation will only become richer and probably more reflective and representative of the true original public meaning of all of the folks whose views and voices should count.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Yeah. Sure. Professor Meyler.

 

Prof. Bernadette Meyler:  Yeah. I would just love to add a bit to what Elizabeth was saying, which I think is part of -- looking at the different voices also is about what kinds of governmental materials are examined in an originalist investigation. So if a court is looking primarily at, say, state statutes, then the court might be excluding a number of voices that weren’t represented at the time of the enactment of those statutes. Whereas, if we think about looking at legal practices or, say, common law meanings, that may actually allow for the inclusion of more voices than looking at state statutes because even enslaved persons often appeared before the judiciary, that there are ways of excavating different voices through, say, the common law tradition that might not be apparent within the, say, state statutes or the work of representative bodies. So I think that being attentive to what kinds of governmental sources are used as well as looking at the kinds of newspaper sources and other sources that Elizabeth was mentioning is another way of opening up the conversation when you’re looking at different voices that are part of a conversation about original meaning.

 

Hon. Britt Grant:  I’ll add one thing, too, if I might. Excuse me. I think original public meaning has become the main lens of originalism, but to Dean’s point, I don’t think that originalism as a scholarly or judicial enterprise has been completed as a project. And I’ve recently heard presentations about original methods originalism or original law originalism, and I think it’s important as we continue this project to be open to new ideas about how we can best interpret the Constitution or even statutes. I think that’s an important thing to consider.

 

When we think of originalism, we often think of just the Constitution, but in my experience, both at the state courts and at the federal court, sometimes I was looking at statutes from the 1800s to try to figure out what appellate procedure from 1964 in Georgia really meant. And so, I think it’s important to really keep our eye on all of the options for originalism as an interpretive method and to keep open, keep reading scholarship, thinking through all this -- all those different aspects of it.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Paul.

 

Hon. Paul D. Clement:  So I’d just like to, in a couple of the earlier remarks, just sort of concur in part and dissent in part. I’m not a judge, but I still like to think I can do that. [Laughter] I completely agree with Elizabeth that when you’re interpreting the Fourteenth Amendment, that taking into account the understanding of the original public meaning in the African American community’s absolutely essential. I’ve used that to argue that actually the Freedmen and the Freedmen Bureaus had a robust understanding that the Fourteenth Amendment was going to protect their Second Amendment rights. And that’s exactly what they understood was part of the protection that they were getting through the adoption of the Fourteenth Amendment. And I do think, more generally, sometimes, The Federalist Society folks, we love to look at sort of Madison and Hamilton, and we’re not as interested in the Reconstruction Amendments, and I don’t know why that would be the case.

 

The Reconstruction Amendments are hugely important to the extent that they are the vehicle through which the Bill of Rights is incorporated against the states. There’s a robust debate about what original public meaning matters: 1789 or 1868, and I don’t know how that’s ultimately going to be resolved. But personally, I think, 1868’s got to be hugely relevant, and I think some of the leading Reconstruction-era senators are folks that we ought to have -- I don’t know -- panels named after or something. I think we should really be focused on that because it’s a huge part of our constitutional history, so I totally agree with that.

 

I guess where I dissent in part is I think the project of consistently trying to unearth something that was obscure even in 1789 has really limited utility. In the context of arguing the Bruen case, the folks on the other side unearthed a third reporter of Knight’s case that was a little bit different from the two standard widely circulated reports of that decision and tried to make something of it. But there’s -- if there’s an obscure report of a case in three libraries in England and no evidence that that report ever made it to this side of the Atlantic, who cares? The idea is we don’t care about what people were thinking in 1789 just for the sake of identifying somebody that had a goofy view of an otherwise fairly clear provision in the Constitution. What we’re -- I think the point of the project is to try understand what the people who were ratifying the Constitution and discussing the Constitution -- and I’ll spot Elizabeth this: I don’t think we only care about the people who could vote in the ratification process. I think we care about everybody in the body politic on this side of the Atlantic.

 

But if you come up-- if some great scholar comes up with some private diary of somebody in their own idiosyncratic view of something, I don’t care about that. That doesn’t seem at all relevant to the project, so I do think we got to -- you got to keep in mind the whole endpoint of the project in deciding which sources you’re going to credit and which sources really move the needle.

 

Hon. Elizabeth Wydra:  I think that you’d probably fail the public part of the public meaning if it’s someone’s private diary, but I think we just have to be, I think, very cautious about noting what things might be obscured by the fact that certain historians have been doing historical work and haven’t been interested in certain voices versus what is obscured because it’s in someone’s drawer next to their bed. And so, when you’re talking about entire tribes, for example, debating parts of the Constitution that are very much relevant to their daily lives, that isn’t something that’s gotten a lot of attention because -- partly because some of the scholarly work is just beginning, but that is the type of thing that I’m saying is really important to include and making sure that -- there’s a lot of criticism, I think, of the project that people pick and choose what works best for them on both sides. And by being more inclusive with these voices, I think, we can have a richer view and more accurate view of original public meaning and also see the places where there is contestation, where there might be several different original public meanings and having to have the judges -- ya’ll have a hard job sometimes. It’s not always just super easy, one answer, and that’s going to be something that should be presented to the judges for them to interrogate themselves.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Judge Ho.

 

Hon. James C. Ho:  So just to dive into this nice exchange we’re seeing, I like information, the more data, the better, just because I’m interested and want to sort to get -- make sure I’m getting the best arguments on all sides. So in that spirit, I certainly have no concerns and would agree with Elizabeth that I want to hear about everything. Having said that, I think we would want to be sensitive, of course, to are we seeing a situation where different communities have different meanings of words. Is it sort of -- there’s ordinary meaning that the community understands, and a particular community that sees it as a term of art. Is it genuine dispute over words having different concepts, or is it really just different communities having different policy preferences? Without knowing the details of some of the cases we’re talking about here because I wasn’t involved in those, I would be curious to see to what extent the differences are differences of meaning or -- versus differences of policy preferences.

 

I like Dean’s story about the toddlers and the fear of the shots. I’ll confess it reminds me of my own kids. Allyson and I have wonderful children and, frankly, somewhat weird children. These are the only kids you’ll ever meet who do not like their birthdays because they are worried about going to the doctor for the annual exam and getting shots. I’m not kidding. They literally tell us they don’t like their birthdays for that reason. So I appreciate the story on a personal level.

 

Of course, the answer to the proposed interpretive fight in that story is does the child actually believe that anywhere means anywhere, anybody’s body, or does context make clear that it’s anywhere on his body? And so, again, he may want to say he that has a different community definition, but I do -- but I wonder if it’s more motivated reasoning than an actually good faith debate about the meaning of words.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  All right. So since we have an expert on Bruen here, Bruen introduced something that might be -- I’m not sure if it’s new, but it certainly became prominent in Bruen, and that is a discussion of this phrase, “text, history, and tradition.” And so, one thing we might want to think about is what do each of those individual items — text, history, and tradition — play in a proper originalist analysis. Tradition is the one that really stands out on the list, and Judge Newsom, who was originally going to moderate this panel, wrote in a concurrence to his own excellent opinion. He wrote a concurrence to the opinion in which he has a footnote, which raises this question.

 

He said, “It’s never been clear to me what work tradition is supposed to be doing in the tripartite “text, history, and tradition” formulation. To the extent that tradition is meant to stand in for the original, i.e. historical, public meaning of the words on the page, it’s duplicative. And to the extent that it is meant to expand the inquiry beyond the original public meaning, say, to encompass latter-day-but-still-kind-of-oldish understandings, it misdirects the inquiry.” So I guess I’ll just throw out Judge Newsom’s musings and let you all muse. Anyone want to comment on what role tradition is serving?  Paul?

 

Hon. Paul D. Clement:  I’ll take a crack at it, not that I really think it has a lot to do with having argued Bruen, but I do think this is an emerging trend. I think that that also -- when the Court noted the death of the Lemon test and talked about what would replace it, it also talked about text, history, and tradition. So this is obviously -- it’s kind of a throughline in a lot of areas of the law, and so, it would be nice if history and tradition were not like a doublet that really had no independent meaning. It seems like if the Supreme Court telling us three things, we ought to try to differentiate the last two. I think one way of thinking about it is that you could think of history as being the things that predate the relevant time period, like the Framing, if we’re talking about that, and then the tradition being what follows the Framing to the point where the Court is reaching the interpretive question. And maybe I’m sort of very, very gently taking a little bit of issue with Judge Newsom’s framing. It’s never a great idea for a lawyer. But to me, I --

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  He’s not here.

 

Hon. Paul D. Clement:  Yeah, well. That helps. That helps. But maybe a good illustration is something like the practice of legislative prayer, and does that violate the Establishment Clause? And you could look at the practice in England in the Parliament or the practice in Congress and the Articles of Confederation, and I think that you would say that’s history. And then, you would look at the fact that Congress had a chaplain in the First Congress, and all the same people that were proposing the Bill of Rights and the Establishment Clause, in particular, didn’t think there was anything problematic about having a chaplain. And then, you look at the fact that the Second Congress and the Third Congress and the Fourth Congress and the Fifth Congress and the Sixth Congress, etc., etc. all had the same thing. And then, in the 1970s, the Supreme Court is asked to say does this unbroken practice violate the Establishment Clause. Has there been a sort of lurking Establishment Clause violation going back to the Framing of the country?

 

And it seems to me that there is -- that it is perfectly appropriate for the Court to look at that tradition and to simply say, well, that stuff happened after the Framing, so it doesn’t really inform the original public meaning. I guess I would disagree, which is to say, first -- you could probably spot me the first twenty Congresses because that’s a bunch of people who might have been alive and well at the time of the Framing, but then, there is a certain humility that kicks in at a certain point. And there’s almost like a sibling resemblance with something like the major questions doctrine where just when you’re -- and whether you buy sort of the full-blown majority view or the Justice Barrett concurrence view, I think there’s a strain of judicial humility that sort of says, gee whiz, if somebody’s coming in and telling me something that has been going on a long, long time and nobody’s thought it either violated this constitutional provision or violated this statute, that is something that ought to be a strike against the person saying that this well-established practice has really violated the law all around. I don’t think it -- I think there’s probably a reason it’s third on the list. But it seems to me there is something there that’s different from history and probably does have an important role to play in interpretation.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Thoughts? Comments?

 

Hon. Britt Grant:  I think I would generally agree with that, and I would say that whether we look at tradition as a reflection of settled understandings that, as Paul says, maybe judicial humility would suggest thinking really hard before we interrupt those settled understandings or some sort of liquidation throughout time. We’ve seen Founders discussing liquidation, and there are a lot of debates about what that means. But maybe that’s an idea where, even if it wasn’t entirely clear at the beginning, if we can see that there is a tradition of interpreting something a specific way, then maybe that’s something that we could pay attention to as well. So it’ll be interesting to see, as this doctrine develops and extends in other areas, whether we reach any consensus on what tradition means with respect to those two things.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Bernadette -- Professor Meyler? Sorry.

 

Prof. Bernadette Meyler:  Yes. No, that’s okay. So I think that I see it going back a little bit further to the Washington against Glucksberg test for the Fourteenth Amendment due process inquiry and that their tradition is playing a role and a tradition of protection of particular rights. And I think that, in that context, we might wonder whether evolving tradition or a more static tradition is what should be looked to and whether -- and also how broadly a tradition can be defined. Is it a tradition of protecting parental rights per se or protecting the rights of a non-marital father? So I think that those are some of the issues that I see coming up with respect to tradition. It’s the question of how broadly a particular tradition is defined and also whether you’re looking to an unbroken tradition since the Founding or looking to the evolution of tradition.

 

And that’s where I might distinguish it a bit from what Paul Clement was saying about major questions because, in that context, it’s not just something that’s new that might be called into question under certain understandings of tradition but rather something that’s evolved away from the original meaning. So I think that sometimes there could be a conflict between, say, precedent or -- and I know there’s another panel on precedent -- and original meaning where the tradition that has evolved through precedent might have deviated from what people now think would be the original meaning of a particular clause.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Right. And I think an example of that might be if you think about the Crawford case. So we had a long tradition of substituting hearsay rules for confrontation. We did that for a very, very long time, and the Supreme Court, in Crawford, said, “No. We have to look at confrontation and what the original meaning of that is. And it’s not the same as the hearsay rules.” And so, despite the fact that there was a long tradition, we went -- we reverted to the original public meaning.

 

Hon. James C. Ho:  Well, I wonder whether that suggests what I assume to be true but -- and not controversial but would welcome people to disagree. When we talk about text, history, and tradition, what I’m assuming we really mean is text. Text is what we’re looking at, whether you call it textualism or originalism. That’s what we’re interpreting as lawyers and judges. It’s to the extent where the text has -- is ambiguous. It’s capable of different of meanings -- competing communities, what have you, where we then look to other tools, whether it’s dictionaries or history or tradition or canons of interpretation or anything else.

 

You mentioned Glucksberg, and whether it’s Glucksberg or Bruen, I think, frankly, we’re all sort of eagerly awaiting to see what the Supreme Court tells us it means when it refers to history and tradition. Glucksberg seems to be the standard, revived and recodified in Dobbs. Tradition could, theoretically, include a lot of things. It does include economic liberty. You referred to parental rights. If we’re serious about tradition in addition to text, that opens up a whole new area of analysis, or is tradition subservient to text, which might take us to a different path. And I think the Supreme Court presumably will tell us at some point.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  So maybe the test, as you would propose it, is text as informed by history and tradition?

 

Hon. James C. Ho:  I assume that’s what we’re doing, but I’m waiting for the Supreme Court to teach us, so I can do what they’re telling us to do. It’s not always easy to do what they want us to do.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Fair. Speaking of -- that’s a perfect segue. So let’s talk about precedent. So what role does an originalist analysis preserve for precedent? Do we think of precedent as part of originalism, as sort of being baked into Article III’s reference to the judicial power? Or is precedent antithetical to a true consistency -- consistent commitment to originalism? Do the practitioners on the panel think differently about this than the judges? Anybody want to talk about precedent? Nobody wants to talk about precedent. Okay. So the Supreme Court -- I’ll talk about precedent.

 

Hon. James C. Ho:  It’s like Bruno.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  So the Supreme Court has told us -- for those of us on the panel who are middle managers, right, appellate judges, we have to do what our nine bosses tell us, and we try very hard to faithfully follow what they tell us. And one thing that they have told us very clearly -- you might call this -- I like to call it the Agostini principle. Some people call is the Rodriguez [inaudible 00:50:39] principle. But one thing they’ve told us very clearly is that when there is a case that is directly on point, even if we the lower court judges look around and think, “Gosh, the foundations of this precedent have been undercut. It doesn’t seem consistent at all with the way that the Supreme Court is telling us to approach cases.” Now, the Supreme Court has told us, “You are to apply our precedent when there’s a case directly on point, and we, the Supreme Court, will overrule our own precedence. Thank you very much, lower court judges, for your input.”

 

So I try to do that because that’s what they told me to do. But one thing that I think about often is whether that’s consistent with the judicial role. If you think that a case is wrongly decided, if it’s a case that wasn’t decided using an originalist methodology, if you think it’s a case that you’re pretty sure the Supreme Court would overrule, what do you do as a lower court judge? So I can toss that out to the other judges, or I can keep talking, but it’s probably more interesting to hear from you.

 

Hon. James C. Ho:  I’ll take a quick stab at it. So this is one of these eternal debates that I have with -- I’m sure many judges have with law clerks, which is -- the argument will be, “Judge, you didn’t swear an oath to uphold Supreme Court precedent. You swore an oath to uphold the Constitution. So does that suggest that you get to do whatever you want in terms of interpreting the Constitution?” It’s an interesting argument.

 

It’s obviously trying to look at the words of the oath, and it’s a view that’s held by, to my knowledge, not a single member of the federal judiciary, [laughter] for any number of obvious reasons. It’s a hierarchal; we don’t want to be fired; we don’t want to overturned, etc., etc. Or if it’s anything else, you’re just kind of bumping your head against the wall. Right? The Supreme Court’s going to do what it’s going to do, and we have to follow it.

 

The way I’ve tried to reconcile it — and I often cite Judges Bumatay and Bush because they’ve written a lot on this topic — is we’re duty-bound to -- if you believe in originalism, which I just sort of think of as lawyering, then we’re duty-bound to be faithful to the text and original understanding of whatever words we’re supposed to be interpreting to the maximum extent permitted by a faithful reading of Supreme Court precedent. Now, obviously there are some words there that require further fleshing out, and I’m interested in sort of seeing how we flesh these out in future cases, but the point’s -- to me, the main things are maximum extent consistent with a faithful reading of precedence. That’s sort of how I try to wrestle with it at a sort of abstract level, and now, we have to sort of implement that in subsequent cases.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Does that mean that you would read a precedent -- the strict command is when there is a case directly on point. And does that influence how broadly or narrowly you read the precedent?

 

Hon. James C. Ho:  I think that’s what the word, “faithful,” is doing. Right? So you could say, “Well” — to use a very silly, stupid example — “the facts of that case -- that Supreme Court were done on a Tuesday. This is on a Wednesday. Obviously, that’s not faithful.” And so, you have to figure out what is the precedent. What is the rule that is being imposed on us by that Supreme Court decision?

 

And we try to be faithful to it, but we don’t have to extend it to situations that go outside of it. I fully acknowledge that leaves a lot of open discussion for what does it mean to be faithful, and as I said, that’s -- one sort of modest thought that I’ve seen fleshed out is you don’t want to make the law completely illogically by making it -- by distinguishing in ways that are utterly unprincipled. And so, that might be an initial take on that.

 

Hon. Britt Grant:  I think the question for us is very different than, of course, the question for the Supreme Court. Right? So I think they -- I think the question that they deal with is, to my mind, the most difficult one in originalism, which is where is that line between sticking with precedent, and it’s -- in certain cases, you know you have to overturn it. Right? We all know the classic cases that I won’t list here, but I think for us, as circuit judges, it’s a different question. I think I agree with Judge Ho about reading -- I won’t resay what he said either, but I think sometimes, though, there’s a kind of administrative rule to precedent that we also forget about.

 

I think the Eleventh Circuit has a unique background in this because, having split from the Fifth Circuit, the court made a very conscience decision to adopt all the precedence of the Fifth Circuit for our own. So in almost every single Eleventh Circuit case, you’ll see a footnote citing Bonner v. City of Prichard. I’m maybe messing that up, and I see it so much. But the point was the fact that a panel of this court may come out differently on one issue one time was not worth all of the upset to people’s understanding, lawyers’ understanding, litigants’ understanding of how they needed to put their behavior forward. So I think, as a -- on kind of the smaller issues, I think precedent becomes very important as an administrative matter. And then, on the more publicly divisive issues, I think it’s really interesting to see how we can apply some of those same tools in a thoughtful way and make sure that we’re fulfilling our duty to the Constitution and as intermediate appellate court judges as opposed to the ultimate deciders on the Supreme Court who, as you say, give us certain instructions about what to do.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Right. So I wonder to what extent that Agostini principle influences the way that lawyers think about presenting arguments to intermediate appellate courts. So if you’re a litigator and you think, “Look, this case is governed by precedent; it’s a constitutional question, but it’s governed by precedent,” are you just going to argue the precedent and then save the originalist fire for the U.S. Supreme Court? Or do you think about, “Well, maybe there’s an opening here; maybe there’s a way to read the case narrowly, the precedent narrowly,” and convince the panel that there’s an opening?

 

And part of this -- I wonder about this because, having been on the federal court now for, I don’t know, five years, maybe six years, we get very little briefing in our court that engages actual originalist methodology. There’s a case the Supreme Court just heard called Culley v. Marshall. I think that was last week. It involves the forfeiture of automobiles and whether you have a right to a pre-termination hearing when your vehicle is forfeited. Our court had decided a merits case on that. I was not on that panel, but the case was presented to a panel I was on earlier, the same question, and we dismissed at the motion-to-dismiss stage, so we didn’t reach the merits.

 

But in that litigation, there was no originalist briefing whatsoever of -- the litigation, as I recall, involved should we apply one of two doctrinal tests made up by the Supreme Court, the -- a balancing due process -- Mathews v. Eldridge balancing test or the Barker v. Wingo, also balancing test, out of the Speedy Trial Clause. And that’s the way the case was framed. I’m listening to the oral arguments last week, thinking, “Oh, I know what this case is about,” and they’re talking about, “Well, should we follow the historical analysis presented to us by this group of amici or by this group of amici?” And I thought, “Wow. It really would have been helpful to have some group of amici. That might have really been a nice thing.”

 

So, I guess, the question is as somebody litigating in the appellate courts, do you present your originalist case? Should you present your originalist case, or should you just hold your fire for the Supreme Court when all the guns will come out, and they’re going to get the best advocacy, and they can come to the best conclusion that way?

 

Hon. Jason Miyares:  I think it has been an interesting transformation, particularly in the state courts, what we have seen, where they’re now -- traditionally, they have outsourced and not used federal interpretation to interpret their state statutes. I think we’ve seen the opposite in the last several years, almost a revolution. I know that we have a case in Virginia, the West Point School Board case, where we actually made the argument to our solicitor, Andrew Ferguson, I think, quite robustly, looking at the Virginia statute of religious freedom and also looking at the -- both the original intent and the tradition of that. That was originally introduced in 1779 in the Virginia General Assembly at the genesis of Thomas Jefferson carried by a young, quiet delegate from Orange County, James Madison, with vehement opposition by a very vocal member of the General Assembly named Patrick Henry. And the origins of that really was that Patrick Henry had introduced legislation that was going to seek state support for the newly minted Episcopal Church in Virginia. Problem is almost every other Christian sect was horrified by this, and there was some vehement opposition.

 

And so, when we looked at -- when our solicitor argued it, we pointed out — in Virginia and it was reaffirmed; it was actually passed in 1786 by the General Assembly, and it was reaffirmed in 1971 — that the Virginia statute provide much more robust protections than the First Amendment Free Exercise Clause. And so, I thought we were able to make, I think, a pretty compelling argument, looking at the history of that, of the very explicit language that nobody should be burdened by practicing their religious beliefs by the state. And I’m not going to necessarily get into the facts of the West Point case because, candidly, it’s still pending in front of the Supreme Court. But I thought that was a great example of both using originalism and the precedent of what our case law was in a new setting in state court, which previously hadn’t really been done before.

 

Hon. Paul D. Clement:  Yeah. And Judge Larsen, I think from the perspective of federal court practice, at least the way I would answer the question, is it depends. And it depends where you are in the litigation. Are you trying -- where is the precedent? Is this a case where you really think you can maneuver around a Supreme Court precedent? If you are -- if the whole point of the litigation is to get a Supreme Court case overruled and the lower cases are hemmed in by the Agostini approach, then I don’t think there’s any point in pretending that those courts can overrule Supreme Court precedent. I think, in those circumstances, there’s one of two playbooks, and I’ve seen people do it both ways.

 

There’s a playbook that, I think, Mike Carvin used in trying to get the overruling of Abood back in front of the Court after the Court had signaled it, and he basically went into district court and said, “Hello. I lose under Abood. Please rule against me very quickly.” And then, he went to the Ninth Circuit and said, “Hello. We lose under Abood. Please rule against us very quickly.” And then, he filed the cert petition and got cert granted.

 

So that’s one approach. But you got to be pretty confident, a, that there’s no wiggle room, and, b, that there’s going to be a cert granted at the end of the rainbow. And so, if you’re litigating in a situation where it’s not that clear, you’ll try to get around it. You might use originalism. But I guess, this gets to a broader question, which is -- one reason you might do that as a litigant is one of the things that I think is a legitimate move for court of appeals judges, notwithstanding the Agostini principle, is there is this thing called the concurring opinion. I know Judge Ho’s used those from time to time.

 

And I don’t think there’s anything wrong with basically a judge saying, “I’m totally bound to apply the Supreme Court precedent, but I’m going to tell you in my concurring opinion why I think it’s wrong and why I think it would be useful if the Supreme Court revisited it.” And I think that’s both legitimate and, frankly, important because one downside of the Agostini principle is -- it’s great, and it’s orderly, but then, it doesn’t provide a great signaling device to the Supreme Court of the United States as to when they should reconsider their precedence. And they turned down a lot of cert petitions in my experience, so having something like a concurring opinion to point to can be really helpful.

 

Then, let me just say one other thing, which is -- so I think your point, Judge Larsen, really points to the -- kind of a broader phenomenon, which is one thing that’s a little weird about our system is that cases look a lot different in the court of appeals typically than they do in the Supreme Court of the United States. And that’s kind of weird in a system that’s supposed to be about that vertical review. And part of it is inevitable. The average court of appeals case probably has four or five issues in it, and they have to cover all those in the word limit. And then, it gets up to the Supreme Court, and there’s just a single issue there. The number of amici is generally smaller. I guess my thought, though, is if I were a court of appeals judge, I would, in cases that I think had a good chance of getting to the Supreme Court, I would try to narrow that gap.

 

And again, I think there are legitimate ways to do that. One example is that the -- if you have cases where it’s almost inevitable that the Supreme Court is going to call for the views of the solicitor general and be quite interested in what the solicitor general has to say, if I were a lower court judge, I would call for the views of the government -- the relevant government agency myself. Otherwise, it seems like you’re setting yourself up for failure because the Supreme Court’s going to be looking at something that’s very influential to them that you didn’t even give yourself a chance to look at. And similarly -- and maybe the judges on the panel would disagree with me, but I think if you’ve got a case where you really think this could go to the Supreme Court and you think there’s important historical literature that amici could bring to bear and the parties have dedicated all of three paragraphs to the argument, I don’t think there’s anything legitimate -- illegitimate, rather -- about a supplemental briefing order that invites the participation of amici.

 

Again, maybe you think that’s overreaching. Maybe you think that violates the strict Silberman-esque view of the Article III courts are stuck with the briefing of the adversarial parties, no matter how lousy. But I tend to think that’s a legitimate move, and it narrows that gap because I would think it’s very frustrating, as a court of appeals judge, to have the Supreme Court deciding an issue where, by the time it gets to the Supreme Court, it just is unrecognizable.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  That’s actually one of the first things now Chief Judge Sutton said to me when I came on the court is, “There’s a lot of things you’re going to learn about what it’s like to be a court of appeals judge, and one of those things is you’re going to decide a bunch cases, and they’re going to get upstairs, and you’re not -- you’re going to say, ‘Oh, wow. I didn’t know that’s what this case was about.’”

 

Hon. Elizabeth Wydra:  So I just want to apologize. One of the briefs that Justice Barrett was talking about in the Culley oral argument was indeed filed by the Constitutional Accountability Center, so I apologize for not filing that brief in your case.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Accepted.

 

Hon. Elizabeth Wydra:  Yes, it is truly a resources bandwidth question. But it’s -- that is, I think, a :real issue for the lower court cases because -- and it could be solved, as Paul suggests, by inviting amicus participation, but good originalism takes time, and it takes expertise, and particularly, on the left, there are not that many of us who are practicing it. And CAC is small but mighty, but we can only do so many cases. And I like my fellow colleagues to be able to sleep some time. And so, being able to write briefs that have that rigorous, credible originalist analysis takes a lot of work.

 

And so, it’s one thing when it’s in the Supreme Court, but it’s another trying to cover all the ground of the courts of appeals. And I think that’s a real challenge for judges because then are you trying to do it yourself. Are you asking for amicus participation? As a litigator, I want to give you the best argument, so I would like for my side -- whatever side I’m advocating for to be giving you those arguments. But that is not always possible in every case.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Yeah. Professor Meyler.

 

Prof. Bernadette Meyler:  Yeah. I was very curious about everyone’s take on whether or not to invite amicus participation at the appellate level, but I also wanted to introduce another element, which is just that I think some Supreme Court cases are directly lower courts, especially district courts, to actually engage in more originalist inquiry, especially if you think about the aftermath of Bruen, that in order for the government to kind of demonstrate that there were analogous statutes at the time of the Fourteenth Amendment, that, in a way, they’re going to have to already be doing originalist analysis at the district court level. And I’m also curious about how people feel about the expenditure of time on originalist analysis in that context as well.

 

Hon. James C. Ho:  So just to follow up, there are two things that have been said that I -- that are interesting to me. One is the resource limitation issue, and the other is the amici aspect. So on resource limitation, I was actually a litigator, an appellate litigator, longer than I’ve been a judge, and what strikes me as resource limitations are a huge issue on both fronts. In practice, obviously, it’s the limitations of your client. Some clients want to do full [inaudible 59:07]; other clients won’t. I think Paul is absolutely right. It depends on the nature of the case. The lawyer has to make the call about what’s valuable.

 

The resource limitations issues is also very serious in the judiciaries, particularly court of appeals. As practitioner, let’s say you argue, what, one case a month, one every other month, more than that. Whatever the number is, it’s some handful of cases that you’re getting involved with on a per-year basis. That provides you a decent -- hopefully, a decent amount of time, assuming your client’s willing, to really get in deep to make sure you’ve maximized every aspect of whatever legal issues are presented in your case. On the Fifth Circuit, we do 20 arguments per sitting, per month, seven sittings a month, and that’s just the argue cases in addition to all the other matters that we have to deal with. And so, the resource limitations are very serious, and so, we are essentially looking to lawyers to present briefs that are hopefully well-written and cover the waterfront.

 

And the way I think of it is if it’s not in the briefs and we think it’s important, we can dive in ourselves and try to -- obviously, we have party-presentation issues and forfeiture issues and whatnot, but as long as you presented the issue, we could theoretically do our own additional -- make sure you found all the cases and all the right authorities. But what I struggle with is every single minute I spend diving deeper on one case is time I’m taking away from every other case on my docket, never mind my family and my sleep. And so, I think the resource limitations on both sides of the bench, the podium and on the bench, are important aspects of this issue.

 

As to amici, I like amici. I liked it when I was a practitioner. I think they can be helpful. Obviously, the “Me Too” type of amicus brief where you’re just repeating what somebody else says, that not terribly helpful. It’s just a waste of space. But when it’s a good amicus brief, that can be wonderful.

 

And it’s not necessarily that the practitioner -- the party lawyer has messed up. Maybe they’ve omitted something, but maybe the amici has an angle that it’s more awkward for a particular party to present. I was involved in a case, one of these pre-Bostock-type cases where we invited amici, one particular amici, to argue because neither side had argued that Title VII doesn’t apply to certain classifications. So we invited amicus to do that. Having said that, I get nervous about doing that too much. I’m not sure why. Maybe it’s the silver mask view of the world. I certainly would be wary about playing favorites, signaling where a court is.

 

In the case that I mentioned where we did it, it was literally because we had one side of the case not represented. And so, we needed somebody to literally fill in a position. It’s sort of like when the Supreme Court invites somebody when the government confesses error. It’s that sort of thing. You just want the adversarial process. Beyond that, I’m -- put me as not sure.

 

Hon. Jason Miyares:  And I would say, just from the attorney general’s perspective, what we have seen is, particularly when you’re looking at amicus, you have state AG offices that are very under-resourced, and often times, they will look to team up with states with larger AGs office that maybe are aligned philosophically. And essentially, it’s a way to pull our resources together, which we do all the time, whether it’s a multi-state investigation. But we’ve found that repeatedly, what I have seen — it’s actually one of the things that has surprised me in my role is how much coordination there is with the other comparable state AGs and their SGs in working together on amicus briefs, almost like assigning homework assignments, of, “Can you help state X on this matter?” And everybody does each other a kind of solid when they need assistance themselves. And I have found it invaluable because what you’re able to do is you’re to engage more and maximum your resources, and you’re really able to help some of these states that have very, very small SG offices and able to really assist them, to provide resources. So I view it as invaluable.

 

Hon. Britt Grant:  I’ll add two things. First, to follow up on his comments, when I moved from private practice to the state attorney general’s office, I almost immediately within six months thought, “Wow, if at least a few of these cases that I was, I wish that we had reached out to relevant attorney general offices to ask them if they would be interested in filing an amicus brief to tell them about this case that was going to really affect the states in very particular ways.” And the courts didn’t have the states’ perspectives, and I think it might have made a difference in at least one and maybe two cases that I can think of right off the bat.

 

So I would say don’t ask states -- as he says, there are resources issues. Don’t ask states just willy-nilly but really think through. If you’re litigating an issue that’s going to make a big a difference to the states, it’s going to have an impact on state laws, even if it’s a federal case, then don’t hesitate to try to find those connections, try to reach out to the attorney general’s office, and let them know about the case. They may or may not be able to get involved, but I think the states do have a very important perspective in our system that -- thankfully, the states are litigating more and more and filing amicus briefs more and more. But I think it’s an area that still has room for additional growth.

 

And the other thing I’ll say about the adversarial process is so many of our doctrines are designed around the adversarial process. Right? Standing has been a really big question in the Supreme Court and the circuit courts lately. And I think when we think about doing it all on our own, we forget that so much of our system is designed around the idea that litigants will have the right incentives when they have a problem to really try to figure out the best arguments in favor of their position. And as judges, we’re just not always situated to figure out the best arguments in favor of one position and to realize that there are arguments on the other side, maybe from perspectives that we haven’t considered. And so, to my mind, briefing is really important and really helpful almost any time you’re digging into one of these questions. And I hope that, in both state and federal courts, we’ll start to see more of it as lawyers become aware that a lot of judges are thinking about these things in different and expansive ways.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  So we’ve been talking a lot about -- almost exclusively, about originalism as it’s practiced in federal court. We have here a former state Supreme Court justice. We have the attorney general of a state. General Miyares touched on this already a little bit, but I wonder whether there’s something different about doing originalism when you’re talking about interpreting a federal constitution, which the wrap on originalism that you hear on the -- from its critics is, ‘Oh, the federal Constitution is old, and it’s impossible to amend, and therefore, the judges need to update it.” That would be the critique.

 

I wonder whether that same -- those same concerns exist in most of the states, not all, for those of you on the Eastern seaboard. For those of you from Massachusetts with your Constitution of 1780, okay, I yield. But I come from a state which ratified its most recent constitution in 1963, so it’s not old, and it’s not hard to amend. It’s super easy. You can amend the Michigan Constitution -- not super easy but comparatively easy. You can amend the Michigan Constitution by initiative. We saw it happening in states just yesterday. And so, I wonder whether the arguments against originalism have less weight in state courts, and I wonder whether there’s anything different about doing originalism when we’re talking about a state constitution.

 

Hon. Jason Miyares:  At least from my perspective, Jefferson called the states the laboratories of democracy, and I find it fascinating that you’re having this kind of, not revolution, but a rethinking — Judge Sutton and others that have really pointed at using originalism in our state constitution. Obviously, Virginia and Massachusetts and others have a unique history of our own, just given the both depth and breadth and the history. But I think it’s absolutely a useful tool. Every state amends their constitution differently, as we all know. Obviously, Ohio does it by referendum. You have to have a requisite number of petition signatures to get it on a ballot, and then, it’s simply 50 percent of the voters.

 

In Virginia, it has to be passed by the General Assembly, both the House and Senate. It never goes to the governor’s desk. There has to be an intervening election of the Virginia House of Delegates, and then, the newly constituted General Assembly has to vote on the exact same measure, the exact same wording, cannot change so much as a comma. And then, if it passes, then it has to go to be ratified by the voters that November. So the Virginia Constitution is more difficult to amend than, say, the Ohio Constitution, but obviously, we have an amendment process that probably some would say would be easier than amending the federal Constitution.

 

I view it as an absolute tool that should be used at the state appellate level. I don’t think you should outsource it to a federal interpretation. I think you should look at -- I think you should have your state judges be looking at both the history, tradition, and the original meaning of the text because our constitution is relatively new in Virginia. And so, I think we’re in a totally different place than maybe what other people think, but from my perspective, I view it as an absolute useful tool, and I’d like to see more judges using it in Virginia, applying it to our state constitution and state law.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Go ahead. Professor Meyler.

 

Prof. Bernadette Meyler:  A thought about using originalism in the state context. So I think one of the reasons, potentially, for the move to original public meaning rather than original intent is the fact that we have no official notes of the federal convention that established the Constitution. We have Madison’s notes on the Convention, but it was not supposed to be recorded. So there’s a way in which there is a lack of contemporaneous information. We have to derive insights from a retrospective account or from very piecemeal accounts of various participants.

 

Of course, that’s not exactly the case with the Reconstitution Amendments. We can look at the Congressional record for those. But I think that that influences a bit the tone of originalism within the federal context, and I think that the fact that, in a lot of state contexts, we do have availability of deliberations about the constitution perhaps might lend itself towards having more argument about what the meaning of particular clauses of a state constitution might be based on the original intent rather than original public meaning.

 

Another consideration, though, I think does have to with the referendum process. And I know, coming from California, there are a number of fairly poorly drafted measures that have been put on the ballot, and it’s not entirely clear that the public explanations given for them were accurate or really reflected what the language actually says, and the drafting itself isn’t really very easy to pin down. So I think that that raises some complications. What exactly were voters voting on? And it raises some questions about how to kind of interpret a clause like that. And I think that that is somewhat different from the federal context where amendments go through a much more rigorous and much more lengthy process. And so, you would have a lot more material to go on in terms of determining what the original public meaning of a federal amendment was.

 

Hon. Elizabeth Wydra:  I think that’s a really great point about the availability of sources and clear sources for some of these analyses because if we don’t do a rigorous analysis, then it’s not really helpful to the judges. One area in which Constitutional Accountability Center has been able to participate in state courts, even with resource limitations, is many state constitutions incorporate by reference either the text explicitly or the values of the Fourteenth Amendment or the Declaration of Independence. And so, we’ve been able to file in state cases under state constitutions that include that reference because we have done the originalist work on those amendments and the principles and values of the Declaration of Independence.

 

Hon. Britt Grant:  You see in state constitutions, I think, interesting interpretive principles, and legal fiction sometimes start to take place. And one thing that you said reminded me. On Georgia constitutional amendments, the rule -- obviously, the amendment is typically longer than you can have on the ballot, and the rule that the Georgia Supreme Court put in place decades ago is the description on the ballot has to be enough to let the voter know which constitutional amendment they’re voting on under the legal fiction, that that will allow everyone to think back to the time when they personally and individually before the vote reviewed the text of the constitutional amendment in full to determine whether they wanted to vote for it. So it’s interesting.

 

In Georgia, too, there’s a rule that we -- if you -- if the Georgia Supreme Court had an interpretation of a provision and then the constitution was amended on a large-scale basis and that provision stayed, then the view is that the writers of that particular constitution were aware of this Georgia Supreme Court opinion and did not intend to change it in any way. So that’s locked that provision in, almost in perpetuity. And so, I think some things are certainly easier because we have more modern language, especially with the amendments, but some things are a little bit harder because of these interpretative conventions and some of the difficulties with the direct-to-the-people voting that we’ve discussed. So I think there are things that are easier, things that are harder, but I don’t think that it -- I don’t think it makes it more defensible to do it because I think it’s our duty as judges to interpret what the law is. And whether you’re at the state or the federal level, the Constitution, until it’s changed, is the law, and it’s our job to figure out really what that said and to give our best effort and use all the tools that we have.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Okay. So we’ve talked about federal courts, and we’ve talked about state courts. And I don’t want to put too much burden on Professor Meyler, but I don’t think we should neglect the academy. And so, I have two broad questions. The first is probably directed specifically to Professor Meyler, which is she’s an actual legal historian, and so, one question I have is how does a historian approach originalism, the process of divining the public meaning of a particular constitutional provision. And does that differ from the way that courts and judges might do that, or is it the -- basically, the same project? So that’s my first question. And then, I guess, the second question would be are the law schools helping. Are they helping us to -- helping our -- the students to become practitioners who can deploy these tools?

 

Prof. Bernadette Meyler:  Great. Well, thank you so much for giving me that opportunity. So I would say that historians -- and I’m not a PhD in history. I’m a PhD in English, so I think of myself as doing work on kind of interpretation as well as history, although my work was in early modern England. And I think that one way in which historians approach originalism may be differently than lawyers or practicing lawyers does have to do with the resource question that came up earlier because, I think, we have more opportunity to delve in-depth into particular provisions over a longer period of time. We can do archival research that might take a very long time.

 

I had a project that dealt with the New Jersey decisions, pre-Constitution, of the various local courts in New Jersey. And it turned out that the archives and records in New Jersey couldn’t find the materials for a year, but then, that was fine because my project could take two years. That would not be okay on an appellate court level. So I think that that’s one way in which there is a big difference.

 

Another difference, I think, has to do with one of purpose. Right? So my colleague, Jonathan Knapp (sp), has recently written a book on originalism and history. We are -- he is bringing forward various ways in which historians would critique the practice of originalism for contemporary purposes and looks at a variety of different factors of why there might be a different objective in unearthing the history as opposed to applying it today. And one of the main issues really has to do with context, right, so that if we’re bringing to light some original meaning of a clause from 1789, then we may be taking it out of the context in which it was created. There may be -- according to Jonathan’s account, a written constitution meant something different in the 18th century than it does today. By deracinating the -- a provision from the general constitutional context, we’re misunderstanding it.

 

Now, I think that it’s important, nevertheless — and this is sort of my interpretive lens — to try to create some form of continuity between the moment of the Founding and today, that we can’t just take it as an alien document that was one thing then and is another thing now so that there is a need to engage in interpretation in the same way as we would try to interpret Shakespeare today and have a relevance for Shakespeare today. But I do think that because historians have more, say, time on their hands to engage in the effort that there’s going to be a survey of more sources. There’s going to be more openness to a less determinant meaning. Right? So I think that a lot of the clauses, if you look at a lot of the original materials from the colonies as well as from England, you see that there isn’t necessarily one determinant meaning that can be pinned down of the common law background of the Constitution. I think that’s not as much of a problem for historians as for judges who are trying to apply the Constitution in the present.

 

And on the front of our law schools helping, I think it’s an interesting question of what exactly the law school pedagogy is now. So teaching a first-year law school discussion seminar on histories of legal education and if you look from Langdell, who founded the American legal education system through the present, there is a remarkable continuity, actually, of what are the required first-year classes, and based on Langdell, we focus almost entirely on cases. Right? And that’s the -- case method was kind of sanctified in the late 19th century as the way that we approach teaching law students. And I think that some originalists, certainly my colleague Michael McConnell is among these, have kind of brought in more original sources in teaching the Constitution. I bring it in in my classes sometimes. And in other classes, we have deep dives into history.

 

There’s more interdisciplinarity, so I think that more historians are teaching in law schools by one count of one my colleagues. At a meeting recently, he thought we have nine legal historians on the faculty. So there’s an effort to kind of bring in more of those perspectives. But I think that actually, in the last 150 years, law schools have changed less than we might think and that the case method is still the dominant method and that that means that precedent rather than original meaning tends to be what’s focused on.

 

Hon. Jason Miyares:  I think there is an enormous crisis in higher ed in general, but I also think, in law school, you have a suffocating level of political correctness and progressive orthodoxy that has a view of originalism as immoral, and therefore, they won’t teach it, or if they do teach it, they play lip service. And think of the utter shock for so many of these law school graduates that suddenly are encountering judges that have that as part of the expectations. And I think you have a real crisis right now. You have elite law schools, in particular, that are preaching diversity in everything but thought. There is simply almost virtually no ideological diversity whatsoever. And I think that is creating a real, real problem right now.

 

We have a robust intern program in the AG’s office, so we get students from both Ivy League schools and state schools in Virginia. And I will tell you the conversations that I’ve had with so many of those young students who are incredibly bright that are interning in our office -- the only word I would use to describe how they are seeing America, in general, is disdain, utter disdain. And they are really struggling right now with self-censure ship. The leave of fear that these students have on these campuses is palpable, and it is not conservative professors. And so, I -- it is one of the most troubling, long-term trends that I see right now for this country, in general, when over 50 percent of those ages 18 to 24 say, for example, that Hamas is justified in slaughtering innocent men, women, and children, and less than a third say they have a love of America. I don’t think that happened by chance, and I think, unfortunately, what you’re seeing in our undergrad campuses, I would multiple it even higher in so many of our elite schools. So I think they are not equipping students to come out properly trained in how to look at originalism because, like I said, they view originalism as immoral. And I think it is a real troubling long-term trend in higher ed right now.

 

Hon. Paul D. Clement:  And just one thought on this. Look, I love legal historians as much as the next person, but I don’t think the solution to this problem is adding legal historians to law school faculties. And part of it is, I think, we’re -- by the time we start focusing on originalism and the work of legal historians — and again, I don’t mean to denigrate that; that’s -- there’s a reason that’s always been a discipline, even back in the ‘70s, when the Supreme Court didn’t give a fig about originalism — but it really is a little bit separate. And I think that the way that -- the best thing a historian could do is -- could unearth some new thing that nobody else knew was not part of the original public meaning, or a lot of what of legal historians spend their time doing is coming up with a revisionist history so everything we thought we knew about something gets turned on its head. And I would imagine there’s a few people in academia whose whole project in legal historian -- in legal history is really to defeat originalism and show that you can come up with a counter-history to everything. And that’s why I have to get back to the project, and I think Judge Ho had it exactly right when he said the project is text informed by history and tradition.

 

And so, I think we may be overmystifying originalism to the point where, oh, no mere lawyer can do this and you need a legal historian to do this. And if that’s the case, then I kind of think that either the Supreme Court took a wrong turn or we all took a wrong turn by going getting our Juris Doctors instead of our PhDs in history. But I don’t think either the Court or this group has taken a wrong turn. I think we just got to get back -- that, yes, history and tradition is important to inform the text. Part of the reason that Justice Scalia was on about this project was to constrain the discretion of judges and to give them clear targets to shoot at that are consistent with life tenure and judicial modesty. And part of the reason that you want to have more focus on text, history, and tradition is in lieu of an intermediate scrutiny rubric where any judge can come up with any result they possibly want.

 

So I just think it’s important to kind of demystify this a little bit, and the -- in a sense, the question is not, “Let’s get to the absolute best historical account of some incident,” but it’s really just -- it’s a little less daunting. It’s just, “Okay, there are these words. These words are our Constitution. They were ratified at a particular time.” If there’s a particular ambiguity, the history can help. If there is an unbroken tradition that goes back to the Framing and somebody’s telling you that, “That’s actually been unconstitutional since 1789, just nobody but me was smart enough to figure it out until now,” those are all things you should be skeptical about. But it's not that hard a project, and at the end of the day, it all gets back to the text anyways.

 

Hon. Elizabeth Wydra:  And I think, just to follow up on what Paul said -- maybe I’m just agreeing with him because I only have a JD and not a PhD in history as well, but I think it’s also just what we’re teaching about the Constitution. What I do in my daily work is very focused on the Reconstruction Amendments, but I think so many folks, when they think about the Constitution or when they think about originalism, they think of the Constitution as it existed in the 18th century. And even law students, I think, do not have a -- to the extent they even get an education on the 18th century founding of the United States Constitution, they have even less of an education on what many have called the Second Founding that happened after the Civil War. And that doesn’t have to be ideological.

 

Honestly, teaching the Constitution should be something that is cross-ideologically embraced. You can critique it, of course. You can embrace it. But I think, certainly, knowing it is powerful as a lawyer, as an American. And I think that it’s also very interesting to look at the way in which the amended Constitution really writes across the face of our national charter our story of national progress in addition to constitutional progress. And so, I think including that in more law school constitutional law classes would be incredibly useful.

 

And then, of course, to second Paul’s point about it isn’t this mysterious PhD practice -- but I think it’s also interesting to students to see the ways in which you apply what can seem like distant history to very current debates. And I know when I speak with students about how a Fourteenth Amendment originalist argument relates to reproductive justice, they find that very interesting and, similarly, with other issues. So I would love to see more Constitution education on that front in law schools, and it wasn’t really there when I was at Yale, so Yale, call me.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  All right. So I thought we might take some questions from the audience, if people have questions. I’ve now said, “Questions,” twice, and I’m going to say it again. It should be a question. That ends with a question mark. There are microphones. If you can make your way to the microphone, then we can hear you. And also, one more thing, tell us who you are.

 

Coach Weinhaus: Hi. Coach Weinhaus for Yeshiva University, or UCLA, and Abusive Discretion. The panel did an excellent job, exploring sources of methods of originalism, and Mr. Clement evoked judicial humility. And I’m curious how do we, as a society, identify judges who will be able to stay true to originalism and then, keep choosing, I guess, to limit their own power through other forms of discretion?

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Well, I think the confirmation process is designed to do that. The appointment and confirmation process is designed to do that. I think that when presidents are selecting judges, they are certainly entitled to ask about methodology, not about approaches to particular questions but certainly about what the judges’ political -- not political philosophy -- judicial philosophy, not political leanings, are. So I think that’s the process we have in place for dealing with that question.

 

Hon. Jason Miyares:  I would say this -- your question’s about -- where society’s impact on this. I think it’s going to be very, very difficult for, from a larger perspective of where society is -- I was reading a social scientist who’s talking about the decoupling of purpose in society, and he was not a conservative. He made this observation. I thought this was fascinating. He said, “We are the first society in human history, in all of human history, to reject the wisdom of those that have come before us.” It is a complete phenomenon in Western Europe and North America.

 

And if you go to Africa, if you go to Asia, if you go to Latin America, they have reverence for those that have come before and their wisdom. And it is only a recent phenomenon in the last several decades, the last 30 or 40 years, in which Western society has made the determination in a lot of, I would say, elite institutions that we’re going to simply reject those that have come before us because they have nothing to offer us. I think that permeates in almost everything that you see in a larger society, so I think that it is -- it’s -- our originalist judges, given what I’ve just described is having in academia -- I think it will get probably more difficult moving forward. Even though you have seen, I think, originalism become much more broadly accepted in a variety of legal circles, I also think it is also going to be more challenging.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  All right. It’s hard to see over here, but we have a question -- oh, it’s Roger Pilon.

 

Roger Pilon:  Yes. Yes, it is, from the Cato Institute. Thank you, Judge Larsen. My question is whether Judge Ho’s clerks may have been right when they asked whether even appellate judges should take their oath more seriously to the Constitution rather than to precedent. And I give you the important case of 1995, U.S. v. Lopez, where old Judge Harwood [sic], on the Fifth Circuit, entertained the argument from a young public defender in that case who had the effrontery to say that the Commerce Clause does not authorize Congress to enact the Gun-free School Zones Act. That power belongs to the state of Texas. But for the fact that Garwood said, “He’s right,” that case probably would not have made it to the Supreme Court. But in so doing, Harwood [sic], who, of course, was around in 1937, said, “Maybe the Court got it wrong on the Commerce Clause in 1937.”

 

Hon. James C. Ho:  So if the idea is that Judge Garwood’s opinion in -- at the Fifth Circuit level in Lopez was a defiance of Supreme Court precedent, I’ll be candid. I’m interested in that. I’m going to go look at that. I was not aware that it was literally defying Supreme Court precedent. That’s inconsistent with all the cases we talked about in terms of Agostini and Rodriguez. The Supreme Court has told us repeatedly not to anticipate.

 

Roger Pilon:  Well, professors had to rewrite their casebooks after the Supreme Court upheld Harwood [sic] --

 

Hon. James C. Ho:  Well, sure, in the sense that the Commerce Clause had not been used to impose limits on federal power until Lopez and Morrison and what have you. But that’s different from saying that Lopez is literally irreconcilable with cases like Wickard, and if I recall, the Supreme Court itself reconciled those opinions. So like I said, I’m always open-minded, always open to being proven wrong. If there is an argument that Lopez was correctly decided as an originalist matter but completely insubordinate, from a Supreme Court precedent matter, that’s news to me, and I’m -- certainly would be interested in learning more about that.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  All right. We’ll go over here to the left.

 

Hon. John Curry:  Okay. Thank you. Judge John Curry from Chicago. Judge Ho, you pointed out that sometimes there’re somewhat politically motivated textualism arguments, and they may be rooted in some community or some political object. Clearly, in the progressive field, let me sort of sketch out what we see. The academy will generate some sort of progressive perspective, and that may mean changing language, using language in a different way. Then, the general media picks it up, and then, the politicians pick it up, so we have a new meaning, which is really rooted in the left or progressive point of view. And then, that’s used as a fulcrum for arguing a case, saying, well, this is what the text in this law or the Constitution says, and it really means this.

 

And I think the example you gave that, well, that could be shown to be originating in a community as opposed to really what the text is about, the original public meaning of the text. Wouldn’t you think it would be a good idea when this occurs to -- for a judge or an advocate in a brief to actually point out, “This is the root. They’re arguing this is what this means, but this is where it rose from. It started out at the University of California, Berkeley, and then, The New York Times picked it up, and then, certain political operatives have generated this. And that’s not truly the meaning that was in this statute.” I wonder if you think that approach would be useful. I think it would be useful to see that read so you get out the fact that this is not really an accepted public meaning but a politically motivated meaning.

 

Hon. James C. Ho:  Yeah. I would just say I think I sort of noted earlier I think we all agree that we’re always interested in more information. I think your question, if I understand it, sort of reminds me of what Justice Thomas has often said, which is -- I forget him metaphor about adding cars to a train but then asking the question, “Are we even going in the right direction?” So certainly, let me just use this as an opportunity to kind of comment on what Elizabeth said earlier, which is — and I agree with it — which is originalism properly done isn’t conservative, isn’t liberal. It’s just lawyering. And if that’s the goal, I do take it -- I do take some solace -- we were talking about the selection process in the first question. We now have a consensus at least in terms of what people say, which is the judicial function is, in fact, an originalist function.

 

Swearing an oath to follow the Constitution means you will actually follow the written Constitution. At this point, I’m not aware of anybody who openly defies that. How good we are -- each and every one of us is actually doing that and doing it faithfully and following Justice Scalia’s principle that a bad judge was -- a judge who always likes the results of their decisions is a bad judge. I think that’s a pretty good principle to go by, but originalism properly done is steadfastly neither progressive, conservative, liberal, whatever terminology you want to use.

 

Hon. John Curry:  Thank you.

 

Hon. Paul D. Clement:  Yeah. And the only thing I’d add is just, again, getting back to, I guess, what is my theme, which is originalism isn’t something separate. It’s just one mode of trying to get the text right. And so, the principles that you’re talking about in terms of dealing with history aren’t really any different from the principles that I think you’re supposed to use when you’re interpreting statutory text, and you look at a bunch of dictionaries, and there’s one outlying dictionary, and you try to figure out, well, what’s going on with that one outlying dictionary. And Justice Scalia wrote an opinion for the Court in the MCI against AT&T case that’s had a second life as part of the major questions doctrine. But at the time, it was famous because it was the first time that Justice Scalia just ripped a new one into Webster’s Third.

 

But what generated that scorn for Webster’s Third is he was looking at a whole bunch of definitions of the word, “modify,” and then, he sees one that just is completely out of whack with the others. And then, he went back and realized that, okay, Webster’s, when it put out its third dictionary, decided to stop trying to figure out what words actually mean and just tried to essentially assemble widespread misuse of words and make that one of the definitions. And so, based on that, he threw out one definition of modify that didn’t fit in with any of the others.

 

And I think, when you’re looking at history, if at a certain point -- it seemed like everybody understood that a term meant a certain thing, historically, but then, all of a sudden, a revisionist school comes along -- you have to be cognizant of that but not because you have to be a great historian, just because you have to approach the job of interpreting the text the same basic way when it comes to historical sources as with respect to just the basic text and how you’d interpret a statute.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Okay. Sorry. The light is in my eyes, so I can’t really see you, but you can speak up and tell us who you are and what your question is.

 

Bryan Bishop (sp):  Yeah. Hi. Right. I’m here. I’m Bryan Bishop from the Stephen Hopkins Center for Civil Rights in Rhode Island. And I’m wondering if you view dueling traditions, which perhaps are underappreciated in comparing the Roe and Dobbs decisions because people kind of go to the substance, and the penumbra is first. I’m wondering if dueling traditions are more a distraction from the originalist project or perhaps an invitation to broader subscription to the project.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  I’m not sure I quite understand the question. Dueling --

 

Bryan Bishop:  What I’m suggesting is that if we’re debating traditions and to an extent if that comes in in looking at our legal traditions, whether that might actually interest people who think that originalism has a conservative or a right-leaning valence. They might realize that tradition doesn’t necessarily always cut that way, that maybe we should play on the originalist field and try and tease these out. Or is that rather simply an excuse to overthrow originalism?

 

Hon. Elizabeth Wydra:  So I think it’s a really interesting question, and certainly, part of what I do every day is try to convince my fellow progressives that we can and should play on the originalist field, and we can often win on that field as a substantive principled matter but also, frankly, as a strategic matter, given the makeup of the Supreme Court and many of our appellate courts across the country. One thing I think that -- you mentioned Roe and Dobbs and dueling traditions, and I think that that case and the Fourteenth Amendment cases generally are really interesting because the Fourteenth Amendment was — not to use tech bro slang — but was intended to be a constitutional disruptor. The folks who were writing the Fourteenth Amendment wrote it and thought it would be a constitutional disruptor to many different aspects of our constitutional order, that it -- they intended to turn on its head the relationship between state and federal citizenship. So instead of having state citizenship primary, they thought that this, especially with birthright citizenship provisions, etc., federal citizenship would become more important in many key ways. Similarly, disrupting a tradition of discrimination and opposition, the most obvious of which is with respect to the horrible institution of slavery, but they also considered other ways in which people had been suffering conditions of unfreedom.

 

The Thirteenth Amendment guaranteed freedom in the United States, and the Fourteenth Amendment, in many ways, answered the question, “What does it mean to be free?” And in doing so, the drafters of the Fourteenth Amendment intended to disrupt many discriminatory traditions. So when you’re going to engage in a text and history analysis of a Fourteenth Amendment provision, to me, it’s important to take into account that your traditions you look at might in way be different because the text was put into the Constitution in order to disrupt many of these traditions. So that’s something that I think is -- we talk about a lot, and I’d like to see more people talk about it. So thank you.

 

Prof. Bernadette Meyler:  Yeah. I just want to add that I think that that’s true actually even of the original Constitution. You can look at the Suspension Clause and wonder how much of it is about enshrining what came before and how about deviating from that. But I think the other point I would make is that it’s not, say, just going to Roe and Dobbs but even going back to what Judge Larsen mentioned before, the Crawford case. I think a lot of the Sixth Amendment originalism decisions have been embraced by progressives as well as some conservatives. And so, there are plenty of ways to, I think, use originalism in different political valences or for different political ends as well.

 

Hon. Britt Grant:  If you look at, for instance, the Heller decision, both opinions in that case were deeply originalist, and one, of course, got more votes than the other. But I think that’s a really good example of “both sides of a question” digging into the original sources and trying to use those to discern the meaning.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  All right. We’ll take a question over here on my left.

 

Art Macomber:  Thank you. Art Macomber, Coeur d’Alene, Idaho. My question is really for the judges, and I’m wondering about the analytical framework. I think Mr. Clement said, okay, so you state with the text, and then, you have history and tradition. So the final two are kind of a swamp, and I see that, for the Founders, they were looking backwards. And I think if you don’t start with Magna Carta and move forward, you don’t really get an understanding of how -- we look backwards and see the Constitution. They were setting it up and looking forwards, given what happened in the past.

 

And my question is this I know you have subject-matter considerations, the First Amendment obviously different than the Third Amendment. Right? History and tradition on the Third Amendment is pretty well capped. But how do you, as a judge, approach this issue? What is the analytical framework for the history and tradition swamp that you engage in — step one, step two, step three? And if you could talk a little bit about that, it would be very helpful. Thank you.

 

Hon. Britt Grant:  I think it’s interesting, again, as a circuit judge, certainly, we have occasions to look at history and tradition, but again, I think, less so than the Supreme Court. So I think, for me, sometimes it comes up in what we might think of as smaller issues. I mentioned that a little bit before, issues that are not on the front pages of the newspaper. And I think that’s where you can look back and see earlier statutes. How did -- maybe even if you’re looking at habeas corpus, right, Magna Carta, and how did it go from there? What was the original understanding of habeas corpus at the Founding? How did that impact its development as we went through the 19th and 20th centuries?

 

Even those questions, I think, can sometimes inform, say, an EDPA issue that we’re dealing with today. And so, I think, that’s not an issue where you’ll necessarily have a brief that starts with Magna Carta, but I think, once you start to dig into the text and look at things that happen with statutes and try to understand what framework, even 20 and 30 years ago, people were working within. I think that you try to look at those questions at every step of the line. So to me, originalism doesn’t start and stop around the Founding era. It’s a developing process. When you look at the developing understandings as we have statutes that have gone through their own processes and their own development, I think it really help you understand, as a judge, what that text means when you look at the text that came before it and the practices that came before it.

 

Hon. James C. Ho:  I might just lightly try to merge the premise of your question with what Elizabeth said earlier. What I said earlier was I think there was at least some sense that one way to approach this is text. That’s what we’re doing. But it can be, can be, informed by history and tradition. But as Elizabeth points out, there are times when the drafters, whether it’s a constitutional amendment or a statute or what have you, there are times when the text is pathbreaking, right, when the whole point of a text is to go in a very different direction.

 

Now, obviously, you need to figure out when those situations exist and when they don’t, and we have certain kinds of interpretation. The one against lightly assuming variations of common law would be one example where we don’t assume a pathbreaking moment, but when the text does break a path, suggest a complete departure from the past, then, history, tradition obviously, presumably, could play a different role in that situation. So it’s just a matter of figuring out which situation you’re presented with.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  All right.

 

Will Trachman:  Hi. Will Trachman from Mountain States Legal Foundation.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Yeah.

 

Will Trachman:  We don’t write on a clean slate very much, not all of us are practicing before the Supreme Court. Is there an opinion on whether litigators can use originalism when there’s already a balancing test or a tier of scrutiny at play? So to say, well, this is not a compelling interest that would have been compelling to the Framers or in the original public meaning, or this wouldn’t have been narrowly tailored to the Framers. And separately, we have a case right now, representing a student who was prohibited from wearing the Gadsden flag as a patch on his backpack, and we’re arguing under the Tinker standard. So could we say, “Well, obviously, it wouldn’t have been a substantial disruption in the 1860s to wear a Gadsden flag on your backpack?” How does originalism interact with current balancing standards?

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Yeah. That’s a great question. First of all, I don’t think you’re going to get any of the judges on this panel to opine on your case. So we’re not going to do that. But I think, as a general matter -- look, if the Supreme Court has said, “Here’s a balancing test, and you have to apply the balancing test,” the judges, for the most part, are going to apply the balancing test. And if there are cases in the circuit or coming from the Supreme Court that cash out what that balancing test looks like, I think the judges are going to be inclined to say, “Well, this is how we’ve applied this before. The cases tell us that this factor on this factor. We look at these things, and your case looks exactly like that one or looks different than that one.” I think that’s what most judges are going to do as a first line.

 

That being said, if you can make a compelling case either that there’s an alternative to the balancing test that we ought to be taking very seriously, I don’t think any of us are going to not apply the balancing test we were told to apply. But it might provoke that concurrence that says, “Hey, you should replace that with something else.” And also, I think it’s an interesting proposition to say, “We should think about how this would have balanced out at the Founding.” If you’ve got that case that you can make, I think I share Judge Ho’s perspective. Bring us the information, and we’ll see how it cashes out. Again, I don’t know about your particular case so not commenting.

 

Hon. James C. Ho:  Yeah. Look, if you think you have an originalist argument, I would make it. Absolutely. I’m reminded of what Justice Scalia often said. Justice Scalia famously was pretty categorical, if not actually categorical, about legislative history, and yet, he would repeatedly tell lawyer audiences, “If you have a legislative history argument, you absolutely should make it.” He may not take it. He may not agree with it. But some of his colleagues might. Some of the judges on other courts might.

 

And so, I would view things from a practitioner’s standpoint in that lens. If you have -- presumably, you think you have precedent on your side. You should cite the precedent. But I would always be prepared -- if nothing else, at oral argument, we also train, whether it’s me or me mooting other people in my office, have a backup argument. Have multiple arguments. You should win based on a precedent. You should win based on originalist analysis. You should win based on, frankly, policy arguments because some judges may pay attention to that.

 

Just frankly, to me — and this maybe goes back to the General’s comment about the state of legal education — is -- it just strikes me as woefully incompetent, educational malpractice, for law schools not to teach every tool in the tool book, if, in fact, your avowed object is to train legal professionals.  The problem—I think General is absolute right—is law schools aren’t doing that anymore, at least not -- maybe not -- categorical, many law schools -- certain law schools may be focused more on indoctrinating and sort of just wanting to inflict a certain sense of political change rather than doing what I thought they were doing, which is training future lawyers. And so, future -- lawyers of all kinds, including future lawyers, need to have every tool in the toolbox so that you can deploy for your clients. I would have thought that that would be uncontroversial, but apparently, that’s the controversy of the day.

 

Hon. Britt Grant:  I’ll say I think you should absolutely make originalist arguments, if you have them. And not only might it inspire concurrence, but it could inspire an “and also” in a majority opinion. There’s important scholarship from, say, Professor McConnell on how Brown v. Board wasn’t written as an originalist decision, but it certainly is very consistent with the original meaning. And so, I think all judges want to make their opinions as persuasive and rock solid as possible. And if there’re originalist arguments that point in the same direction, especially as whatever the result is of the balancing test that we’ve been instructed to use, then I think a lot of judges would be really excited to include those arguments in their opinions to fully bolster the decision.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Professor Meyler.

 

Prof. Bernadette Meyler:  Yeah. I think this is a very interesting question because a lot of recent Supreme Court cases have kind of called into question some of the tiers of scrutiny or other tests that have traditionally been applied since, say, the 1940s. And so, I think, one strategy might be to say, “Well, in Bruen, there seems to be a rejection of those kinds of tests, so maybe there’s some uncertainty about whether the Supreme Court is actually endorsing tests along these lines in other cases.” But then, also, I think there’s a counterargument about to -- maybe to the Supreme Court about rejecting these kinds of tests because I think, as Judge Ho had mentioned, there may be some evidence of the Founding about some forms of balancing. Right? If you think about Justice Marshall using a question about is it necessary or absolutely necessary -- what is the level of review.

 

And then, secondly, there is a question about how much originalism really also imports a particular method of judging. Does it include judicial practices from the Founding or not? And then, I think, third, there’s also a practical question about implementing doctrine in the lower courts, whether tests of -- balancing tests or other things are just more feasible for lower courts to implement as a routine matter. So I think there are some interesting arguments on either side.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  All right. Let’s move here to the -- my left.

 

Violet Grayson:  To what degree -- I’m Violet Grayson. I’m a practicing lawyer. And to what degree do you experience tension between originalism and textualism?

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  I’m sorry. There was just noise in the hallway. I couldn’t quite hear it.

 

Violet Grayson:  I said, “To what degree do you experience tension between originalism and textualism?”

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Oh.

 

Hon. James C. Ho:  I’ll just take a quick stab.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Yeah. Go ahead.

 

Hon. James C. Ho:  I’ve never seen any tension between the two concepts. Obviously, they’re two different words that are used. Typically, textualism is associated with statutes. Originalism is associated with the Constitution. But I don’t see them in tension. The way I have always thought about it, and this could be completely wrong, but just how I think about it is we talk textualism when it comes to statutes because statutes typically -- just read the text, and you can kind of figure out there are more words. There’s more detail. And so, you can kind of begin and end with text.

 

Whereas, constitutions, and certainly the federal Constitution, there are times when you have few words, and you need more to decide a particular dispute that’s in front of you. And so, you look behind the text to figure out, well, what do we mean. What did the Founders mean when they drafted these terms? But to me, it’s the same conversation we’ve been having earlier. We’re looking at text. If you need more than the text, you might need to be informed by things behind the text: history, tradition, dictionaries, what have you. But I think it’s all the same project. At least, that’s how I’ve always conceived of it.

 

Hon. Jason Miyares:  Yeah. I would -- kind of a different perspective. Prior to my service as Attorney General, I served in the General Assembly in the Courts of Justice Committee, and we used to always say, “We don’t vote on ideas. We vote on bills.” And it was all -- exactly to Judge Ho’s point, looking at how we were going to be changing the code, and the one thing we always stressed was there was going to be a judge, whether they’re in Fairfax or Galax, that is going to be trying to interpret how we have amended and changed the code of Virginia. And they are likely not going to have the benefit of watching what the meaning or the intent or the testimony of the patron of the legislation that’s seeking to change whatever section it is, 18.2, whatever section of the Virginia code. So I thought it was -- we always had the attitude that it was so critically important to make sure the text, the actual language -- and we argued over single dot and comma, as lawyers often do, precisely because we had the idea that a judge is going to have to read the plain language, and it needs to be crystal clear. And oftentimes, bad bills make bad law and then bad precedent.

 

Hon. Elizabeth Wydra:  And I would just add I think that’s a really interesting question because the idea with textualism is that you’re sticking to the text. Now, of course, sometimes, the text is -- needs greater context, or you can understand it better if you look to these other sources. And I normally think that that’s a great idea. One of the places where I do feel like there’s tension, however, sometimes, is when, through the originalist project, you’re using history or tradition to subvert the text or to make the words mean something perhaps other than you might think they mean based on the plain text of the constitutional provision, for example. And so, when that happens, I’m not saying it’s always wrong, but it certainly makes me pay a little bit more attention to what is actually happening in that instance. I think of this particularly with respect to the Fourteenth Amendment.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  All right.

 

Aaron Watt:  Good morning. Thank you to all the panelists for being here. My name’s Aaron Watt. I’m a 3L at Scalia Law School. I have a question about the originalist project. Someone else asked about sort of the order of operations, about starting with text. And I think back on my federal courts class about sovereign immunity. I think it’s a good example of something where it seems like we start from history and tradition, and we say we really didn’t mean to derogate from that.

 

I wonder if there are other places where it’s appropriate to start from the opposite direction as well. Are there rights that were so taken for granted up through English common law into the United States that it would be more appropriate to look to see what the foundational rights and to see if the law has derogated that? What are your thoughts?

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Is that a question about common good constitutionalism?

 

Aaron Watt:  I don’t think it is. Actually, I don’t support that perspective. But just from an originalist perspective, if what the people thought they were doing was incorporating rights, privileges, or immunities or whatever it was that they had taken for granted that existed, if that’s what the original Founders thought they were doing, is it appropriate to start from that place when evaluating just particular rights at least?

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  So maybe that’s a question about the Ninth Amendment. Maybe I’m not understanding the question. If we could take a particular constitutional provision, so the Confrontation Clause or the right to jury, as an example, so if we took the right to jury, how does that -- how does your question cash out there? Or are you asking, “Are there rights that the Founding generation would have understood to be a part of the set of natural rights,” for example, that they wanted -- that when they talked about the other rights retained by the people, that’s what they meant to enshrine? Those seem like two different questions, and I’m not quite sure which question you’re asking.

 

Aaron Watt:  Sure. And it’s hard for me to come up with a starting point in the text because, of course, then, I would have started from the text. This is part of why I wanted to --

 

[CROSSTALK]

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  And you didn’t -- the whole premise of your question is not to start with the text. Yeah.

 

Aaron Watt:  And it’s at least why I bring up sovereign immunity as an example. And so, I think about things like parental rights. Is that something that would have been taken for granted as a right? Where does that right originate from if it doesn’t originate from the text? And so, maybe my question isn’t clear enough quite to respond to, but I wanted to give you what I’ve got on it anyway.

 

Hon. James C. Ho:  I’m going to go with the fact that you’ve sort of hit sovereignty immunity twice, and I’m going to take that to be the premise of your question. And I just lightly disagree or at least offer a different take on your premise, which is to the extent you’re saying — and this is going to get nerdy really quickly — to the extent that your point is the Eleventh Amendment obviously talks about sovereign immunity in some ways but not in the broader way that we have in various settings -- diversity, which is a federal question, etc., etc. I don’t see that as anti-textual. I see that as the Eleventh Amendment reflecting drafters thinking that the Supreme Court got cases wrong. I think it’s Chisholm -- or I forget this area, now. It’s been a while since Fed Courts for me.

 

But it’s really not the text that’s doing the work, at least the text of the Eleventh Amendment. It’s the text of Article III, and the drafters, rightly or wrongly, thought, “You know what? Supreme Court, you got it wrong, so we’re going to lightly -- we’re going to overturn your case through the text of the Eleventh Amendment, but obviously, we’re restoring a broader conception of state sovereign immunity that we thought was already in Article III or perhaps the Tenth Amendment.” I think multiple Supreme Court justices have said it’s wrong to use the term, “Eleventh Amendment immunity,” other than in those cases where it’s actually about the Eleventh Amendment. It’s state sovereign immunity that preexists the Constitution and wasn’t overturned by Article III. So I might disagree with your premise and, therefore, stick with the text.

 

Hon. Elizabeth Wydra:  I think it’s hard to think of a time when you wouldn’t at least start with the text. Privileges or immunities, for example, in the Fourteenth Amendment, is a broad term, but if you look at the original public meaning, there was a very clear understanding -- at least, the general concepts that were included. Now, whether it’s the Corfield v. Coryell list of rights, whether it was the first ten amendments plus -- you look at the debates, and you can see that the -- you mentioned parental rights -- that the right to form a family was included in those ideas of privileges or immunities. So I think it would always be right to start with the text because there’s a reason why they used privileges or immunities as opposed to some other term of relating to rights or liberties.

 

Prof. Bernadette Meyler:  I think it’s an interesting question because even if you look at Article III, there isn’t an explicit provision for state sovereign immunity in Article III. Right? So you’re implying something into the text, and I think that I would go back to Judge Larsen’s comment about the Ninth Amendment, or even the Tenth Amendment, that there are these provisions of the Constitution that are fairly broadly phrased and that do imply invocation of some forms of structure or rights that were preceding the Constitution. And so, figuring out which provisions are against that backdrop and which aren’t is one of the, I think, tasks of interpretation, even if you’re starting with the text.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  All right. We have time for just a couple more questions, so let’s take one over here on the left.

 

Clarke Forsythe:  Clarke Forsythe, Americans United for Life. If the focus of originalism is the ratified text, which, if any, outside voices are relevant to the ratified text?

 

Hon. Britt Grant:  I think it depends on what you’re using them for. I’ll be interested to hear from our scholars to my left, but I think voices are not -- I don’t think that any voices are appropriately used to override the text. But to the extent that we can use different voices to better understand the text, then I think a lot of the comments from, really, all the panelists today have indicated that we can take those into account. I think Paul Clement had a lot of arguments about whether we should allow private voices to override public understandings, and I think that those questions are interesting. But I think, as long as we’re using them for the right reasons and placing them in the proper context, I think you can certainly consider and then put within the overall framework -- we’re happy to hear, I think, about a lot of voices and then give them whatever meaning they have, in terms of helping us understand the text, but not override the text.

 

Prof. Bernadette Meyler:  Yeah. I would say that, in my view, looking at the participants and debates, right, so a lot of these kinds of rights or provisions were subject of different debates or might have been subject to different laws in different colonies. So looking at the structure of those debates, I think, is particularly informative in understanding what the text means.

 

Hon. Elizabeth Wydra:  Yeah. When you’re looking at an original public meaning analysis, which is the dominant form of originalist analysis after you look at the text, then, of course, you are going to include voices other than just those who were the ratifiers because they are included in the public. But yes, obviously, it implies some level of publicity. So Paul’s private diary, I don’t think, would count unless excerpts of that diary were published à la Federalist Papers and distributed to the public. But we look at newspapers. We look at convention debates. And certainly, when I think about my particular area of expertise in the Reconstruction Amendments, there were a lot of these public conventions and debates. And so, there is really a rich history to be looked at there. And I think that as we get even more scholarship and have more sources, public sources, then that will be a really interesting rich debate.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Okay. We are very close to being out of time, but there are only two speakers at the mic, and I just -- I have such a benevolent heart. So I can’t just cut one of you off, so it’s the lightning round, quick question, and we’ll give you each a quick answer. And then, we’ll adjourn.

 

Gabrielle:  Well, thank you. I really appreciate the love and benevolence. My name is Gabrielle. I’m a third-year law student from University of Miami. And all I wanted to ask touches upon what Miyares has said about the hatred of originalism in law school, and he’s absolutely right. And I ask this question because I think it extends from this very formulaic argument that they produce that because the Founders were wrong — at least in so far as who was afforded certain substantive rights — or that history was wrong for a period of time, that they must be wrong about the actual interpretation or meaning or scope of the actual substantive rights themselves, so we should just do away with anything they thought of entirely.

 

And of course, that ignores the beautiful design of our Founding document that, when we do extend rights to all human beings, we don’t have to do away with the whole document, and we have the most successful governance experiment of all time. So my question is how do we respond to this vitriol from the other side? Just because we have historical mistakes, it doesn’t mean that we should dispose of this.

 

Hon. Jason Miyares:  Well, this is what I would say. This idea that the greatest critique of originalism is we got to ignore the dead hand of the past, and as I had one intern tell me that the general sentiment from some of their law professors is why would we want to study dead white men? And I think it takes away the richness of the basic of the Founding where if you look at James Madison, he was obsessed with two things: both anarchy and monarchy. And so, how do we frame a government in such a way that can respect both the rights of the individual and the face and the passions of the mob but also make sure that part -- that power is devolved. And I think the other thing it takes away, which I think law students often are not taught, is just how obsessed Madison was going to the Constitution Convention on why democracy fails. He spent so much time looking at both Ancient Greece and Ancient Rome on what caused them to fall, not just forming the government. How do we create a system of governing that absolutely can self-perpetuate itself? And I thought that is greatly missing.

 

And it is the first written constitution in all of human history that actually limits what government can do and empowers the individual. It’s never happened in all of recorded history. And the other thing that makes me is a sense that we got to ignore a dead white man, and it’s not quite applicable, but my -- people ask me, “What kind of name is Miyares?” I say, “Well, it’s southern.” My family fled Cuba, and my uncle, Angel Miyares, when he was arrested in Cuba and he went through the humiliation of a mock execution, one of the things that he appealed to was, “You have no right to do this because I have certain unalienable rights of life and liberty.” In other words, he was appealing towards something that was a university principle laid, of course, by our Founders. Obviously, the Declaration of Independence is kind of the birth certificate later on for the Bills of Rights. So I think it is a passionate need to expose the fact that these university principles that have been appealed to to man’s better nature in every gulag, whether they’re in North Korea or Cuba or in Russia, and the universality of it that applies to all races and creeds.

 

And the point that I make is -- and when Dr. King made his speech at the Lincoln Memorial, he didn’t appeal to Rousseau. Right? He said he was there to collect a promissory note made to every single American — past, present, and future — of life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness. He didn’t appeal to Confucius. He didn’t appeal to Rousseau. And if you look at simply -- when Dr. King taught at Morehouse College, do you know what he taught? Philosophy. Do you know what he assigned to his students? The greatest thinkers of Western Civilization. Look at the curriculum that Dr. King picked out and taught in his philosophy class at Morehouse College, and I think you should point to that, that there is a universal principle here that is oftentimes ignored and to tragic consequences on our college campuses, tragic consequences.

 

Gabrielle:  Thank you.

 

[Applause]

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Okay. So I hope you have a good one to take us out on.

 

Connor:  To quickly piggyback off of that question as well, my name’s Connor. I’m the President of the Student Chapter at William and Mary Law. What can students and young attorneys do to help circumvent that censorship on college campuses and in hiring practices? Many of us feel as if we have to choose between self-censorship and professional and even social suicide. So what can we do to bring in the next generation of originalist thinkers because I think a lot of us believe that we’re being -- we’re losing that platform. We exist, but the platform itself is shrinking and disappearing.

 

Hon. Jason Miyares:  I would just say real quick. Alumni should withhold their donations to their alma mater until they commit to ideological diversity, number one. [Applause] And I think -- and I do think that their -- and I’m a proud alumni of that same Federalist Society chapter at William and Mary. C.S. Lewis has a great line where he says, “The beginning of friendship is when you turn to somebody and say, ‘Oh, you too?’ I thought I was the only one.” Right? So I think there is both a power of the organizations like Federalist Society and others for people that have this originalist worldview to realize they’re not alone. And I think that’s critically important as well is to build up, continuing these different organizations that can foster and encourage the next generation.

 

Hon. Britt Grant:  I’ll say this: have debates in The Federalist Society. That’s, I think, one of the most fundamental principles of The Federalist Society is that there are important issues. Let’s hear both sides of them. If you’re not getting the originalist side at -- from the academics at your law school, have a debate. Invite people in. Let students hear. And I think more students will be persuaded, and they can feel like they can sneak in if they think the right side is also being represented. And maybe they’ll hear a different view and start to think about it more carefully.

 

Hon. Joan Larsen:  Okay. We are a little bit overtime, but I have to read you some things that I was told I must read. So I’m going to do it, and then, you can thank our terrific panel. So if you are pursuing CLE, we’d like to remind you to make sure you sign in and sign out once per day. If you did not sign in ahead of this panel, please do so now via the QR code in the program and also available at registration. Additionally, we would like to remind you of the Remnant Trust’s Rare Documents Exhibit located on the second floor in the South Carolina Room. You can access the second floor using the elevators located next to check-in. If you are ever need -- in need of coffee or a power strip to charge your phone or your laptop or your iPad, I suppose, throughout the day, these are located at the Mezzanine Level, accessible by the front elevators. There are no panels directly following this one, so we’d like to announce that lunch will be served shortly in the main hallway. Thank you very much. We are adjourned.

 

 

 

 

11:30 a.m. - 1:30 p.m.
Hyperextension? Federal Financial Agencies & Cryptocurrency Regulation

2023 National Lawyers Convention

Topics: Financial Services • Cryptocurrency
District Room
The Mayflower Hotel
1127 Connecticut Avenue NW
Washington, DC 20006

Share

Event Video

Listen & Download

Description

In recent years federal executive branch agencies have enacted a “whole of government” approach to hot-button topics like environmental, social, governance (ESG) and cryptocurrency regulation. This theory of policy administration combines the efforts of multiple executive branch agencies with different expertise and authorities toward achieving a singular objective.

Some of the agencies marshaled to address cryptocurrency regulation include the Securities and Exchange Commission (SEC), the Commodity Futures Trading Commission (CFTC), the Treasury Department’s Financial Crimes Enforcement Network (FinCEN), and the banking regulators. Jurisdiction is often complicated by the nature of a particular asset, administration changes, and agency leaders’ personalities and priorities.

How does current cryptocurrency regulatory policy align with the statutory authority and original purpose of these agencies? Are the agencies fulfilling legislative mandates to protect investors and promote safety and soundness? Or are they stretching their authority to achieve a policy outcome in the absence of legislative authorization?

This panel will examine the issue of cryptocurrency regulation and statutory authority of executive agencies.

Featuring:

  • Mr. Brian P. Brooks, Partner, O’Melveny & Myers; Former Acting Comptroller of the Currency
  • Prof. Chris Brummer, Agnes Williams Sesquicentennial Professor of Financial Technology, Georgetown Law
  • Ms. Caitlin Long, Founder & CEO, Custodia Bank
  • Prof. Christopher L. Peterson, John J. Flynn Endowed Professor of Law, University of Utah S.J. Quinney College of Law
  • Moderator: Hon. Patrick J. Bumatay, United States Court of Appeals, Ninth Circuit

Speakers

Event Transcript

Paul N. Watkins:  …Financial Services and E-Commerce practice group. We’re very excited about the panel that we have today. Before we get started, I want to mention an important housekeeping point. If you want CLE—and I assume you all want CLE—there are QR codes on your program, outside this door, in the main lobby. You need to scan those in the morning and then when you leave in the afternoon so that you get credit.

      This panel is sponsored by the Financial Services practice group. We now have a great webpage on the FedSoc site, where you can track all the events, all the webinars and articles and everything that the group handles. If you have ideas, please come speak to Nate. Speak to myself. We want to be targeting the issues that are most important for your practice and the issues that you’re seeing.

      Now, we’re pleased to have a fantastic moderator and panel, and it’s my privilege to introduce one of the most principled and hardest-working jurists in America today, the Honorable Patrick Bumatay.

      Judge Bumatay, after law school, began his legal career clerking for Judge Tymkovich on the Tenth Circuit. He then served in a number of senior and high-profile roles in the Department of Justice and finally served as an Assistant U.S. Attorney before being confirmed to the Ninth Circuit’s Court of Appeals in 2019. So, Judge, please take it away.

[Applause]

Hon. Patrick J. Bumatay:  Thank you. Thank you, Paul, for that introduction. We’ve been friends since our 1L year of law school. I think it’s safe to say that no one expected either of us to be on this stage today. So thank you for that introduction, and thank you for the invitation to be moderating this panel. And I think it’s a really important one as well.

It’s called “Hyperextension? Federal Financial Agencies and Cryptocurrency Regulation.” I think it’s safe to say that this is a new frontier of regulation. And I could speak for most judges in saying that our concept of ideas, like cryptocurrency, blockchain, and the like, is rudimentary at best. So one of the challenges I see when considering regulation in this space is educating the judiciary, and that’s only after there’s some consensus on what regulation we want. That’s why panels like this are so necessary.

So now, I’ll introduce our panelists. Our first speaker is Brian Brooks, a Partner at O’Melveny & Myers in Los Angeles and here in D.C. Mr. Brooks has had an interesting career on multiple sides of this issue. He’s been CEO of Bitfury Group and Binance.US. He was also Chief Legal Officer at Coinbase. In addition, he served as the Acting Comptroller of the Currency during the Trump administration.

Next, we’ll have Caitlin Long, Founder and CEO of Custodia Bank. Ms. Long has been a self-described “Bitcoin evangelist” since 2012. She’s also had a 22-year career on Wall Street and has served on Wyoming’s Blockchain Task Force. She’s going to talk about some interesting litigation going on between Custodia Bank and the Federal Reserve.

And finally, we will have Professor Christopher Peterson of the University of Utah College of Law. Professor Peterson was in the leadership at the Consumer Financial Product Protection Bureau during the Obama administration. He’s extensively researched the FDIC and the Federal Reserve. And in 2020, Professor Peterson ran for governor of the great state of Utah.

So before we get to Q&A, each panelist will now give their opening remarks. Brian, do you want to kick us off?

Brian P. Brooks:  Is that a question? I’m not sure if I want to kick us. Thank you for the introduction, and thanks everybody for being here. It’s a great time to have this conversation, I think. We’re having this conversation during the Supreme Court term where the future of Chevron will be decided. We are having this conversation at a time when the role and discretion of the banking agencies through Caitlin’s lawsuit is being decided. And these are really fundamental issues. So I think it’s going to be a great conversation.

I want to talk about a couple things here just to kind of introduce the topic, and then I think we’re going to have some great debate among the panelists. So the first thing I want to talk about a little bit is what crypto is and why it matters. I’m not going to presume a high level of knowledge—let alone enthusiasm—among this group, but I think I’m going to convince you that it’s a little bit different than what you think. And then I want to orient you to our administration’s approach to crypto regulation, which is I think it’s safe to say it’s not just different from, it’s literally the opposite of the approach of this administration. And you can make your own judgments about who you agree with, but it’s important to understand the paradigms.

So let me start with the concept of what crypto is. Crypto, I believe, is a species of one of the two macro forces that are reshaping the delivery of financial services globally and ultimately reshaping the financial system. So I’ve written pretty extensively about the idea that the two macro forces changing the way financial services are delivered are unbundling and decentralization. Let me just talk for 30 seconds about what I mean by both of those things.

So historically, in the United States, at least in the twentieth century and today, the concept of financial services revolved around the simultaneous delivery of three different services. And those services are deposit taking, payment processing, and lending. And there was a belief for a long time that the only way to deliver financial service was to have all three of those things sitting in the same place.

So, if you think about it, the only really efficient way to make loans is to have a pool of low-cost capital where you can earn a spread between the cost of raising the capital and the income derived by lending out the capital at a higher rate of interest. And so that is thought to mean that you can’t really be an effective lender unless you are also a deposit taker. And incidental to deposit taking is payment processing. After all, if you want to pay your cable bill, there has to be money on deposit somewhere that you can use to remit that payment. And thus, we came up with this concept of what was colloquially known in the twentieth century as the money center. And the biggest banks were called money center banks.

Technology arose—called the internet—which meant that some of those assumptions may no longer be true. They may have been vestiges of an era when centralization was necessary, and centralization may no longer be necessary. And the analogy that many people talk about in crypto is the post office analogy. So once upon a time, if you wanted to communicate with a person far, far away, you had to have a centralized aggregator of those communications. That’s what the post office was. So you would take all your letters on a Monday morning. Some were going to Salt Lake City and some were going to Miami and some to Utah. But you’d put them at one place, and the post office would then aggregate all the letters to Miami in one slot, and all the letters to Utah in another slot, and it would then farm them back out and deliver them.

With the rise of the internet, the concept of centralization no longer mattered. I can now send an email directly to you, and it does not have to go through a central repository. We can have node-based networks, and we no longer need the post office the way that we once did. And the metaphor for banking is very similar to that. It may be in an internet world that I no longer need to raise deposits in order to make loans. I can have peer-to-peer lending networks where in real time I can find a source of funds for my loans that way. So unbundling is a general feature of internet technology that is changing financial services.

The other feature—and this is where crypto comes in—the other feature, the other macro event that changes financial services, is decentralization. So, if you think about the way centralization works in the traditional financial system, the idea is that in addition to bundling all these services I talked about, you have a management team, and the management team is making decisions about which loans to make, which customers to onboard, which products and services to offer.

And this is why at a bank you’ll have a credit committee that at one bank might be willing to make oil and gas loans, and at another bank, they’re not willing to make oil and gas loans. One company might be long on commercial real estate, and another might make residential mortgages. But they’re making discretionary judgments on that basis. And there are advantages to that, right? There are also disadvantages, which is human beings make mistakes.

And when you have a centralized system of decision making, you can have a credit committee that doesn’t recognize changes in the interest rate curve or that perhaps is very bullish on a sector that is ultimately going to fail but they nonetheless invest in that sector and make mistakes. Another technology development has created unbundling, and that technology development is called blockchain, okay?

The concept of a blockchain is the idea of a network that is -- has distributed ownership and control where there is no one person making decisions and no one person can decide, for example, to turn off your bank account or to suspend your ability to take credit or to make payments. But to have a decentralized network, somebody has to be induced to contribute the computing power to the network.

So in the original internet, which is a centrally managed thing, you had big companies like Google and Facebook delivering the computing power to make the network function. If you’re going to have a decentralized network do things like I’ve just described, then somebody has to get paid. And the way they get paid is through cryptocurrencies.

And so when you hear people talk about tokens—whether it’s Bitcoin or Ethereum or some of these other tokens that you hear people talk about—the original concept behind those tokens was, if you think about Bitcoin as the very first one, the idea was bitcoin is the reward that you get for helping to maintain the network. It’s as simple as that. And that’s true across lots of other blockchains as well. Now, we won’t get into the complexities of the different layers of blockchains, but just think about cryptocurrencies as your reward for helping to support a decentralized network.

It turns out there are a lot of reasons that decentralization matters. My favorite example is if you think back to the famous Canadian trucker protest over the COVID lockdowns back in whatever year that was—I’ve tried to put the COVID lockdowns out of my mind so I purposely don’t remember the year.

One of the things that happened during the COVID lockdowns in Canada was when the truckers protested the need to show COVID tests every time they crossed the border with their haul was that their bank accounts were turned off. And if you think about the idea of what money is about and what banking is supposed to be about, this was money that these people had earned from work. They had paid taxes on it, and they’d simply deposit it in a bank for future use.

And one day, the government decided that their political views were so outrageous that their bank account should be turned off, and they shouldn’t be able to have lunch. They should be literally starved out of their protest. And that is something that can only be accomplished in a centralized system, right? You need command and control to do something like take somebody’s money away from them.

That really energized the crypto community because one of the things about decentralized systems is nobody can control it. So there is no government who can tell you that your next bitcoin send/receive transaction will be turned off. And that’s one of the social urgencies of decentralization—one of the reasons why so much interest exists in this asset class is for people who believe in civil liberty. Decentralized systems are thought to be superior on balance to centralized systems. You don’t have to believe any of that, but that is what the people who live in this world and act in this industry really believe.

So let me now make my comments about our regulatory approach to this activity, okay? So you have these tokens that are basically maintenance rewards for these underlying networks. These underlying networks, you may use them, you may not use them, but there’s no arguing that on a given day, the market cap of this sector is well north of a trillion dollars. The number of participants in this country alone is well north of 50 million people. So there is a nontrivial market for this asset class. You may not own this, but many of your friends and neighbors do. And they have a thesis for why they own it, much as you might have a thesis for why you own the stocks and bonds that you own.

And so, in our administration when I was comptroller, we had a thesis that these assets were new; they were relatively risky, but there was a growing market for them. And our belief was that the purpose of the regulated financial system was to provide a framework for risk management.

So we looked at these relatively risky activities, and we asked ourselves, “How can we provide supervision, licensing, custody, and other financial infrastructure to allow these assets to grow and gain market acceptance or not but to do it in a way that is predictable, stable, and safe?” And so we issued several pieces of guidance on this.

The first piece of guidance that we issued was guidance in the summer of 2020 that said that national banks have the legal authority to custody crypto assets. And our theory of this was that we looked back at the history of bank custody powers, and we found that over a long period of time, banks had been authorized to custody, not only specie—not only gold and silver coin back in the day—but also more exotic assets, like fine wine held for investment, art held for investment, digital security tokens in the traditional environment, digital stock certificates, things like those. And we saw no difference between bitcoin and fine wine.

These are noncash, high-value assets, and banks have long expertise in building safety and security around the custody process for those things. And we believe that the industry would be safer if we allowed banks, as opposed to nonbanks, to custody crypto assets.

Now, an interesting thing happened that day. I was just looking at this just a couple of days ago. One hour after we issued guidance saying something as simple as banks can custody crypto assets, the price of bitcoin jumped more than 30 percent, and it stayed elevated at that level for 9 or 10 weeks thereafter. So it tells you something about the idea that the market is so unclear that the regulatory framework for crypto is so uncertain that any point of light creates a 30 percent price jump. It’s bananas, but that is the case.

So fast forward. We then looked at the next issue in crypto, which has to do with a certain kind of crypto asset called a stablecoin. This is a blockchain native token that conveys price stable value, usually dollar equivalent. So you might think of a stablecoin as the modern day equivalent of a prepaid debit card, okay? It’s not cash. It’s a piece of electronic collateral, but it’s like an internet version of a prepaid card. And we said something very simple.

We said, “Banks are authorized to hold the reserve assets that back stablecoins.” So, if you’re going to issue 10 stablecoins worth a dollar, you have to have $10 on deposit in the bank. And again, our view was, “Well, banks used to support American Express travelers’ checks, and banks support the Bed Bath & Beyond card.” Okay, that’s probably a bad example. [Laughter] But it also supported a lot of non-bankrupt prepaid cards.

So our theory was, “Backing these kinds of prepaid assets is something banks have a long history of doing. It’s part of their legal authority in the payments authorization. So banks are allowed to do that.” And again, within about a week of us doing that, the velocity of the largest stablecoin projects increased 50 percent. I mean, just very simple regulatory clarity created massive market activity to the good of the holders.

We had a few more pieces of guidance like that. And at the end of my term, the term sort of was capped with my granting the first crypto bank charter. Now, if Caitlin had come in for a national bank charter, she might have been having this conversation. But we chartered a bank called Anchorage Digital Bank, which was a custody-only trust bank. But it was the first crypto business that was allowed inside of the national banking system. And again, a lot of good, positive market activity followed from that. And then our administration came to the end of the term.

On the first day of the Biden administration, a number of things that I did were repealed. So that’s how I knew I was really provocative, as I was a first-day repealer. Some people’s things didn’t get repealed for a week or two. But I had some things repealed on the very first day.

And at a certain point, the administration came out and took a position which they are now taking today, which is, right as we may have been legally—and the Biden administration did put out guidance saying grudgingly that they agreed with our legal analysis—but they decided nonetheless that even though banks have these legal powers, crypto was, A, just too risky, and, B, just not useful enough to be allowed in the banking system. And so they took risky activity that was being managed inside the system in our administration and pushed it outside the system.

So I’ll leave you with this question, and then I’ll turn it over to Caitlin or whoever the next speaker is. But I’ll leave you with this question. The core philosophical difference between the Trump administration and the Biden administration on crypto is, do you believe the purpose of the bank charter is to keep risky activity outside of banks because we’re here to protect banks, or do you believe the purpose of the bank charter is to take risky financial activity and bring it inside of a supervised system with capital liquidity and risk management requirements so that the kind of financial intermediation that wealth creation demands can be overseen in some safe and sound way? Our philosophy was the latter. This administration’s philosophy is the former. You decide.

Hon. Patrick J. Bumatay:  Thank you. Ms. Long?

Caitlin Long:  Thank you, Judge. I’ll give some background on what brought me into this industry because I think it might help folks who are wondering, “What’s the big deal with digital assets?”

When I was running the pension solutions business at Morgan Stanley in New York, I kept running into the morass of settlement in the financial system. And it is a place where there are a lot of nefarious activities. It is a place where mom and pops’ pockets are being picked regularly, and it is a place where we have the technology to settle the settlement problem. And what am I referring to by the settlement problem?

It’s why securities transactions settle two days after the trade date. It’s why payments, the ACH payment system, is one to three days. If you are settling Fedwire, you can settle same day, but you can’t program your payment to settle at a particular minute or settle something where, say, you have a securities transaction and you’re sending a Fedwire, those two things settle at the same time.

And as a result of that gap in settlement between one -- leg one and leg two of any financial transaction, there is an enormous amount of counterparty credit risk that is in the financial system. If we step back and think about how that evolved in the middle of the last century—actually, in the middle of the nineteenth century—we were able to communicate transcontinentally through simple data structures like Morse code. But that meant that the financial data leg of a transaction could move at the speed of light.

But the money lag -- back then, money was gold. Gold could only move at the speed of matter. And that gap between moving data at the speed of light and moving money at the speed of matter is what created all of this counterparty credit risk. And as a result of that, the financial system created layers of abstraction. “Well, let’s abstract the physical gold and have a piece of paper that’s redeemable for the IOU. Well, then let’s actually put pieces of paper redeemable for those pieces of paper on top of it.”

And eventually, what ended up happening is the dollar itself, under all that pressure to create credit, became an IOU itself. Go look at the money in your wallet. It is an IOU of the Federal Reserve Bank. It didn’t used to be. We eventually, as a result of all of this pressure—which again, stems from the fundamental gap between moving data at the speed of light and moving money at the speed of matter—we lost money in the sense that we lost control of it. Money itself became credit.

And as a result of that, the U.S. economy ultimately decoupled from what it was up until the late 1960s, which was an equity-financed economy to now a debt-financed economy and one that is fundamentally unstable. So I set about trying to fix the settlement problem that I saw on Wall Street.

I saw a lot of nefarious things, especially in the securities lending business. I also got involved with moving multibillion dollar payments between two nonbanks where we had to get the Federal Reserve involved. And it just made no sense to me that this is how the system worked. So those are the fundamental problems.

Ultimately, all the abstractions that created these layers—and we lawyers had to deal -- by the way, I’m not a practicing attorney, but I did go to law school—the layers of abstraction and all of the legal gymnastics that had to be created in order to solve for that settlement mismatch—and I’m referring to U.C.C Article 8 for those of you who are financial services specialists—we wouldn’t need that if transaction data and money settled at the same time or if securities and money could settle at the same time. But what we need to be able to do that is programmability of money. And that is what bitcoin brings us, and that is what stablecoins bring us for U.S. dollars.

Now, the second point is, what is the role of the states in what I’m just describing? Those of you who are familiar with the history of banking may understand that banks in the United States have always been chartered by the states. It wasn’t until the Civil War era that the National Bank Act of 1863 created the Federal Chartering Authority that Brian was the acting comptroller of the OCC, where we now have what’s called a dual-banking system. National banks and state chartered banks that have exactly the same rights.

If you fast forward, two utilities were created to service the banking system. One was the Federal Reserve in 1913, which runs the payment system, and the other was the FDIC, which is the insurance company for the industry. And they were both created by Congress to service the entire industry as utilities.

There were multiple reforms of the Federal Reserve in history, but one meaningful one happened in 1980. And it was back when Paul Volcker was trying to get control of the inflation of the 1970s. And member banks were disadvantaged. Fed-member banks were disadvantaged because they had to park reserves at the Fed, but the Fed wasn’t, at that time, paying interest on those reserves.

And in a high inflation, high interest rate environment, the cost of capital was so high that member banks were fleeing the Federal Reserve System. And that made his job coming in as the chairman of the Fed in 1980 even harder because, if you studied economics in school, you understand—especially back then, where credit was created almost exclusively in the banking system—you understood that the banks took a dollar of the monetary base and multiplied it to become roughly $10 of M2.

Well, if that process was happening outside of the control of the Fed, it was much harder for Volcker to get control of inflation. So what did he do? He literally begged Congress to pass the Monetary Control Act of 1980, to treat all depository institutions on an equal playing field, and require every depository institution in the United States to hold their reserves at the Fed so that they were all inside the system. And all this credit creation that was happening outside the system was something that he could get control over.

So the bargain that the Fed made was that all depository institutions were required to hold reserves at the Fed, and the Federal Reserve was required to service all depository institutions. And I won’t go into the details of what is an eligible depository institution, but for purposes of this discussion, you can assume that it is a validly chartered state chartered bank or a validly chartered OCC bank that holds a national charter.

What has happened in the ensuing decades is that states have started to charter banks that the Fed has viewed as nontraditional. And what is interesting about that is that it’s an eclectic group of states dating back to the real estate crisis of the late 1980s. A few northeastern states created uninsured state bank charters. And then after the FDIC refused to provide insurance for any bank servicing the digital asset industry that was a startup, a few other states—Wyoming and Nebraska—chartered a new type of bank, also uninsured. And then most recently the state of Idaho, which has a state’s banking statute that doesn’t require its banks to be insured, started to charter payment banks that are uninsured banks.

So now, you have six U.S. states and potentially many more—everybody’s watching this—who are trying to figure out, “All right. Did the Monetary Control Act actually mean what it said, that all depository institutions had access to the Federal Reserve System?” If you step back and think about the statute, it’s 12 U.S.C. § 248(a). The statute that says the Federal Reserve -- literally all eligible depository institutions had to hold their reserves at the Federal Reserve. And now, you see states saying, “Well, some of these payment innovators, the FDIC won’t insure them. So now what?”

What’s also interesting about innovation in financial services is if you think about the mission statements of federal financial regulators, I’m not aware of a single one of them—whether it was the OCC, the FDIC, the SEC—that has economic development or innovation within their remit. In fact, their incentive as agencies is to block innovation.

However, the states almost always have economic development in their remit. So what is the practical implication of that? The practical implication is that the states are the laboratories of democracy, and the innovations bubble up from the states. But what we started to see under the Obama administration under Operation Choke Point 1.0 is the federal banking regulator—in that case, the FDIC—started to pick and choose which industries got to have banking services.

And we subsequently started to see the Federal Reserve start to block applications from validly chartered, state chartered banks for Federal Reserve master accounts. So the impact of this is that there’s been a centralization of power in the banking industry in Washington, D.C., that is trying to override the dual banking system and the ability of states to charter their own banks.

They’re now in Washington, DC, going through what is effectively a veto process where federal banking agencies are asserting jurisdiction that they do not have over whether states have the right to charter banks. And that is the impetus for our lawsuit. Our lawsuit, of course, is not something I can talk about. I respect the process and it is subject to a protective order.

The fundamental question it comes down to has nothing to do with crypto. I’m interested in using crypto as a technology to solve that settlement problem. The fundamental question of the lawsuit is, “Does the Federal Reserve have the right to veto a state’s bank chartering authority?” I’ll leave it at that.

Hon. Patrick J. Bumatay:  Thank you. Professor Peterson?

Prof. Christopher L. Peterson:  Well, hi, everybody. Thank you. First, I want to say thank you, Judge, for agreeing to host the panel. It’s kind of cool to be on a panel where there’s a United States Court of Appeals judge that’s moderating it and also with a comptroller of the currency and a bank CEO. I’m just a public school teacher from Utah, and I’m pretty much the least fancy speaker in the entire conference program. So it’s an honor to be here. I do want to thank also Sam Fendler, who did the logistics on our panel really efficiently and the audiovisual people that are working back there and all the servers at the hotel that are taking care of us.

I’m the token liberal on the panel, but it’s an honor to do that, I think, because I believe in civil discourse and reasoned debate and a civil society that has a competition and ideas and tries to find a pathway forward for our republic in a way that’s constructive. And I guess I’m also, in addition to being the token liberal, I’m also the token crypto skeptic, I think, in the panel.

I want to start out with a confession, and I don’t know why this happened. When cryptocurrency first came about, I was a little bit skeptical to begin with but open to the ideas. I really like complicated rule systems. I teach constitutional law. I teach contracts, but I also teach commercial law. And it’s my favorite class to teach by far because Article 9 of the Uniform Commercial Code is so complicated and intricate.

It’s a beautiful creation of human ingenuity. And there was a part of me that thought, “You know what? Cryptocurrency is going to be kind of like that, too. Payment systems and the settlement problem, that’s a real problem.” It would be cool if we had some way to fix that.

But before too long, the more I heard about what was happening and the problems with it, eventually, in my mind, probably about three or four or five years ago, anytime anybody ever said the words “crypto,” in my mind, I would try to be polite and smile. And I don’t want to offend anybody, but remember, this is the -- we don’t do cancel culture. So I’m going to say something that’s a little bit edgy.

But whenever I hear the word “crypto assets,” in my mind, I hear the words “magic beans” because I’m not really convinced that there’s a lot of value add to these financial instruments or these distributed ledger products, non-fungible tokens, etc. And so I could be wrong about that.

I mean, there’s still the potential that this will somehow revolutionize, and there’s going to be some value there. But they’re not farming. They’re not feeding anybody. They’re not transporting goods. They’re not manufacturing goods. They’re just making up new, different types of crypto assets that are all -- distributed ledgers, I get that. We’ll talk about that in a little bit.

But the other problem with them is that there are lots and lots of law and order scandals that keep happening over and over and over in this sector of the economy. And if you think I’m being too uncollegial or uncivil by using the term “magic beans” to describe all of it all, let me just go through a couple of scandals, and maybe you’ll feel better about me.

First off, I’m going to start with one called—and I’m not making this up, and it also happened after I came to call it magic beans—it’s a company called Beanstalk Farms. I didn’t make that up. That was what they called themselves. It’s a DeFi or decentralized finance governance protocol that would allow people who own the assets to vote to change the code, which is, “Oh, it’s decentralized,” so you could change the software code.

If you own some assets for Beanstalk Farms, then you can vote to change the software code. But they also had flash loans that would allow you to borrow assets, probably for whatever complicated hedging strategy you had or whatever. And so you could borrow assets and then give them back really quickly. So some entrepreneurial person borrowed a whole bunch of assets in a flash loan that got them just enough to actually be able to change the code. And then they changed the code to allow them to steal about $182 million of crypto assets.

Magic beans were what Beanstalk Farms was selling, it turned out. Axie Infinity is a second example. Axie Infinity is a video game where you can make crypto assets, get paid crypto assets. It’s a pay-to-earn game, they call it, and it’s on something called the Ronin network. And so, all around the world, apparently, it was particularly used a lot in Southeast Asia, but here in the States, too, people were playing this video game because they’re getting paid in crypto assets. I gather it was a mediocre video game. I don’t know. I never played it.

But they’re making all this crypto, these crisp assets playing video games. And the North Koreans came in and hacked it and stole all of the assets. The North Korean government has a crypto hacking operation and stole -- it was 597 million in crypto assets, including $25 million in a USDC, which is a stablecoin pegged to the value of the U.S. dollar.

And then a third example, [Wintermute]. They were a vanity address company. In a crypto asset, you’ve got a private key or a private account, which is usually just a bunch of letters and numbers and gibberish. It’s not very fun to talk about. And so this company would save your private key but then give you, on top of that later on, a vanity address that would be like “Crypto Bro 99” or something like that. It’s just a joke; don’t be mad. Anyway, it had a bunch of security problems, and so somebody came in and hacked it. And people lost $160 million in crypto assets through this hole that it had introduced in people’s private keys.

Fourth example, Terra’s algorithmic stablecoin. So this is another stablecoin that was pegged to the U.S. dollar, but they didn’t -- they weren’t holding dollar-for-dollar assets. They had an algorithm that was sort of giving -- suggesting that they had sufficient assets to back the stablecoin. But it turns out, of course, they didn’t, and that collapsed.

And hard to judge how -- what the loss in value was. I’d read something that said $60 billion, which seems high to me, but I don’t know. It’s a massive loss where they were representing themselves as having -- that one of their crypto assets had the same value as the United States legal tender did, and they were representing that they had figured out a way to guarantee that they were going to have reserves sufficient to cover those losses, which proved to be utterly false.

And then another example, this one’s not that -- I just got to put it in there because it’s the guy’s name. This guy’s name was -- it is -- and I’ve never met him. I’m sure he’s a lovely guy. I don’t mean to pick on his name. But his name is Shady Mashinsky.

[Laughter]

Prof. Christopher L. Peterson:  That’s great; it’s fantastic. He operated Celsius, which was a crypto lender. But really, what he had was a crypto asset Ponzi scheme, where he -- they were getting investments and then having big returns. And then, of course, he was paying the new people with -- sorry, the old investors with the new people’s crypto assets, and it was just a typical Ponzi scheme.

And people lost over a billion dollars in assets to Shady Machinsky’s crypto lending. [Laughter] I’m sorry. And I haven’t even got to FTX, which was the biggest one. Sam Bankman-Fried just got convicted of fraud, apparently, and billions of dollars in assets.

I’m going to mention one more because I know I’m going on too long. It’s a company that you probably haven’t heard of. It’s called the Nomad Chain Bridge. It’s a cross-chain bridge. The idea is you have different assets on different blockchains.

So maybe you’ve got some Ethereum, and you want to buy—I don’t know—Dogecoin or Moonbeam or whatever, but you don’t want to change it into dollars with your wallet because that might be -- there might be a “know-your-customer” verification there. They might see that you might be committing tax fraud, or maybe you’re trying to launder assets, or maybe you just don’t like dollars and you want crypto. That’s fine, too, maybe. But they would port from one blockchain to the other using smart contracts on the Ethereum blockchain.

They made a whole bunch of representations about -- and the software was designed just about 20 minutes from where I live in Salt Lake City or just in the suburbs of Salt Lake City. They made a whole bunch of representations. They were going to have watchers that would take a half hour for these transactions to settle because they have watchers that are going to verify that it’s not getting hacked, and it’s the safest, best, perfectly safe way to do this.

But what happened was they updated their software protocol, and somehow, a backdoor was introduced into the software. And the next day, somebody came—and I don’t remember how it was—stole about $50 worth of crypto assets by just going into somebody’s wallet and using this backdoor to just extract the money out of their wallet.

The chain bridge introduced a security problem with the blockchain and allowed them to take $50. No watchers came and stopped them. It turns out that no watchers came to stop them because even though the company promised that there would be these watchers that would do this, they never appointed any watchers. It just didn’t even exist. They never actually implemented the basic security protocols that they had promised all the people that they would adopt. At least that’s what I believe happened.

After that 50 bucks got stolen, the next day, they came back, and about $186 million of crypto assets were taken out of people’s wallets. Some of these people are maybe not that sympathetic, but a lot of them are long haul truck drivers that are listening to crypto podcasts and invested their retirement account into this instead of a Vanguard low-fee mutual fund. They got wiped out because they use this cross-chain bridge. And I know this one because I should just disclose.

In addition to being a country lawyer, I also am of counsel at a law firm here in D.C. called Gupta Wessler, a full-time law teacher, but I also try to look for cases that they might be interested in and help them on their appellate briefs—that kind of thing.

And so we and another law firm—a couple law firms—got together, figured out this was happening, got some clients, and was suing them for federal racketeering because we think that that’s a money transmitter, and they were doing unlicensed money laundering and that they committed wire fraud and lying to all their customers about the security features that didn’t exist.

Now, I could be wrong about all those facts. Those are alleged, but we’re pretty sure that’s what happened, and I think it was wrong. If there’s anything, I’ll just stop on my rant about the lack of law and order in the market. Having disclosed my stake in that case, there’s a verb that I’ve figured out that exists. It’s called “rugging.” Have you heard of this? Do you know what this is?

So the idea is you build the—I don’t know—the pillow fort in your front room on top of the rug, and everybody’s talking about it. You get this structure. It’s all really wonderful. But then you just pull the rug out from underneath them. And that’s happening over and over in many of these cryptocurrency systems that they’ve developed a special verb for when that happens. It’s called “rugging somebody.” And that’s when the whole system falls apart and collapses.

So I don’t think that for people that know what the word “rugging” is, the fact that this happens again and again may not be a bug in the system. It’s the feature of the system itself. So I guess my second broad point I want to make is that, a lot of the time, I hear a lot about decentralization. And I think two things about this. First, it’s not clear to me that these are really decentralized systems.

Yes, the ledger is decentralized, unlike the Federal Reserve—which keeps the records of everybody in the ACH system or the Fedwire system. Everybody has a copy of the ledger on all their computers. I get that. But in other ways, the system is not centralized. Why? They’ve got a software protocol that’s the same in everybody. And there’s a group of people that’s controlling the software protocol, which introduces centralized holes or problems into the system in ways that aren't solved by having lots of different copies of the ledger and different records.

And then, second, even if some of these systems are more decentralized, it’s not clear to me. It’s not self-evident to me that that’s all that particularly useful all the time. It takes more energy. Did you know that Bitcoin—which is probably the most legit of all of the cryptocurrencies—every year, Bitcoin uses as much electricity as Norway does. That’s a lot of electricity—a lot of coal, a lot of oil that we’re burning just to kind of create this math puzzle, to create a crypto asset that really doesn’t have that many more value uses than fiat currencies. Maybe in El Salvador or Guatemala or somewhere where their currency is not stable, but I don’t know.

And I guess I also think that it is facilitating some extremely socially destructive behaviors. Crypto assets are the asset of choice for ransomware hackers, kidnappers, child pornographers, and drug dealers in many instances—also, people that are just investing in them. But that is part of what this ecosystem is all about.

And then, I guess the last point I’ll say is that I get that there are going to be some controversial lawsuits where the SEC, the commodities future, the CFTC moving in to try to impose some law and order on this system where there are all these scandals happening. And the definitions in their foundational organic statutes often have some ambiguity in them.

What is a security? What is a commodity? What is a money transmitter? What does it mean to be safe and sound? What are the precise definitions of deceptive, unfair, and abusive practices? Congress passed statutes that have ambiguity in them to respond to the many different kinds of commercial behaviors and practices that evolve over time.

But the federal regulators have to step in to try to create law and order. Congress has not acted because Congress is in gridlock and hasn’t done anything. Maybe they will at some point, but they haven’t yet. And so what else can they do other than try to step up and respond to some of these abuses that are happening, I think, in a rampant way in the marketplace? So I think that the federal regulators have not overreached.

Now, they’re going to win some cases; they’re losing some cases. We’ll see how it all plays out. The people that I think have overreached are people like Beanstalk Farms, Sam Bankman-Fried, and a slurry of other charlatans and scammers that are ripping people off. That’s who’s overreached. Maybe I’m the law and order guy after all. Not you.

Hon. Patrick J. Bumatay:  Excellent. Well, thank you all for these excellent opening remarks and staying within your time limits. We have about 45 minutes for questions and answers, but before we get to Q&A, I’d like to give the panelists an opportunity to respond to anything they’ve heard from the other panelists. I know you two seem like you’re chomping at the bit. Who wants to go first?

Caitlin Long:  I’ll start by saying I grant most of what you said.

Prof. Christopher L. Peterson:  Great [laughter].

Caitlin Long:  Right. I had a debate with one of the very, very early bitcoiners whether 90 percent or 99 percent of the industry needs to just burn on a raging funeral pyre. It does. The same thing was true of the early internet.

The problem is exactly what Brian was alluding to. By not creating any regulated pathway, all of these scams proliferate in the dark. And I do believe the Department of Justice is massively underfunded in this enforcement area. Could be going after a lot more of the criminals and scammers than they are in this industry. I hope they continue to. And I am someone who has handed evidence to law enforcement of one of the biggest frauds in this space, trying to clean it up.

But by approaching it the way you’re approaching it, you are literally shoving all of this activity into the dark markets and keeping the good actors on the sideline. That is exactly what the Biden administration has chosen to do. They executed a, shall we say—in Wyoming, we would call it “a shoot the stallion to scatter the herd” approach—they went after Coinbase, which was the closest to getting approved by the SEC, has been working for years to try to get a regulated pathway by the SEC.

The Fed, the White House, and Senator Dick Durbin went after my bank, which wasn’t even open—how Dick Durbin even knew to attack us on the Senate floor when we weren’t even open yet. I have been public about the fact that we knew the White House and the Fed sent the press after us because two days before the Fed voted down our bank charter membership application, two major news outlets were hounding us, telling us that we were going to be voted down.

And by the way, they put it in writing in one case that all of the applicants in front of federal banking agencies that had any crypto to their business model were simultaneously asked to withdraw their applications. That’s in writing, okay?

So clearly, it’s now obvious. There’s an all-of-government coordinated approach to take the best players who were actually trying to create a lit market, a regulated pathway for these activities to be able to use this technology. And those were the ones who got skewered the worst by the regulators.

Brian P. Brooks:  Okay. I’m going to try something a little bit different. Shady Mashinsky. [Laughter] So there’s nobody named Shady Mashinsky. There’s a guy named Alex Mashinsky. And it’s funny how when you gild the lily, you lose a little credibility. He’s an actual person, not named Shady. No idea where that comes from. But what I will tell you is --

Prof. Christopher L. Peterson:  It comes from the newspaper. I mean, I didn’t make it up [laughter].

Caitlin Long:  It’s not accurate.

Brian P. Brooks:  But it’s just not true. So here’s what I want. I want to make sort of two broad points, and then there are a couple of things I do want to deconstruct. But the first broad point I would make is for every Shady Mashinsky that you can name, there’s a Bernie Madoff. I mean, human beings are flawed people. This is why we build regulated systems, is to constrain the human impulse for fraud, greed, corruption.

There’s nothing about crypto other than value, and when they’re criminals, they’re looking for ways to obtain value for no consideration. People steal things. That’s why we have a banking system, is to make it harder to steal things.

So I would just begin by saying, “Oh, my God. We’ve named five scandals.” I can name many more scandals than that in the banking system, and so can you. So that’s not an indictment of the system. That’s an indictment of people. And that’s why we have disclosure, capital liquidity, antifraud, the Bank Secrecy Act, and all kinds of other things that everybody in this room knows well. That’s an argument for conducting market activities inside of a regulated system as opposed to keeping them out because they’re so very scary.

There’s a deeper thing, though, that Chris says that I want to unpack for a minute. And he said it in a way that sounds very plausible. He says there’s not a lot of value added here. He said, “They’re not farming. They’re not feeding anyone. They’re not manufacturing anything”—and that’s true. So the question then is, who decides, in a market economy what has value? So I was just going to ask all of you this question. How many of you in this audience own a snowmobile?

Caitlin Long:  Nobody.

Brian P. Brooks:  So that sounds like an argument. We should probably ban snowmobiles. I don’t have any use for them at all. I cannot imagine why we even have them. In most of the states, it doesn’t even snow that much with global warming, and they use gas. We should probably just ban them.

Now, how many here smoke cigarettes every day? Again, and they cause cancer. Probably, we should just ban them, I think. We should just ban cigarettes and snowmobiles. How many of you still have black lights from the ’70s? [Laughter] Now, some of who remember those, we’d argue there actually was utility there. You know what I’m talking about. But for the most part, we should probably just ban them because not that many people want them. They’re kind of weird and sketchy, maybe even skeevy. We don’t want blacklights.

But wait. This is The Federalist Society. We know that in a market economy, the government doesn’t get to tell us what things are useful enough to be allowed in the market. That’s like Bernie Sanders’ comment that we have too many different styles of shoes in this country. This is Nikita Khrushchev stuff.

You don’t tell other people what utility they get to derive out of a product that you yourself don’t find important. There are a million things that we do everyday that do not feed anyone; they don’t manufacture anyone; they don’t farm anything. And yet, weirdly, we derive utility from the fact that we could buy those things if we wanted to. That’s what markets are about.

And if you look at every stock that’s listed on the Nasdaq—and there are several thousand of them—I’ll bet most of you in this room have never and would never buy any of those companies’ products. But we allow the market to decide whether those things have value. We don’t allow the government to decide whether those have value. And that’s very troubling.

Now, I want to go through just a couple of things here that I think are actually worth unpacking just so people understand it—people who aren’t crypto-native people. So one is the comment about the long haul truck drivers who are listening to crypto podcasts.

Now, I will tell you. I’ve had some weird experiences with random people who listen to crypto podcasts. [Laughter] There is a strange culture here, I will grant you that. I had a famous experience once where I was in the back of an Uber in suburban Charleston, South Carolina, and it was one of the weirder Ubers I’ve ever been in. Normally, your Uber is like a Honda Accord, or if you’re a rich guy, it’s a Yukon. But this was an old Pontiac. I’ve never actually been in an Uber like this.

But I was in the backseat with my fiancé going to a suburban shopping mall. It’s just a vignette here. And we’re driving to the shopping mall because it’s the only place with the lens crafters open on a Sunday. You don’t care about any of these details. But the point is, as we’re driving down the street, I am who I am, and she ran crypto at a very famous company you’ve all heard of.

And the driver, at some point, he said in this low country accent, “Do you all know anything about crypto?” And you don’t really want to be in a conversation on one of those lonely highways in suburban Charleston, South Carolina. So you kind of, “Yeah, I know a little bit.” “What do you know about it? I’m invested in”—and he lists some list of assets. Well, I know a little bit about it, and so we have a little conversation.

And at a certain point, he looks in his rearview mirror. Then he asked me another question, and I answer again. And he looks in the rearview mirror, and he says, “Man, what’s your name?” And I told him my name, and he slammed on the brakes and pulled over to the side of the road because he wanted a selfie because crypto is a super weird world. So I’ll give you these long haul truckers. [Laughter] They are inspired by a lot of weird stuff. There’s no question about it. But the comment was, he bought crypto instead of a Vanguard low-fee mutual fund.

So, I mean, look. I don’t give investment advice. If I did, I would tell you that nobody should have more than 50 basis points of their net worth in crypto. They shouldn’t. There’s a lot of evidence that somebody who does have 50 basis points has higher uncorrelated long-term returns than someone who doesn’t. But no one should put their net worth in crypto.

But I will tell you that in almost every year since it was invented, Bitcoin has outperformed every other asset class. I mean, if you had put your entire net worth in Bitcoin on January 1 of this year or had put all of your net worth in a Vanguard low-fee mutual fund this year, the difference in a rate of return would be about 130 percentage points because Bitcoin is up about 190 percent this year. I’m pretty sure that your Vanguard S&P 500 fund doesn’t do that this year, last year, the year before, or any year.

So these comments, these incumbency bias comments about, “Well, it’s not as safe as the U.S. dollar,” the U.S. dollar is incredibly unsafe over long periods of time and over the last short period of time, unbelievably unsafe, right? I mean, Bitcoin—and I’m just going to focus on Bitcoin as the main crypto asset—Bitcoin is highly volatile, but it goes strongly up over time.

The dollar is moderately volatile, and it only goes down. There has never been a day when the value of the dollar as an investment asset has gone up because purchasing power declines due to the two percent inflation peg and the fact that we just had nine percent inflation last year. So again, yes, it’s volatile in an upward direction. The dollar is moderately volatile in a downward direction. So you shouldn’t let incumbency bias sort of bias us.

Two last things I’ll just comment on. These are all unrelated comments, but I’m just unpacking some of the arguments that were made. This comment about Bitcoin uses as much energy as Norway. I mean, put aside the fact that, “No, it doesn’t.” And, I mean, I’m the one on this panel who’s testified before Congress multiple times on the subject and ran one of the world’s largest bitcoin mining companies, a subsidiary of which Caitlin’s on the board of, by the way. So I think we know a little bit about bitcoin mining.

But what I will tell you is the entire bitcoin mining business is about one thing, okay? It is about renewable energy. That is what the entire business is about. And I’ll tell you how that works, okay? Renewable energy is, as an energy source, a terrible source of energy for two reasons. It is because it is intermittent because the sun only shines during the day, and the wind only blows when the wind blows. So it’s intermittent, and it’s unstorable.

So when solar energy is being generated, it produces far more energy than can be consumed. Same thing with wind. And it can’t be stored for periods when it’s not being generated because we lack the battery technology to do that. And that is why we don’t have very much solar and wind capacity because it is an uneconomic source of energy.

The only way to have wind and solar energy is to either subsidize it, which is kind of the government’s current model—“Let’s force you to buy seven cents a kilowatt hour energy when natural gas will give you two cents a kilowatt hour.” So you can either force people to take it and subsidize it through tax dollars, or you can take the excess capacity that’s unstorable and convert it into an immediate economic asset called Bitcoin.

The entire business of Bitcoin is wind and solar. So this idea that it’s -- I believe the line was, “We’re burning a lot of coal and oil.” We just aren’t. You can’t make money bitcoin mining burning coal and oil. You can only do it getting essentially free excess capacity from solar and wind farms. I can tell you that because I was the CEO of one of the largest companies in this space.

Caitlin Long:  And hydro.

Brian P. Brooks:  And hydro, right. But anything that is zero cost and unstorable, that’s what the business is. And finally, there’s a bit about socially destructive behavior. I don’t know what to say about that. I mean, it is weird when you’re in any new area. I remember being at a wedding in the year 2000 where everybody there was the CEO of barbecue.com and the CFO of pets.com and a bunch of bankrupt and arguably fraudulent business models that stole a lot of people’s investment dollars and went to zero.

Was that socially destructive behavior? I don’t know. I ran the banking system for a year, during which I imposed more than a billion dollars of fines on banks for all kinds of discrimination violations and cyber breach violations and improper use of personal data violations and credit risk management things.

All I know is Jamie Dimon lost more on the London Whale trade in one day than most of the scandals that Chris just talked about. And nobody thinks the banking system is a fraud. People are flawed. People commit crimes; people commit errors and are negligent, and that’s why we have systems to constrain the impact of those things.

What all of that means to me is, in a world where 52 million people might disagree with those of you who don’t own bitcoin—but that’s a lot of people who disagree with you—they find value in a one and a half trillion dollar market cap thing even if you don’t. And if that market’s going to exist, it would be better to exist inside of a framework that can provide supervision, that can provide capital and liquidity requirements, and clear rules of the road versus the market we have because the alternative isn’t to not have the market.

The alternative is to have an unregulated market characterized by all of the outcomes that Chris describes. So to me, I’d far rather see that inside of a system I can observe.

Hon. Patrick J. Bumatay:  Thank you. Professor Peterson, you want to respond?

Prof. Christopher L. Peterson:  Well, there’s a lot there. Let me go on a couple of points. And folks want to ask questions, too. Judge, you may have other questions. But first off, I got to say, I never said anything about banning cryptocurrency, and I certainly don’t advocate banning snowmobiles.

Look, I’m a free market guy, too. I believe that people can buy and sell stuff. But that doesn’t mean that I have to pretend that I think that it has more value than it does. And it also doesn’t mean that I have to -- the topic of the panel is whether or not the federal regulators are overextending themselves.

And my point in illustrating seven—not five—major cryptocurrency scandals, of which -- I thought seven was too many because I was going to go on too long and people would be mad. It’s a long list. It’s not just seven. It’s many, many more. And, of course, there are a lot of scandals in the banking industry. I agree that people -- humans are flawed, but I also think it’s pretty clear that this market in particular is problematic.

There are lots and lots of scandals, not -- disproportionate to the value that they’re providing to the economy. Nobody out there, at least that I’ve heard, is saying that it should be banned. And that’s certainly not what the federal regulators are doing. Nobody at the SEC or the CFTC has been saying that crypto should be banned. What they’re saying is that they -- that some of these assets and practices fit within the traditional regulatory framework that you just said that we should engage with.

So they should be considered securities, or they should be subject -- they should be commodities, or they should be accounts, or the money transmitter licensing rules should apply to them. It doesn’t strike me as all that terribly controversial that, for example, a suspicious activity report should be delivered to FinCEN when one particular company is trading large amounts of crypto assets with no “know-your-customer” due diligence between the two of them.

Caitlin Long:  We’re not arguing against that at all.

Prof. Christopher L. Peterson:  Okay. Well, then maybe we’re not disagreeing, and maybe it’s just a matter of tone because it sounds like there are a lot of things that we agree with. But that is what they’re saying in the case that I mentioned, in the Nomad cryptocurrency case. Their position is that the cross-chain bridge does not have to file any suspicious activity reports when people port one type of crypto asset to another and that even though that looks an awful lot like money laundering, that they’re entitled to do that all they want because it’s crypto, bro. It’s not dollars.

Caitlin Long:  You’re not hearing either of us challenging that.

Prof. Christopher L. Peterson:  Okay. Well --

Brian P. Brooks:  Although I would say -- we’re having a dialogue. So here’s the exciting part. This is where we become -- remember those old Sunday shows in the 80s where they really got into it? So one thing I would say, Chris, is when you say that nobody’s arguing to ban crypto, I do disagree with you on that.

Prof. Christopher L. Peterson:  Okay. Well, I’m not arguing to ban crypto.

Brian P. Brooks:  I understand. But when you talk about the securities regulators and all they’re saying is, “These meet the conditions of securities, so they should be treated like securities,” one way that the U.S. is very different from other countries is crypto assets that are deemed securities are not allowed to register and trade in the United States.

So, for example, when the SEC takes the position that the Ripple token, XRP, is a security, they’ve prohibited FINRA from allowing a broker dealer to trade XRP. So it’s not possible to register. So Apple can list a new share of stock and can register and trade that on the New York Stock Exchange. But if XRP is a security, it is prohibited, right? That’s not the case in lots of other countries.

I was just with the Brazilian securities regulator yesterday in New York, and their approach is just like the U.S. Some of these are securities, and thus, there’s a registration process, and you can trade them on a securities exchange. But in the U.S., it is, in fact, true that the SEC does want to ban crypto. Their belief is not that it should register and trade but that it should be banned.

Prof. Christopher L. Peterson:  Well, I don’t think that that’s entirely clear. I’m not sure I agree with that, and it’s certainly not what anybody in Congress has said. And there’s still a vibrant and active cryptocurrency --

Brian P. Brooks:  I mean, it’s what a significant number of people in Congress have said.

Caitlin Long:  Oh, definitely.

Prof. Christopher L. Peterson:  Sorry. There are some people who have said that.

Brian P. Brooks:  Including the chairman of the Senate Banking Committee.

Prof. Christopher L. Peterson:  Congress has not passed legislation to ban crypto. And I don’t think that there are leading cryptocurrency proposals that are going to go that far. But I do think that the notion that what we’re going to do with our banking system is allow banks to leverage themselves up with crypto assets is -- exposes a lot of taxpayer funds.

Caitlin Long:  That’s not what is proposed. Yeah, that is absolutely the opposite of what’s been proposed. There’s no leverage allowed.

Prof. Christopher L. Peterson:  Well, so do you think -- let me ask you. And it sounds like maybe we’re agreeing about some things then. Do you agree that we should not allow banks to hold crypto assets as reserves?

Caitlin Long:  Yes.

Prof. Christopher L. Peterson:  Great. That’s good. I’m glad we got that sorted away.

Brian P. Brooks:  Okay. But, Chris, do you agree that we should allow banks to custody crypto assets as part of a custody business? This is what I’m talking about.

Caitlin Long:  Bank of New York Mellon is doing it, right?

Brian P. Brooks:  This is what I’m talking about. Right.

Caitlin Long:  The Fed has allowed Bank of New York Mellon to do it. But when a startup bank in a red state proposes to do it, the Fed “rug pulls” the state of Wyoming after the state of Wyoming literally spent a hundred meetings with the Fed working on getting this charter approved.

[CROSSTALK]

Prof. Christopher L. Peterson:  [Laughter] That’s not what the verb means.

Brian P. Brooks:  What’s just hard to understand is, so when Silicon Valley bank failed, one of the things that they had on their balance sheet was about $800 million of fine wine, which was custodied for clients, right?

      And so you think, “Well, banks are banks. They shouldn’t be having a wine vault.” But they do have a wine vault. It’s an investment asset—almost a billion dollars’ worth of wine in custody. Why would custodying a bunch of thumb drives with bitcoin private keys be any different from that?

Prof. Christopher L. Peterson:  Well, one final arm is it could be more likely to be the proceeds of illegal, ill-gotten gains.

Brian P. Brooks:  Why?

Prof. Christopher L. Peterson:  It could be facilitating money laundering.

Caitlin Long:  Wine could be as well.

Brian P. Brooks:  Why would you say that?

Prof. Christopher L. Peterson:  Because there’s rampant money laundering in cryptocurrency. It happens all the time.

Brian P. Brooks:  So there’s Treasury financial crimes report every year. And in the most recent one at the end of 2022, they talked about this, and they said that as a percentage of total market activity --

Prof. Christopher L. Peterson:  This is a tough room, by the way. [Laughter] 

Brian P. Brooks:  As a percentage of market activity, there is far more money laundering as a percentage—not in absolute terms but as a percentage—far more money laundering in the banking system than there is in a crypto system, which doesn’t mean that there’s not money laundering in crypto. There is absolutely is.

Prof. Christopher L. Peterson:  Yet, and it’s illegal, and we actually go after it.

Brian P. Brooks:  But also in the banking system. Sure.

Prof. Christopher L. Peterson:  No, I know. But you and all the other banking regulators go after it, and nobody in the banking system -- I mean, there’s a lot of things that we agree about. We’re clearly pissing each other off, but [laughter] --

Brian P. Brooks:  We’ve done it before. I’m not pissed off. I find it hilarious.

Prof. Christopher L. Peterson:  There’s a lot of stuff that we agree about it. I mean, it sounds like we all agree that money laundering is bad. Do we all agree with that?

Caitlin Long:  Yes, it’s a crime.

Brian P. Brooks:  We do, but we don’t all agree that banks should custody crypto. So let us ask you a couple of questions.

Prof. Christopher L. Peterson:  No, no. We just talked about that. Do you agree that there are a lot of people in the crypto industry that maintain that the kinds of things that would facilitate money laundering, they claim that they don’t have to have money transmitter licenses and can facilitate money laundering. Is that problematic to you, or do we all agree about that?

Brian P. Brooks:  I think, Caitlin and I probably personally --

Prof. Christopher L. Peterson:  Because, if we do, maybe you’ll submit an amicus brief in my case.

Brian P. Brooks:  No, no. I don’t agree with you. What I would say on that is -- my guess is, between the two of us, we know the companies and executives who control 90 plus percent of the American crypto market, and all of them have money transmitter licenses every --

[CROSSTALK]

Prof. Christopher L. Peterson:  Oh. Well, let’s talk about that. So Coinbase is held out as a bit of one of the better actors, but Coinbase is also one of the primary investors in the Nomad cross-chain bridge. So Coinbase has a money transmitter’s license.

Brian P. Brooks:  But Citibank is one of the major investors in the Sinaloa drug cartel. I mean, so what? The market cap of this asset is one and a half trillion dollars.

Hon. Patrick J. Bumatay:  We only have about 20 minutes left of this panel, and this debate is really exciting. But I also want to give the audience an opportunity to ask some questions. Let’s intersperse that. So if you have audience questions, please state your name and your affiliation. And please make sure your question is actually a question.

Edward “Coach” Weinhaus:  Sure, thank you very much. Coach Weinhaus, Yeshiva University and UCLA. I’m also the founder of Athena Bitcoin, where we were primarily responsible for the implementation of Bitcoin as legal tender in El Salvador, as you know, the only country to really do that. I also taught the first crypto course at Booth University of Chicago and doctoral research in monetary sovereignty and cryptocurrency. And pretty much anywhere else in the world, I feel like a bitcoin sort of luminary, but then here, it’s really a great honor to be with you guys. So thank you.

Also, just as one comment. It’s not a question. A little unfair to have two people like that teaming up on Professor Peterson and also misspelling his name. But because of that, I’m going to give him a softball.

So what fundamental challenges—at least to the United States overall regulatory system—does the ability to avoid the SWIFT system internationally for transfers when a nation like El Salvador could host a bank that can receive or transfer value in dollars because it’s dollarized or Bitcoin? And obviously, everyone can comment, but it’s intended to play into your theme there.

Prof. Christopher L. Peterson:  So I think the most plausible use case scenarios for crypto assets, especially Bitcoin, are in countries that have unstable fiat currencies and also have government controls on the way that they can move money around. I’m not naive that -- I mean, there is government oppression and tyranny in our world, and there’s mismanagement of economies, and crypto assets do provide some benefits to that. And that’s one of the reasons that, like snowmobiles, I don’t want to ban them.

But that being said, though, I think that some of the benefits of those crypto assets are often oversold and that one of the things that’s particularly useful about math puzzle artificial currencies is that you could do a sales job with them and convince people into doing things that are against their best interest. That’s the concern I have domestically. And I’m not sure I got exactly -- so if you’re -- I think I took your point to mean that in comparison to SWIFT processed money transmission, there might be some advantages to crypto assets. But maybe I missed your question.

Edward “Coach” Weinhaus:  Well, so if you’re on the SWIFTsystem internationally, your dollars, America sees them. El Salvador is both because it’s bitcoin, which is money not on the SWIFT system, and it’s dollarized. So it also has a SWIFT system, and its banks can theoretically hold both of them.

Prof. Christopher L. Peterson:  In El Salvador?

Edward “Coach” Weinhaus:  Yeah, in El Salvador.

Prof. Christopher L. Peterson:  I guess that makes sense. I didn’t know that, but that makes sense.

Edward “Coach” Weinhaus:  I didn’t know if you saw any implications for that. I mean, Caitlin might be a little closer.

Prof. Christopher L. Peterson:  I hadn’t thought about it.

Caitlin Long:  Cross border is definitely one of the most important use cases for this technology—cross border, being able to move money quickly. One of my clients at Morgan Stanley took -- it took seven days for them to move their own corporate cash from their manufacturing subsidiary in Thailand to the mothership in California—seven days to move their own cash. And just being able to move that cash same day—this was 10 years ago now— we calculated would have saved them $200 million of capital. That’s the use case.

Brian P. Brooks:  I don’t want to belabor this and not get to the questions, but I’m just going to -- I’ll try and sharpen a response to this, which is, A, I think the premise of the question is that, somehow, bitcoin transactions on blockchain are invisible, whereas SWIFT transactions are visible by the Treasury Department and by the sanctions regulators, right? That’s kind of the premise.

People who work in crypto know that that’s just not true. Blockchains are public ledgers, and there are gigantic companies whose entire business is tracking movements across blockchain from wallet to wallet. So when people say—and this is largely false—but when people say, “Oh, my God. All of this money went to Hamas,” I mean, the truth is a very small amount went to Hamas and hasn’t gone to Hamas in nine months because they stopped accepting bitcoin.

But when they did, the reason we know that is because it’s transparent, and chain analysis can tell us when Hamas got the bitcoin. But the premise is one that you hear a lot, which is, “This is all secret” versus SWIFT is not secret. There’s nothing secret about bitcoin. Bitcoin is a public ledger that everyone has access to. And they’re giant companies whose whole business is tracing movement from person A to person B.

Prof. Christopher L. Peterson:  Can I just chime in on that? It’s not secret, but it is opaque. I mean, chain analysis can figure it out as they did in a bunch of the big scandals, but—like Mt. Gox and other early things—but it’s opaque. They can figure it out. Government regulators sometimes can figure it out, but lots of people can’t.

Caitlin Long:  No, no.

Prof. Christopher L. Peterson:  And that’s just bitcoin. And it doesn’t include tumblers.

Caitlin Long:  It’s not true. There is an effort right now by a gentleman named Nick Carter. He’s actually paying out bounties for citizen journalists, and he’s paid out now 30 different bounties for exposing the truth of how little money went to Hamas. It is absolutely possible, if you have the right technology skills, you don’t need to be a company.

Hon. Patrick J. Bumatay:  Okay, let’s go to the next question.

Questioner 2:  Yeah, thank you. I’m curious. One or all of the panelists, what’s your thought about the proposed digital dollar, either in relation to or in comparison to crypto?

Brian P. Brooks:  So I’ve spoken a lot about this. What you’re referring to is like a U.S. central bank digital currency. So almost every central bank in the world is talking about central bank digital currencies. I have an enormously strong civil libertarian opposition to this concept. The concept basically is, once there’s a CBDC—and there’s a lot of assumptions behind this comment—but once there’s a CBDC and we no longer intermediate transactions through the banking system, we now have people having direct clearing with the central bank.

That makes the central bank capable of deciding which transactions can clear and which transactions can’t clear. And you might think—and I used to get this a lot when I was the controller—you might think, “Well, this is America. It’s not China. We’re not going to prevent you from buying cigarettes or snowmobiles or whatever.” I think we all know the fallacy of that comment, right? We all know the fallacy of that.

I sat in my office one time with the CEO of one of the largest banks in the world, and he told me that they were looking at whether they could change the way that they did credit card processing to prevent their card from being used to purchase firearms. And I said, “Would that apply only to credit cards or also debit cards?” He said, “Both, anything with our Visa membership.”

I said, “So even when it’s a debit card—so it’s my money. It’s not your money. You’re not lending me money, even on a short-term basis—you won’t let me buy a hunting rifle to go hunting with my dad the way that I did when I was 12?” “Yes. Well, it’s just too dangerous.” That’s the thinking that makes CBDCs scary.

The rationale for CBDCs is what Caitlin says. It’s instant settlement versus the latency that we have in today’s system. But for that, we have stablecoins, which have incredibly high velocity: instant transactions, privately issued, not controlled by political actors. I don’t want the government to tell me that I’ve burned enough gas this month or I’ve smoked enough cigarettes this month. I’m very worried about that, and I see that as an inevitable outcome.

Caitlin Long:  Fully agree. Just full disclosure. Custodia was granted the patent by the USPTO in July of 2022 for a tokenized bank deposit, which is exactly the private version of a U.S. dollar—taking in a dollar deposit and turning around and issuing on an open public blockchain a token for that dollar. And you might have seen what the Federal Reserve said about that.

Hon. Patrick J. Bumatay:  Any quick response?

Prof. Christopher L. Peterson:  I have concerns about whether or not it’s going to be safe and sound, whether or not there are going to be technical details, whether it’s going to be hackable. And I’m a lot less worried about the government overreaching because The Federalist Society will come for them and will stop them.

[Laughter]

Hon. Patrick J. Bumatay:  Yes. Professor McGinnis?

Prof. John O. McGinnis:  Yes. John McGinnis, Northwestern I’d like to ask about what I see as a paradox of crypto and whether it might be solved, which is that cryptocurrency, while they are decentralized—at least in our current world—really need more centralized holders. They need wallets or banks or custodians who are regulated, of course, by centralized actors themselves.

Is there a possibility in the future that will you see blockchain and cryptocurrency create structures that will compete and so we’ll have a more decentralization all the way down, even holding these matters, and therefore, have alternatives to some of the more centralized regulatory and centralized holding structures we have?

Brian P. Brooks:  Or as the saying goes, “Turtles all the way down.” So what I would say is that the promise of blockchain is not that the ecosystem is decentralized. The promise is that the network control is decentralized. In other words, the validation of transactions is decentralized.

Clearly, for any kind of foreseeable future and for retail use, they’re going to be centralized on and off ramps. I mean, you have to buy your bitcoin somewhere, and you have to download a piece of software to have a wallet, and some maker is going to make that.

So for me, I think about it less, as is the whole eco -- will there be banks? Yes, there will still be banks. Will there be custodians? There’ll still be that. There will still be technology companies that have CEOs. That will all still exist. The question just is, “Will you have something different from the automated clearing house, which is owned by 16 banks, versus the Bitcoin network?”—which has how many nodes? 12,000? 14,000?

Caitlin Long:  Oh, no, it’s more than 40,000 nodes now all over the world.

Brian P. Brooks:  All right. So tens of thousands of nodes all over the world totally unconnected to each other, none.

Prof. Christopher L. Peterson:  None of them using any power from coal or oil

[Laughter]

Brian P. Brooks:  Yeah. Well, I mean, kidding aside, not if they’re making money, but that’s a different point. I mean, the real point just is, will you still have banks? Yes. Will you still have custodians for retail holders? Absolutely. The question is about the underlying network. Can you have a user-owned network versus an investor-owned network like the Clearinghouse or SWIFT?

I think thinking that the other stuff is going to be centralized. It’s a false premise that a lot of people have, and they attack crypto because Coinbase is a corporation, and therefore, they think Bitcoin isn’t decentralized. I think they’re two different things, is the way I think about it. How do you think about it?

Caitlin Long:  Yeah, I would agree. Also, it’s an interesting question about what is the role of a bank? We look at banks because we’re so used to dealing in -- thinking about money being credit. We look at banks as credit-based institutions. But if you look at the history of banking globally, what banks originally were were just money warehouses where they stored people’s gold. They were just custodians, and they did business for a fee.

The concept that banks have to be a lender in order to be a bank is relatively new in banking history. It used to be that lenders were separated from payment organizations, which were just service providers.

So one of the nice things about the Wyoming charter is it goes back to the roots of banking, where your bank is not your counterparty. You’re not taking credit exposure to them. Brian made the reference earlier about the debit cards, that that was my money. Legally, it’s not. I think most of you all know that when you deposit money in a bank, you’re making a loan to a leveraged organization, okay?

So if we actually look at banking and say, “Well, a bank, under U.S. law is legally a depository institution, which is a corporation that is bestowed with the right to take U.S. dollar deposits.” That is a very specific definition. And if a state wants to create a depository institution that cannot lend because all it’s doing is being a service provider to its customers—not being a counterparty to its customers—that’s a powerful concept, and it is certainly not without precedent in the banking world.

Hon. Patrick J. Bumatay:  Okay. Let’s take two questions at a time, and the panelists could address them together. So I think we’ll start with your side. Go ahead.

Keith Rothfus:  Keith Rothfus from Pittsburgh, PA. Good to see you, Brian. I’m curious about the custody issue because, as I understand custody banks, if you’re holding an asset, it doesn’t become an asset of the bank. It’s threatened. They’re not supposed to be pledging it. The wine in Silicon Valley bank was the customer’s wine. It was just being held.

What is the argument if BNY Mellon is allowed to hold or to custody Bitcoin or whatever, what’s the argument? Do the regulators see it -- if you’re holding it, it’s some kind of nefarious thing that we don’t want you touching, like you can’t custody fentanyl or whatever? But what’s the argument that you cannot custody something like Bitcoin?

Caitlin Long:  There is no legal argument. Thanks to what Brian was able to achieve during his time period at the OCC. It is legal for banks to do this. The issue is that there is an unbelievable amount of incumbency bias in the banking system. It’s true in the SEC as well.

Everyone’s watching the assumption that BlackRock—even though small ETF managers, started applying for ETFs for Bitcoin almost a decade ago, but BlackRock is in the driver’s seat—there is an unbelievable incumbency bias among federal financial regulators. That’s not true of the states, but that’s also part of the reason why there is this clash between the states and the federal banking regulators.

Brian P. Brooks:  Can I just tease out? Since we’re at a FedSoc event, let me just tease out two actual legal issues around this that are kind of fun to think about. So two things The FedSoc cares a lot about are the non-delegation doctrine and Chevron. These are two things we really, really care about here.

And what’s interesting is Caitlin’s right. There’s not a legal argument founded in any of these specific provisions of federal banking law about custody in crypto. So what they rely on are these amorphous nondelegation violations you’d argue about safety and soundness and reputational risk.

So nobody’s saying it’s illegal, but that what they are saying is we’re still not going to let you do it because even though it’s not illegal, it could be reputationally risky. And that can mean anything that given regulator wants it to mean.

Hon. Patrick J. Bumatay:  Go ahead.

Questioner 5:  Thanks, Judge Bumatay, for -- I thought this panel was great. My question, I kind of want to piggyback on the professor’s question with -- so I understand the promise of bitcoin to sort of take away that money-printing ability of the government, right?

But I think that it sounds like we all agree that building on layer one, not everyone’s going to be able to transact in layer one. It has to go to layer two, and then there’s going to be these -- Custodia Bank, and there’s going to be wallets, and there’s that centralization. And then you’re talking about the Bitcoin ETF.

Well, it seems to me that the government can come in and regulate on that level. And I guess I’m wondering. How do you see it going forward because it’s not just the promise of the money printer, but there’s also this idea of the peer-to-peer? And personally, I mean, I would prefer that there not be any regulation because I’d like the government not to be in this space at all. But I understand that that’s the way it’s going. So how do we maintain the promise when it is going towards centralization?

Hon. Patrick J. Bumatay:  And let’s get the last question. We can combine the answers. Go ahead.

Aaron Ward [sp]:  Yeah, so I’m Aaron Ward. My question also relates to sort of decentralization. Recently, we’ve seen a trend of the IRS issuing these John Doe subpoenas, where they’ll essentially tell a financial institution, “Give us the data on anyone who’s conducted this type of transaction within the last time period. So give us data on anyone who’s converted, say, bitcoin to U.S. dollars from 2016 to 2019 or something like that.” And they’ll hand these summons to financial institutions like, say, Coinbase. This will often result in getting data from a huge amount of customers. I think in the Coinbase case, it was 10,000 or 15,000 customers they handed data over to.

And when applied, traditional financial institutions, the courts have found there’s no Fourth Amendment expectation of privacy. So these don’t violate the Fourth Amendment. Do you see any reason that this would be different for cryptocurrency compared to traditional financial institutions? And, if not, doesn’t that kind of undermine the purported decentralization benefits? The IRS can just come in and individually target these customers whenever they please.

Hon. Patrick J. Bumatay:  Thank you. Who wants to start?

Caitlin Long:  On the peer-to-peer point, real quickly, no one’s ever shutting Bitcoin down. It’s way past that point. And as a result, we can always go peer-to-peer. Most people -- just like, frankly, if you knew how to make -- how to use the command line interface, you could make all of your telephone calls using the command line interface instead of having one of these devices and going through a phone company. Most people don’t because this provides you with extra security and a good user interface. Bitcoin is well past the point where it will ever be able to be banned, and that is the failsafe, that you can always go peer-to-peer.

Brian P. Brooks:  Yeah. I’ll try and touch on each of those comments. So on the comment over here, the interesting wrinkle on what you’re talking about—about subpoenas and the authority of the government to come and get your records—the interesting authority here is that in truly decentralized situations, there’s nobody to serve.

And so the weird kind of law that has started to arise in this context is people will serve Twitter. They’ll say, “We can’t find the”—what was that thing called? The Nomad?—“we can’t find the Nomad cross-chain protocol because that’s not a company or a person. It’s a protocol.” So we’re serving the Nomad cross-chain protocol by posting something on Twitter. So that’s the kind of craziness you see there. So it’s a little bit different from saying you have an expectation of privacy.

And I would argue, in Bitcoin, you probably have less of an expectation of privacy than you have in a bank account because of the open nature of the ledger. However, you have problems of jurisdiction and service and those things. I mean, to me, that’s what I find intriguing about that.

On the peer-to-peer bit, what I would just say is—and my guess is everybody in crypto has a different theory on this. So I’ll bet Caitlin’s is a little bit different for mine—but the way I think about crypto is there are four things going on in crypto. This is really all you need to know. There’s Bitcoin, which really—honestly, don’t quote me on this—isn’t really a peer-to-peer transaction network. It’s really a store of value. Some people will disagree since the title of the paper is different. But there’s Bitcoin.

There’s then a set of what are called smart contract protocols. And there’s a certain number of those. Ethereum is the most famous, but there are a bunch of others. Those are the networks that exist to facilitate peer-to-peer transactions in an instant settlement, efficiency gaining, financial intermediation kind of way. And so those things are the things that I look to to support that. Then there are stablecoins, which mostly sit on top of smart contract protocols, and then there’s every other damn thing.

So what I think about it is, just because Bitcoin is slow or has whatever problems you think Bitcoin has in no way undermines the foundational relevance of bitcoin to crypto. But bitcoin is not where the next visa network will be built. Somewhere like Ethereum or Solana or Avalanche or Cardano or one of those protocols will be where the next Visa substitute will be built. But again, there are as many different crypto things going on as there are internet companies that, basically, these are internet stocks at some level.

Hon. Patrick J. Bumatay:  Okay. Professor Peterson, you’ll have the last word. You have about a minute.

Prof. Christopher L. Peterson:  Well, all right. First on the peer-to-peer question, look. I get the sort of promise of having people be able to interact with each other without having banks or other big institutions to cause problems for them. But things like bank runs, stock fraud, money laundering are real problems and have been -- and plagued market economies like ours for hundreds and hundreds of years.

We have a bunch of laws that are supposed to try to prevent and protect people from those kinds of problems. Federal regulators are trying to move forward under uncertainty and radical transformation with no additional guidance from our gridlocked Congress—especially our Senate—to try to figure out the way to deal with these problems.

And I don’t think that they’re overextending themselves, and I think that we’re going to need rules that facilitate dealing with those types of problems, whether it’s our current set of rules or a new one. If we could find some way to compromise and get something to Congress, I don’t know.

And then with respect to getting data on users of cryptocurrencies from wallet providers, other companies, I don’t -- we usually have “know-your-customer” rules in banking. And just the fact that you have tried to design your system to not be outside of that doesn’t mean that there might not be a legitimate government purpose in getting discovery for a lawsuit or for an investigation of criminal activity. There are going to be situations where we need to know who has assets because those assets are the proceeds of crime or other inappropriate behavior, and that’s a legitimate function of government.

Hon. Patrick J. Bumatay:  Okay. That’s all we have time left for this panel. Let’s give everyone a round of applause. What a great discussion.

 

[Applause]

11:30 a.m. - 1:30 p.m.
The Future of DEI in Business

2023 National Lawyers Convention

Topics: In-House Counsel Working Group
East Room
The Mayflower Hotel
1127 Connecticut Avenue NW
Washington, DC 20006

Share

Event Video

Listen & Download

Description

Featuring:

  • Ms. Erin E. Murphy, Partner, Clement & Murphy, PLLC
  • Mr. Patrick Strawbridge, Partner, Consovoy McCarthy Park PLLC
  • Hon. Seth P. Waxman, Partner, WilmerHale; Former United States Solicitor General
  • Moderator: Hon. Timothy M. Tymkovich, United States Court of Appeals, Tenth Circuit

Speakers

Event Transcript

Hon. Dean A. Reuter:  Okay. Very good. Welcome, one and all. Thank you for being here at our convention. Thank you for your interest in this panel in particular. I wanted to take just a minute. We usually have our practice group people who are in charge of putting together the breakout sessions introduce their respective practice group panels. This is a special session of the In-House Counsel Network, so I wanted to introduce it and just say a few words about the In-House Counsel Network so you know what it is and let you know that we are still open to new members of the In-House Counsel Network.

 

Doing a quick inventory of what was happening in the business world two or three years ago, we thought it would be good to organize Federalist Society members and Federalist Society sympathizers who are working in-house, whether they’re the GCs or principle deputies. And that’s the idea behind the In-House Counsel Network. We looked at our database which has tens of thousands of people, and about 120 or so had identified as working in-house. And that’s what we started with.

 

We started small. We started sort of quietly. And then when we felt like we had our legs under us and had an idea about what we wanted to do and emphasize, we had a launch conference in Chicago last May, so 18 months ago. And since then, we’ve had conferences every six months and a panel at each of the last -- counting this convention each of the last three conventions to highlight the issues that are working in-house. Turns out there are a lot. Now there are 500 people involved who are working in-house. So there’s a lot of interest and a lot of possibilities. If you know somebody who’s working in-house, who’s not yet part of the network, fell free to send them our way.

 

With that, I’m very happy to introduce the moderator of this in-house counsel panel, Judge Tim Tymkovich from Denver, Colorado. Judge Tymkovich was nominated to the Tenth Circuit Court of Appeals by President George W. Bush and confirm in April 2003. So he’s been on the bench 20 years now. Congratulations. He served in a variety of capacities since then. Interestingly since 2008—I consider this giving back in an additional way, in addition to your service to your country, to the academic community and the legal community—he’s served as an adjunct professor of law at the University of Colorado School of Law.

 

I can go on, but I’ve told all our moderators to be brief in introducing their panelists. So I will be brief in introducing Judge Tymkovich. With that, judge, the floor is yours. Oh, can I say one more thing? I apologize.

 

Hon. Timothy M. Tymkovich:  You can say it.

 

Hon. Dean A. Reuter:  I just had a conversation with somebody in the hallway which concluded with him saying to me I’ll see you tonight at Union Station. Okay. You guys get the joke. Good. Don’t go to Union Station. Go to the Washington Hilton up on Connecticut Avenue. Thank you. Now, Judge Tymkovich, thank you.

 

Hon. Timothy M. Tymkovich:  Remember, Union Station. Thank you, Dean, for that kind introduction and for putting this all-star panel together and allowing me to moderate the discussion. I’ve been coming to these Federalist Society events, believe it or not, since 1982 when The Federalist Society hosted its first lawyers’ meeting at Yale University Law School. So it’s great to have a chance to participate in the Society over almost four decades.

 

The Society since that first meeting has become a national forum for debate on the great issues of law and society. And this panel is no exception. On June 23, the Supreme Court issued its 6-3 decision in Students for Fair Admission v. Harvard and North Carolina. The decision took on race-based admissions to private and public universities, closing the circle from Bakke to Grutter to today. While directed at the schools of higher education, the decision was grounded in the Fourteenth Amendment’s equal protection clause. But its legal reasoning resonates beyond its factual setting. How will it apply to different settings like private businesses and state and federal government entities?

 

Many entities have developed and implemented diversity, equity, and inclusion initiatives that set the terms of hiring, promotion, retention, compensation, termination, and possibly more. In a statement shortly after SFFA, the chair of the Equal Employment Opportunity Commission wrote that “It remains lawful for employers to implement diversity, equity, inclusion, and accessibility programs that seek to ensure workers of all backgrounds are afforded equal opportunity in the workplace.” But others saw the decision as much more sweeping.

 

One commentator noted that Justice Gorsuch’s concurring opinion made it crystal clear that in his view the Court’s rule that an education institution may never discriminate based on race now applies with equal force to employers. Other lawyers argue that it’s too soon to know how the current Court would answer such questions. Nevertheless, lower courts are on the march.

 

Activist groups and litigators around the country are targeting DEI initiatives on a variety of theories, essentially arguing they promote race-based decision-making or even create hostile work environments. Many entities, from Starbucks to state agencies to venture capital funds to corporate board selections to law firms to airline companies, have been sued over their DEI programs. Now the courts and lawyers must navigate the new legal landscape as they seek to apply the holding of SFFA.

 

Today’s panelists are well suited to educate us on the issues and challenges businesses will face going forward, so let me introduce today’s panelists in the order of their initial statements. First to speak will be Patrick Strawbridge, who’s a partner at the Consovoy McCarthy and represented Students for Fair Admission in its suit against the University of North Carolina. Patrick has represented a broad range of individuals and institutional clients on matters of con law, financial and securities regulation, environmental laws, complex commercial disputes, and consumer protection statutes. Prior to joining his firm, Patrick was a law clerk for Justice Clarence Thomas.

 

Next up will be Erin Murphy, sitting next to me. She’s one of the most widely recognized and one of the nation’s leading Supreme Court and appellate advocates. She’s a partner at Clement & Murphy and has argued dozens of cases in appellate and trial courts throughout the country, including the Supreme Court and nearly all federal courts of appeals. Does that include the Tenth Circuit?

 

Erin E. Murphy:  That’s the only one I haven’t done.

 

Hon. Timothy M. Tymkovich:  Okay. Well, you’re welcome.

 

Hon. Seth P. Waxman:  You’re really missing something.

 

Hon. Timothy M. Tymkovich:  Erin clerked for Chief Justice John Roberts on the Supreme Court also.

 

And our third speaker is Seth Waxman, who’s co-chair of WilmerHale’s Appellate and Supreme Court Litigation practice. Seth argued in defense of Harvard’s admission practice in SFFA and has served on Harvard’s legal team since the suit was first filed in 2014. Although he did not clerk on the Supreme Court, he is one of the country’s premier Supreme Court and appellate advocates, having served as the 41st Solicitor General of the United States from 1997 to 2001 and participated in at least 80 Supreme Court appellate arguments in those capacities. Welcome, panel, and thank you for joining us today.

 

Okay. We’re going to start with some opening statements, and there might be some rebuttal. We’re going to have a conversation on these issues throughout the afternoon. And we will take questions from the audience sometime around 1:00 or 1:05 for those keeping track. With that, let’s get started.

 

Patrick Strawbridge:  I want to make it clear that the goal of this panel is not for it to go on nearly as long as the SFFA arguments themselves went on.

 

Hon. Seth P. Waxman:  Yeah. We’ll need a bathroom break.

 

Hon. Seth P. Waxman:  That would have been really nice.

 

Hon. Timothy M. Tymkovich:  I can feel your pain.

 

Patrick Strawbridge:  The old chief’s method it would have moved much faster.

 

Hon. Seth P. Waxman:  There was a point at which the clerk came out and told all the advocates the chief justice just wants everyone to know that there will be a ten minute break in between the two arguments, which seemed fine, except that two and a half hours went by and we were still in the first argument. And I was sitting at the backup table waiting to argue the Harvard case with the current Solicitor General, and I leaned over to her and said, you probably don’t have this problem, but I am 71 years old. I had at least eight cups of coffee this morning, and I am no longer able to concentrate on anything that’s going on here.

 

When they finally did break, something happened in the Supreme Court I have never seen, which is the jam packed Supreme Court immediately every single person jolted up and went running out the closest door. And there was a 15 minute break at the end of which the only people back in the courtroom were the justices and the arguing lawyers. The entire public was left standing in line at the one men’s room and one ladies’ room available. But we’re not going to do that.

 

Patrick Strawbridge:  Thankfully. Thank you very much for the invitation and for the introduction, and I appreciate the panelists up here appearing beside us. This is always a very useful forum, and I always enjoy coming here to watch. And I’m happy to be able to participate this year. And I appreciate that.

 

I also have one other piece of -- it’s not a disclaimer. I have another comment I’m morally obligated to make every time we talk about these cases. And that is that these cases were really the brainchild and the driving force behind them was my dear departed friend and law partner Will Consovoy. Will deserves all the credit for the victory that our client was able to achieve in this case. I always go to these functions and I ask people just very briefly with a show of hands how many of you were lucky enough to have the opportunity to interact with Will Consovoy at some point.

 

Some of you I know have seen him arguing in front of you before. I would encourage everybody who raised their hand and who knew Will to go on and to try to dedicate yourself to serve with the same commitment and humanity that Will did. It’s a model that I try to observe, and I just have to say that when we talk about these cases.

 

So the topic of this panel is what does SFFA portend or what does it say about the future of DEI policies in the workplace. And we can have lots of debates about what constitutes a DEI policy, and there’s very much an eye of the beholder question that could be asked as to is this practice DEI? Well, it could be described as DEI, and maybe that’s fine. Is this practice DEI? Well, it is described as DEI, and it’s emphatically not fine.

 

I will start this discussion with the proposition that as a matter of law I don’t think SFFA really should’ve changed that much about DEI practices in the workplace. And what I mean to say by that is I do not think that racial considerations in hiring, providing benefits, training people, or promoting them were proper before SFFA was issued. And obviously I don’t think that they’re proper now.

 

SFFA was obviously an attack on what we would consider a loophole in the Supreme Court’s approach to strict scrutiny in racial classifications. It was a loophole that was very specific to higher education. And I don’t think that that loophole ever should have been viewed as supporting or expanding what was permissible either in a state or municipal government workplace or in a private workplace under Title VII.

 

And Grutter itself obviously emphasizes that if you go back and read Grutter, and you could even go back and read the concurring opinion in Bakke or controlling opinion in Bakke, however you want to view Justice Powell’s opinion. It also is very clear that it was talking about the higher educational context, that is the context in which both those cases arose. And there’s limiting language all over the opinion that says it’s limited to the unique context of higher education.

 

And of course we knew thanks to the Supreme Court’s decision in the 2000s in Parents Involved that whatever the value of the diversity rational was in Grutter and in the higher educational context, the Supreme Court was unwilling to expand it even to K through 12 education. And so if it doesn’t even hold up through K through 12 education, I don’t know whatever basis there would’ve been to presume that some sort of racial preference regime could survive outside of the educational context entirely in the workplace.

 

And I think that there were other clear warnings of this fact as well, indeed some that long predated Grutter. Adarand [Constructors] is a very good example of where I think the Court drew a fairly clear line that a nonremedial program for federal contractors could not deploy racial classifications. There’s a similar case involving broadcast media licensing. There was the Ricci case in 2009 that I think made it very clear that fear of liability could not justify racial classifications in public hiring. And even as recently as the Bostock case, the Court was very clear in interpreting the language of Title VII that says that if you are making a decision that is somehow a function of sex, that is permitted by Title VII’s clear language.

 

I will leave for other panels, thousands of other panels past and future, as to the sustainability of the reading of the term “sex” in there. But obviously Title VII also includes the term “race.” And so to the extent that Bostock is saying if you are making decisions based on race you are violating Title VII, which I think a lot of people read it to say at the time, I think that was as clear a statement of law as anybody needed long before -- maybe not long before but several years before the Students for Fair Admissions decision came out.

 

Now, all of that is not to suggest that Students for Fair Admissions decision is somehow irrelevant to employers. The fact that there were a number of warning lights popping up on your dashboard every time you got into your car for five trips before doesn’t mean on the sixth trip now you should ignore the warning lights. And SFFA, I think, makes very clear to the extent that there was a desire to employ racial classifications in promoting or training or hiring or even in employee compensation or in benefits provisions, it obviously undercuts the suggestion that there can be some sort of abstract goal of racial justice that doesn’t have any individualized harm.

 

It obviously talks about the importance of ending racial discrimination, meaning we end all racial discrimination. So to that extent, I think SFFA is just simply another in a long line of cases that strict scrutiny applies. If you’re not doing direct remediation for immediate past discrimination, you’re almost certainly going to fail to uphold a racial classification. So that is my opening remark.

 

Hon. Timothy M. Tymkovich:  Thank you. Erin?

 

Erin E. Murphy:  Thank you, judge, and thanks to FedSoc for inviting me here today and all of you for joining us on what is certainly I think one of the more pressing questions that as the opening remarks indicated, that everybody in pretty much any area is confronting no matter what kind of company or business or public/private you have. There’s a lot of questions right now.

 

And I think that’s partly because while pretty much everything Patrick just said about where the law is is right—it’s true that the Court made very clear that this line of cases was about kind of an exception to the general rule that created kind of a greater toleration of the use of race in the higher education context—as a practical matter I think there’s a bit of a public perception that it’s almost the opposite right now. We are at a moment where we have the Supreme Court putting out an opinion in this area at the same time that DEI initiatives are probably at their height, kind of the highest level that they’ve been in quite some time, which creates kind of a bit of a dichotomy from the perspective of the way I think a lot of the public is thinking about this issue, the way companies are thinking about this issue, the way boards might be thinking about this issue, people who aren’t lawyers that aren’t kind of focused on it through that lens.

 

It’s almost like the diversity concept that was built around these cases in the higher education context became the blueprint for thinking about how do we extend all of that into the context of private companies and employment and all of these other areas. And Patrick’s right. That is certainly not what the Court was ever saying it was doing, and by and large the Court has said no, in that context you’re not supposed to be taking race into account.

 

Now, I think a lot of where the rubber is going to meet the road is the Supreme Court has a line of cases that says, yes, companies can have voluntary affirmative action programs. And there’s a lot of debate about what exactly that means. Certainly, you can read those cases to allow for kind of a relatively loose conception of what it means to have a remedial program and what it means to have something that is designed to advance the interest of your particular business.

 

I’m not sure that’s the way a majority of this current Supreme Court would read those cases, and I think they may be more inclined to say, look, the only exception we were ever trying to recognize in the context of Title VII is for true remediation in the sense of if you, yourself, as a company has engaged in some sort of past discriminatory practice, certainly you can remediate that. But if you’re talking about kind of taking a broader approach to remediating what are viewed as kind of the broader discrimination that’s occurred in society and history, I think that’s something that’s going to be really hard to get this Court to think is the right way to understand Title VII or the right way to understand even its cases that have allowed a little bit more room in the Title VII context. And certainly we know a couple of justices have already made very clear that they don’t see it that way. And Justice Gorsuch lays out a pretty compelling argument that if you take Bostock seriously, it’s hard to reconcile that with the use of race in employment contexts.

 

But I think the other really critical question in all of this is obviously a lot of employers are private organizations. A lot of companies are private organizations that are not bound by the equal protection clause. And so some of the important questions are what is the reach of the federal statutes that are the statutes that operate here? Because there’s a lot of law about Title VII, but certainly not every aspect of DEI initiatives has to do with actual employment decisions.

 

There are initiatives that companies have engaged in that involve things like just broader grants, kind of just broader community service efforts, charitable giving, all of those types of efforts that are going on in companies that don’t fall within the bucket of Title VII. And some of those have been challenged. They’re challenged through Section 1981, which raises questions about -- Section 1981 covers contracting.

 

And so then you have to get into questions about, okay, what does and doesn’t count as contracting on the part of a company? So some of these threshold questions I think are going to be a lot more important right now. Even in the Title VII context there’s a lot of law about what is and isn’t a decision that’s covered by Title VII. But there’s open questions there.

 

The Supreme Court’s hearing a case in December about the understanding of what’s covered by Title VII. And there’s a bit of an interesting dynamic at this point because generally the EEOC has taken about as broad a position as it can take on what counts as an employment decision covered by Title VII, which creates some interesting dynamics if you end up having a court that makes very clear that that means all of those decisions and all of those actions are actions that are going to be viewed kind of more through an SFFA lens.

 

So I think a lot of the litigation here to keep an eye on is not just the question of how do these equal protection principles apply through the various statutes that matter here but also what is the reach of those statutes. And that as Patrick said at the outset DEI is a very large bucket that covers a lot of things. And what this case means for straight up decisions about who to hire and fire, etc., may be relatively clear. Whereas it may be a lot harder when you get to things that are further away from that, things that involve just efforts to broaden the applicant pool or things that have nothing to do with employment decisions at all and are just basically corporate initiatives driven by corporate giving and such that don’t implicate Title VII and get into some trickier questions about a very differently worded statute that has a very different scope.

 

So I am not Patrick who I know who is litigating pretty much all of these issues everywhere, so I am sure --

 

Patrick Strawbridge: [inaudible 00:23:03].

 

Erin E. Murphy:  -- he has strong views about the scope of both. To me both in the higher education context and more broadly I think this is really the beginning, not the end, of the conversation with the courts about what is permissible in this area.

 

Hon. Timothy M. Tymkovich:  Thank you, Erin. Seth?

 

Hon. Seth P. Waxman:  Well, I want to thank Dean for inviting me here and thank all of you for listening to me. When I heard Judge Tymkovich say that he’s been attending the FedSoc convention -- well, it wasn’t a convention then but FedSoc meetings since 1982, it made me realize that I guess I’m also old enough to say that I also have been pretty much not attending but speaking at FedSoc meetings (laughter) I think without exception since 1982, not because I am a member.

 

I’m not a member of The Federalist Society or the American Constitution Society for that matter, but I feel like these events and similar events that provide an opportunity for our profession to speak amongst itself and to others about interesting questions and differences of opinion is so important. And it seems like it becomes more important every year as the broader American society becomes more tribal and shrill and sort of uncomfortable and unwilling to engage with people who might have different ideas or might come from different perspectives. So I like being here, and I appreciate the annual invitation.

 

I have to say that I’m feeling a little deflated right now because I agree with everything that Erin said and much more with what Patrick said than we normally find ourselves when we’re sitting at counsel table in those instances with a podium in the middle. And so I think a lot of what you’re going to hear from me is -- and among the panel is not all that different. I certainly agree with Patrick’s opening remark and Erin’s concurring remark that the SFFA v. Harvard and North Carolina cases had nothing to do with Title VII or employment decisions.

 

The things that were legal and illegal under Title VII and whatever the yet undiscerned scope of Section 1981 is were just as illegal the day before the Supreme Court decided the case than afterwards. I also agree that, nonetheless, there are some important clues that private employers can take in terms of how they structure their own employment practices by what the Supreme Court majority opinion did say in the SFFA decision when it near the end of the majority opinion talked about the kinds of things that of course even universities can continue to consider and continue to do. And so I’ll say before I actually -- I’m doing the prebuttal before I do my sort of opening remarks, but I can’t let the opportunity -- I can’t just drone on with my opening remarks without coming at Patrick with something. I think --

 

Patrick Strawbridge:  It’s the point of the panel, I think.

 

Hon. Seth P. Waxman:  I think everybody would be disappointed.

 

Hon. Timothy M. Tymkovich:  The kumbaya moment’s over?

 

Hon. Seth P. Waxman:  No, no. No, no, no. I’m search for opportunities where we won’t be kumbaya because I know everybody has enjoyed a sumptuous and delicious lunch, and this is the appropriate time of the day when the body’s natural rhythms suggest that if something exciting isn’t really happening it probably would be better just to close your eyes.

 

So I do disagree. The fact that the Supreme Court in SFFA, if we’re talking about the diversity rational, has reversed decades of precedent and now has held that diversity itself, the interest in diversity and the educational environment and perhaps extrapolating beyond doesn’t constitute a sufficient compelling interest to justify the use of race as a decisional factor under strict scrutiny does not at all mean that diversity considerations are not valid, they’re not important, and that private companies are not precluded from prioritizing that if it is consistent with the corporate culture and the values that the corporation -- the kind of workplace that the corporation wants to foster.

 

And so I’d like to basically make two points. One is I think that thoughtfully designed corporate diversity, equity, and inclusion programs are not only legally permissible but from my perspective I think they’re important both for businesses that have those values and for American society more broadly and that there are within the bounds of what constitutes DEI -- and I totally agree with Patrick that it is a vague term that can mean all sorts of things to people and is not that useful as a concept. It’s an expression of goals; it’s not an expression of the means by which companies that want to achieve or promote those goals can go about doing it.

 

And I’d like to suggest that there are a lot of kinds of corporate DEI initiatives that are entirely lawful and valid. And I never thought that my practice would come to providing advice to corporations about something like their HR departments and what their programs are. And I honestly didn’t think about it for one millisecond in the ten years that Patrick and I were litigating the Harvard case. But I do find myself now contacted by lots of company general counsels who are on the one hand getting threatening letters saying, you’re violating the Constitution and you better stop doing X, Y, and Z, or we’re going to investigate you or sue you and on the other hand letters from other law enforcement people and shareholders and stuff saying what do you mean you’re not doing these programs? You’re not doing enough. And it’s a genuine question.

 

So let me just make a couple of points. One is with respect to DEI. There is now a very rich and deep body of social science research that shows that properly designed DEI efforts correlate positively with financial performance but interestingly, so far as I’m aware, that demographic diversity in and of itself doesn’t. And so demographic diversity alone can fail to achieve financial benefits without the kind of equity and inclusion measures aimed to ensure that a company’s employees all feel supported and that they can thrive at work. I think that the data shows that DEI initiatives can enhance companies’ competitive position, their agility, their innovation, and their brand perception.

 

Now, the other thing I would say is that our nation is now remarkably diverse in a way I never could have foreseen when I was growing up back in the Elizabethan times. And yet it is distinctly conscious of race, privilege, other demographic factors and differences. And my own view—and this is my view—is that by training employees on the benefits of principles of diversity and equity and inclusion and creating programs that ensure that all employees are supported that corporate America acknowledges these realities, equips their teams to achieve and can act on their own values.

 

And my second point is that there are many DEI practices that are entirely lawful. As I said and as Patrick originally outlined, DEI is a vague term that’s named for goals, not the measures that are designed to achieve them. And I think entities including private companies can aspire to share DEI goals but develop and adapt measures that are tailored to their own environments and their own goals that are suited to their particular needs and their communities and their contexts.

 

I think an unfortunate side effect of the amorphous nature of the term “DEI” is that it can be cast as some sort of threatening boogeyman in which nobody is really sure which practices are being discussed. And it’s led to a lot of castigation and confusion and championing of practices without a real focus on what is or isn’t permissible. And so let me just be clear about what I’m talking about in terms of defending and advocating for thoughtful, lawful DEI practices.

 

It is clear—and I agree with my other panelists—that long before SFFA v. Harvard was decided and in fact long before it was brought it was entirely clear that race based employment decisions, that is decisions on hiring, payment, job allocation, etc., etc., that are based on race qua race as the Supreme Court calls it, have been illegal under Title VII for decades. There was no Grutter, Bakke, Fisher exception to the ban on using race for its own sake to make employment decisions. On the other hand, there are lots and lots of things that can be done in the context of DEI programs that are entirely permissible, that focus on topics involving race, involving gender, involving other characteristics. And they can be tailored to the likely interests and experiences and needs of people with particular backgrounds so long as they are available to and open to all employees.

 

And so for example, let me just tick off a laundry list of the types of DEI programs that I think, again, tailored to a company’s particular interests and needs, are not racially exclusionary and that foster DEI goals. I think Erin mentioned recruiting efforts and casting a wider net. Outreach efforts for employees that cast a wider net and diversify the pipeline of potential candidates entirely lawful and perhaps laudable; application materials that underscore -- that don’t prioritize or in any way suggest that race is a decisional factor but underscore whatever importance an employer places on principles of DEI so that potential employees understand the environment that they’re going to be coming into if they’re hired and what will be expected of them entirely lawful; mentoring and training programs for employees who have faced some form of adversity in their lives, including though by no means limited to those for whom adversity is somehow tied to demography; programming by companies for employees and officers and directors that are focused on particular topics including the histories and contributions of members of minority groups; employee resource and affinity groups that -- including for minorities, women, and others, so long as all of these groups are available and open to all regardless of their identity; and training sessions that bring awareness to unconscious bias, that inform the employees of the company’s views on the business benefits of diversity in all of its forms, and that instill the corporate values of inclusion, equity, and respect. And I think at least the frame in which I’ve been advising corporate employers about this more or less go along those lines.

 

Now, we can argue at the margins about -- and I suspect that at least Patrick and I will argue at the margins about some -- at least I hope so because even though I’m as old as the ages I still hope to be litigating important issues. And Patrick provides a delectable array of outrageous and controversial law opportunities for that. But look, corporations -- as Erin said, corporations are not bound by the equal protection clause. They’re not bound by the First Amendment. They are in fact First Amendment speakers, and they’re entitled to speak and make decisions in support of their values so long as those values don’t -- so long as that implementation doesn’t violate a federal or state statute.

 

I’ve been thinking for personal reasons very deeply for the past 32 days about the Hamas attack on Israelis and the consequent war. And one of the most immediate reactions was when a bunch of Harvard students on the second day of the slaughter came out and said that the blame for this is entirely on Israel and the Jewish people, Davis Polk wrote letters to three 3Ls that it had given offers to saying the view that you express doesn’t in any way reflect the values of our law firm, and we’re not going to hire you. We can agree or disagree about whether these individuals should be tarred with those particular statements with which they align themselves, but there’s no argument that corporations and law firms can’t make cultural decisions that support those values.

 

Hon. Timothy M. Tymkovich:  I suppose a lot of it like most things in life, the devil’s in the details. Patrick, you’ve been on the frontlines of looking at specific examples of how these initiatives are deployed in businesses, I assume public entities and the like. What are you seeing on the frontline? Are these mostly educational and high level training programs, or are they something else?

 

Patrick Strawbridge:  Well, I think that there’s -- I think when my friend Mr. Waxman says there’s nothing wrong with having goals; there’s nothing wrong with having sort of aspirations, I think actually it is a very fast line from an alleged goal or an aspiration to an intent, and the intent is to achieve a result. And we saw this in discovery.

 

I’m not going to speak specifically to the Harvard case, but in some of our university cases if you got a witness from one of the DEI offices, one of the many DEI offices on campus and you got them on the stand and you asked them under oath are you using race to achieve a certain outcome in your department, whether that’s students or grad students or professors in hiring your staff, and of course, oh, no, no. We just have these goals. But it’s not about the numbers. We just want to make sure we understand how we’re doing compared to our community or our society. But it’s not a quota. It’s not a target.

 

But inevitably, all the actual underlying analysis boiled down to numbers. There were comparator numbers to all their fellow institutions. There were reports at the end of the year that said this is how many we had from this group last year, and this is how many we had this year. And I would submit to you that that just -- I mean, it’s a bit of a Motte-and-bailey argument. It’s like oh, no, these are just aspirations; these are just goals. But if your goal is to achieve or if the way you’re measuring whether you have achieved diversity is by the composition of your workforce, then I think that’s at least a pretty strong prima facia argument that you are engaged in unlawful discrimination of whatever category it is that you’re so carefully tracking.

 

I don’t think it matters if -- I don’t think the answer to that changes if you argue that it’s important to the culture of your institution that you have a particular makeup or a particular constellation of people working in your office. If you are breaking down your workforce by race and if you are publishing whether you call them goals or benchmarks or comparative charts that look at your workforce based on some sort of protected characteristic, then I think that is extremely strong evidence that you are engaged in improper racial discrimination.

 

I don’t think that there’s anything -- I certainly don’t think -- most people would agree that there’s nothing wrong with efforts by corporations to ensure that they are providing equality of opportunity. And the difference between equality of opportunity and equality of result is one of the debates in this particular area of law that goes back to when Seth first started speaking at The Federalist Society. It’s always been, I think --

 

Hon. Seth P. Waxman:  Patrick was in short pants, then.

 

Patrick Strawbridge:  That is true. I think that that’s always been the debate, but my experience in both what I’ve seen in litigation and generally in the culture is that in the last few years, five or ten years even, those lines have gotten increasingly blurred and the current view of many people who operate in this area and certainly of the activist populations who are antagonizing for greater representation is that the only thing that matters is the equality of the result. And the only thing that matters is the numbers. And it’s not a theoretical thing.

 

I would commend to folks if you want to do a deep dive into the Harvard record there was an amicus brief filed by the Hamilton Lincoln Law Institute—and I don’t know if Ted Franks’ in attendance in here or not, but I always like to give him credit or give his lawyers credit—that highlighted some very specific examples of corporate compensation being tied to the content or the demographic makeup of the divisions that they were involved in. And there are other examples, public examples, out there of racial pricing discounts. If you are offering mentors on a racially exclusive basis to people of the same race, I think that violates the law.

 

And I think in my experience there are many people of all races who find a lot of these practices -- setting aside their legality, they find them offensive. They find them in some cases infantilizing. They find them in other cases to be based ultimately on stereotypes. If you are making judgments about somebody because of their membership in any particular community, it is very easy and very quick to see how that just boils down to a simple stereotype. You are assuming something about that person’s views or experience or you’re assuming something about what they can contribute to the office based on a characteristic that is not causable to whatever outcome you are presuming that they can provide.

 

So in my experience I do think that a lot of the initiatives here are not justifiable, and that doesn’t matter whether they’re profitable or not to the company or if the company thinks it’s good business sense. I think our history has shown and a lot of companies if they were put under oath might admit that engaging in certain racially discriminatory activities might actually be beneficial to their bottom line, but the law does not tolerate that was an excuse.

 

Hon. Timothy M. Tymkovich:  Erin, what do you see as threats to companies when they implement these types of programs should inside counsel come to your law firm and have you review the HR materials? Do you want a new practice now? What would you say?

 

Erin E. Murphy:  Look, I think what this conversation is reflecting and what we’ve seen in practices it’s just a really -- it’s a fine line and a slippery slope. You start out with goals, and there may be nothing wrong with the goals. But we quickly see -- and I think some of this goes to that kind of diametrically different perception culturally right now that I was talking about that leads to results that are quite striking.

 

Just as one kind of powerful example, we seem to all three of us be in violent agreement that it was perfectly clear before SFFA that you could not have a program that excludes people on the basis of race. Yet not just companies but several large law firms had programs that were doing that. These are entities that if anyone should know the law about this stuff, it’s them. But nevertheless we got to a point where that was becoming kind of commonplace.

 

And I think that there’s a real danger in that when you sort of start with the goal and the goal is laudable and you’re looking and thinking, wow, it seems like we have a problem with diversity or we have a problem with retention on a diversity basis, there’s nothing wrong with that. But you do have to give a lot of thought to, okay, how are we going to address it. If it’s we’ve realized we have a retention problem and maybe some of that is because of mentoring, well, that’s a reason to kind of think about how do we restructure everything and ensure that we have a good mentoring program that’s meaningful for everybody because some people seem to need more mentorship than others as opposed to let’s single out the people who we think need mentors and give them something that we’re not offering to other employees.

 

I think if you start from that principle of it’s always going to be problematic if you’re offering something -- if you’re excluding people from something that you’re providing, whether -- sometimes it can be at the level of compensation -- if you’re doing that, you’re going to have a real problem. And that, I think, carries through even in things that are kind of softer aspects of the workplace. If you’re providing something, whether it’s the special bonus, the special kind of scholarship entry into the workplace, or it’s just something that seems softer like mentorship, if you’re making those distinctions on the basis of race and only offering them to certain groups or on the basis of sex and offering them to certain groups, I think that’s where you start to get into trouble.

 

So I do think given -- it’s really tough, I think, for companies right now because I think a lot of these programs are driven by a lot of external pressure or pressure from whoever the investors in the companies are. And we all know from being people who work with companies and work with private equity groups and all of that there’s not always a complete understanding of the law. And people do come at it sometimes from that end of look, this is what publicly it seems like we need to be doing right now, so let’s do it.

 

And I think that’s how we ended up in a rather remarkable place over the last five years where we had some companies that were essentially doing like straight up quotas or we will not hire you or utilize you if you don’t put people of a certain race on the work. I think that all starts to become really, really problematic. And so while it’s all well and good for us to kind of say DEI on the front end is good and it’s a laudable goal, the devil really is in the details.

 

And frankly, if I were a company right now, I probably would get legal advice pretty routinely on what you’re thinking about doing because I think there’s just become such a disconnect culturally in what’s permissible as compared to what I think the Supreme Court is telling courts and telling the public is actually permissible -- that there’s a real risk of kind of crossing that line even unintentionally.

 

Hon. Timothy M. Tymkovich:  Relatedly there’s --

 

Patrick Strawbridge:  Excuse me for jumping --

 

Hon. Timothy M. Tymkovich:  Yeah, go ahead.

 

Patrick Strawbridge:  -- back in before Seth. I’ll be brief, but --

 

Hon. Seth P. Waxman:  No, I’d rather follow you.

 

Patrick Strawbridge:  I did want to address -- and this sort of goes to that point, or at least one of the points that both Seth and, I think, Erin are getting at. And that is that there is equally a relatively developed body of social science that says the implementation of a lot of these DEI programs, especially the ones that focus on race, whether that’s trying to address the concept of privilege or antiracism, are actually a net negative on the workplace. And they’re a net negative on workplace relations, and they actually increase dissent and strife among members of the workforce.

 

And I think, of course, that is an important lesson for us all to bear in mind, and it’s an important lesson that SFFA at least does reiterate, which is that when you divide these people into categories and you speak about whiteness, it shouldn’t be considered any more permissible than speaking about Blackness or Asian-ness or Hispanic-ness. These are relatively poisonous concepts, and it’s not just me saying that. There’s social science that suggests that as well. So I think that a suggestion that we should stop focusing on this so much and that we should stop having goals that are organized around these demographic characteristics is a good one.

 

Hon. Timothy M. Tymkovich:  Seth, company brings in -- it has a pretty aggressive DEI program, maybe along the lines that Patrick’s saying, that may contain contested ideological or political or philosophical concepts. And you have an employee that is offended by these. He thinks that he’s being targeted because of his race. Hypothesize a white employee, and he objects to the training program. He gets fired and files a claim through retaliation. Is that something that we might see flowing out of these programs, and how can our corporate counsels avoid that type of scenario?

 

Hon. Seth P. Waxman:  Well, let me answer your question directly, judge, and then go back and make a few supporting points that once again endorse but with some qualifications what my fellow panelists are saying. Look, if you’re describing a situation in which an employee believes that she or he has been subject to an adverse employment decision or subject to what the strict standards for what Title VII establishes as a hostile work environment, which is also actionable under federal law, that’s what we have courts for. And there are instances in which employers have engaged in that over a long period of time, and courts are available to adjudicate those things.

 

We can all agree, and perhaps we can stop -- in the interest of keeping our audience’s eyes awake and our own, we can stop talking about whether it is permissible for corporations to use race or for that matter gender or other demographic characteristics for their own sake as decisional points. That isn’t allowed. It wasn’t allowed. I agree with Erin that there were instances in which even though it wasn’t allowed it was done.

 

One of the very first companies that contacted me over the summer to come in and do an audit of their program actually had a program in which division vice presidents were told that their compensation, their bonus at year end would turn among other things on the number of minorities that they hired over that year. My reaction to that is, look, there’re some things in life that are difficult. There are some things in life that are actually easy. This is easy. You can’t do that. You couldn’t do it. You haven’t been sued yet, but you have to stop doing that.

 

And the same is true -- and I think the answer to the question that you gave Erin, which is should companies go to Erin for outside counsel or Erin and other -- the answer is yes because general counselors are subjected to conflicting advice, conflicting pressures. The easiest thing is always to say, look, we’re just not going to do any of this anymore because I can’t lose my job if we’re not sued. And if we never do anything, we can’t be sued for it.

 

On the other hand, that’s not where our society and it’s not where many corporate goals are. I don’t think that the line drawn -- I haven’t found that the line drawn with respect to specific kinds of programs is all that hard. The hardest example is the example that Erin was giving and, judge, I think you were questioning about which is what about some sort of diversity training program that derides the terms I’ve heard are white privilege.

 

I think about, again in the context of this horrible Hamas attack, this student at I think it was Stanford University. The professor basically said if you’re Jewish, you need to stand up and go over there because you are the colonial oppressors. I mean, it's not a work environment, but boy, if that isn’t an actionable hostile environment, I don’t know what is. And no company is going to want to have a program that basically constitutes giving its employees lectures about how worthless they are or undervalued they are or anything like that. That’s common sense, and if it happens, the companies are likely to be faced with complaints, well-founded or otherwise, of creating a hostile work environment. That’s not at all what I have in mind when I say that thoughtful DEI programs are not only lawful but important.

 

The other thing I would say just to harken back to Patrick lest people get the impression that we’re now two peas in a pod is I think there are limits that perhaps Patrick’s comments don’t recognize to the inferences that can be drawn to attention that’s paid to numbers. Quotas, balancing, that kind of stuff can’t be done, couldn’t be done in corporate America before, can’t be done now. On the other hand, companies are allowed and in fact required under federal law and the law of most states to collect -- it has to be voluntary but to collect and report if you’re a government contractor or you’re an employer with over 100 employees, you have got to report on demographic statistics about your employees.

 

Now, we can argue and Patrick will bring a lawsuit that gets a court to decide whether those kinds of reporting requirements, which have existed since at least the Nixon administration, are or aren’t lawful. But the notion that corporations and employers should stop asking potential employees or employees voluntarily to identify their demographic or gender characteristics is completely unrealistic. What I’ve advised employers to do and what I think employers should do is to solicit voluntary answers to that as, for example, the common application does for college applicants but to ensure that that kind of data is not in any event -- is not part of the decisional process in who to hire at what rate. And in fact, the safest thing to do is just not to have that available to the employment decisionmakers. But the notion that just because these statistics are collected one can draw an inference that discriminatory intent is involved is overbroad.

 

Hon. Timothy M. Tymkovich:  I think NASDAQ has a recent rule requiring certain types of data collection that’s up in the Fifth Circuit, I believe. I think California has a statute that encourages or requires certain representation on board of director membership. What’s your take on those types of kind of government actions promoting diversity within the workplace?

 

Patrick Strawbridge:  Well, I think if you’re requiring companies to hold particular slots for people of particular races, it’s unlawful. And I don’t think that’s hard. You are right that there are rules and there is even government statutes that provide for that no doubt with the view that it’s of the best of intentions to increase representation or to ensure a particular viewpoint. But again, I would submit that if we are assuming that putting a certain number of women on your board is therefor going to lead to a particular set of viewpoint exchanges, you are engaged in stereotyping and assumptions about what individuals are going to offer based upon a protected characteristic.

 

I don’t disagree with the notion that collection and reporting of voluntary data is required by some regime, and it is even required for appropriate reasons such as to make sure that we are not discriminating in hiring or selecting who our employees will be or who we might be promoting. But what I would suggest to you and what I have seen at least with my own experience with DEI offices is that this is not a simple exercise in reporting and passing it around once a year. It is a continual focus of interim reports.

 

There is an awful lot of effort spent on comparison with other similar institutions. It is often the subject of individual demands or state of reports that we have to do better on this metric. We must do better on this metric. And I don’t think it’s very hard when you actually take a holistic view at the documents that are being created here to come away with the very strong impression if not the conclusion that this is not just simply an exercise in gathering data to make sure that something’s being missed. It’s an exercise in harping upon the demographic balance with a goal toward achieving an outcome.

 

That will obviously depend upon what the records are in each case, but it is -- I guess I don’t have the same experience with Mr. Waxman at least with what I have generally seen. But it’s been my experience a lot of the literature and some of the training materials that are out there right now do engage in stereotyping, and they do create a hostile situation for folks of particular races. And it is done under the intention of trying to establish an understanding about privilege or to broaden someone’s perspective.

 

But one of the problems -- this is always a problem, I suppose, for government and also for corporations is it’s one thing to have a lofty ideal and to think that you can carefully manage the lines of what’s permissible and what’s not permissible. But somebody at the end of the day gets hired to do this. And at university it seems like hundreds of people get hired to do this. And in companies an increasing number of people get hired to do this.

 

And they are out there taking actions. And to presume that once you have told people that there are good ways and bad ways to take into account people’s demographic characteristics, you are at the risk of how each of them is going to view where the line can be drawn. And I would suggest that that’s a serious liability risk for everybody and counsel against charging them with the mission of trying to walk that line in the first place.

 

Hon. Timothy M. Tymkovich: Erin, what do you see the consequences might be for the affirmative action space, those cases that -- I think you touched on that, but what in this post-SFFA environment we have?

 

Erin E. Murphy:  Yeah. I think that’s really frankly going to have to kind of be the next piece of this that gets litigated because there is this line of Supreme Court cases from going back awhile that says you can have a voluntary affirmative action program of some type within a company. And I think that it’s been run with a little bit, but if you look back at what the Court said is that it has to be on a temporary -- again, harkening back to what they’ve now said in kind of the reasons they ended up getting where they got in SFFA. It has to be kind of specific to your company and your company needs, and it has to be a remedial effort.

 

 And I think -- partly because we have that societal disconnect I think there’s a tendency to think oh, well, that’s pretty easy to accomplish. We have a program, and we’ll have something that’s sort of short term. And it’s specific to us, and of course this is about remediation. And we’re remediating the problem that we seem to have underrepresentation or we seem to have retention problem or whatever it may be.

 

I don’t think that’s likely the way the Supreme Court’s going to end up thinking about that. I think that if you’re really coming at it through a Title VII lens, remediation has to kind of assume essentially you’re remediating a Title VII violation and that you’ve actually engaged in some sort of impermissible discrimination that you need to fix. And if you’re starting from the point of thinking about it as just we have a diversity problem that we need to fix because there’s under-representation of a particular group or we’re having trouble -- women seem to leave more quickly or people of certain demographics are not advancing, that’s really coming at it from the wrong lens because you’re assuming that there’s sort of a problem to fix when I don’t think that’s the type of remediation the Court has in mind.

 

It needs to be, okay, well, let’s look at that and ask ourselves is that because we engaged in some sort of intentional discrimination. We had some Title VII kind of violation somewhere along the line that’s causing those results? Or is it just having to do with lots of other aspects of society? And maybe you kind of take that and you figure out there’s things we need to change within our company.

 

There may be things we need to do to work on retention. There may be things we need to do to diversify the workforce application and all that. But if you take that to the step of no, no, we’re going to have an outright affirmative action program that draws these kind of distinctions, I think the space the Court is leaving at this point for programs that are drawing distinctions on the basis of race and trying to justify those under kind of a strict scrutiny type regime is probably going to be pretty narrow, at least in the context of employment decisions.

 

Hon. Timothy M. Tymkovich:  Seth, you probably argued some of those cases. What’s your take on that?

 

Hon. Seth P. Waxman:  I agree with Erin. Again, I’ve said it so often in this program that I’m afraid my own eyelids are going to drop if I say it again. But I’m not exactly sure what we’re talking about when we’re talking about affirmative action, but I agree with Erin that it’s subject to the restraints that she’s identified.

 

Companies just can’t use race or gender as a decisional factor in how they’re going to constitute or operate their employment systems. And if there’s a problem where we have members of a particular gender or a particular demographic appear to be leaving and not retaining and stuff, the way the DEI programs address this is to try and figure out why and what we can do without making a race-based distinction to make the workplace more inclusive and make people feel like they’re sufficiently valued and supported that they don’t leave and that they stay. And those programs are all to the good.

 

Patrick’s notion that they’re going to be tough cases and there’s some implicit things going on such that companies really ought to just -- all of these efforts are fraught and can be abused, it’s just waving a flag of defeat. It’s not consistent with what companies want and what companies should be doing as responsible corporate citizens of our society.

 

Erin E. Murphy:  I guess I would just say while we all like to think that companies see the line and aren’t crossing the line, it just doesn’t seem to be true in practice. Many people here -- obviously we have people here who are from corporations, but many of you have worked at big law firms. Now, big law firms -- pretty much every big firm is comparing -- is looking at their summer associate class and asking how diverse is it and comparing it for other big law firms and saying how diverse is our class compared to these other law firms’ classes. And the diversity that’s reflected in the summer associate classes at the average firm is often not anywhere close to even just if you were kind of thinking about it as we want, like strict proportionality to society.

 

Now, it’s hard to really look at that and say but race is not being used as a decisional factor here at all. It’s just happenstance that all of these big firms are kind of thinking about it in some loose way and it’s not really impacting their ultimate decisions. To me, it’s the same problem in a lot of companies in employment context that you have in the universities is you think if you don’t say it explicitly, then it’s not an affirmative action program. But I don’t think that’s the way these cases are really going to play out under the principles that the Court is articulating and applying if you take the same principles that it’s articulating in the education context and apply them to a lot of the programs in the ways that hiring happens in a lot of companies right now.

 

Patrick Strawbridge:  I’ll just say that -- now I’m the one who’s in agreement with what Erin said, but I’m in agreement with what Erin said.

 

Hon. Seth P. Waxman:  Well, that’s not that surprising to me.

 

Patrick Strawbridge:  She’s supposed to be the middle ground between us, I think.

 

Hon. Seth P. Waxman:  We’ve sort of narrowed the territory of the middle ground, but we can posit that Erin’s in the middle.

 

Patrick Strawbridge:  The attention to these characteristics, no matter how much we put a disclaimer at the bottom that says “and of course, don’t use this for decision making process” is just not, I don’t think, consistent with what people’s experiences are or what the average person who’s sitting in their office who receives these messages and these updates is going to gather. And to me, what has been most remarkable for the last five or six years on this front and why I think it suggests that there really is a problem and we really should be cautious about using these categories with our employees is just how much express racial contract set asides, law firm internships were explicitly made only open to people of certain demographic groups.

 

We’re all standing up here saying, well, of course that was unlawful, and it was unlawful before SFFA. And it’s unlawful after SFFA. But the examples are too many that I would’ve believed ten years ago of municipalities specifically saying this contracting program is open only to members of under-represented minority groups.

 

And in my experience what happens is when you are so fortunate as to find somebody who has standing to sue one of these programs, immediately they wave the white flag. They get sophisticated lawyers from great law firms like WilmerHale to come in and tell them, well, no, that was a misunderstanding. That’s not how the program’s going to work. We’ve overhauled the criteria. There’s nothing more for the court to do here, and so no order is necessary. And if no order issues from the court, then there’s no cost or liability to the company other than hiring the firm to come in and change their program because you cannot get a fee award, even though it took considerable expense to find a plaintiff and to draw up a complaint and maybe to draw up a PI motion and bring it.

 

And the feeling that you’re left with is this is kind of a catch me if you can type rational where many people know that they will be able to get away with it because there’s only so many Consovoy McCarthy’s out there on that wall enforcing these rights. And if you don’t find a person with standing in a particular jurisdiction, it can basically stay in place unchallenged. And if Consovoy McCarthy is lucky enough to find somebody with standing in a particular jurisdiction, you’ll ask for a do over. You’ll change the program in two weeks, and then you’ll suggest that the case is moot and we should just move on with our lives.

 

So the fact that so many companies and municipalities in post 2020 at this point in our society thought that they could implement programs like that that on their face are expressly set aside for members of particular demographic groups does not vest me with a lot of confidence that these more nuanced deployment of these terms and these criteria within companies or within universities or within governments will be heeded and will be observed.

 

Hon. Timothy M. Tymkovich:  I love it that we’ve gotten to the point where large law firms have to hire other large law firms to audit their DEI programs.

 

Hon. Seth P. Waxman:  Just so long as we’re the ones being hired.

 

Hon. Timothy M. Tymkovich:  And paid.

 

Hon. Seth P. Waxman:  I have to say that the suggestion of Patrick that there are only -- I’ve spent almost all of my career, the portion of my career that I’ve been in private practice, defending corporations in litigation, not just in race cases -- actually not really ever in race cases but in antitrust cases and consumer cases and all sorts of things. The notion that our legal system has provided a dearth of plaintiffs’ lawyers who are willing to take cases on is -- this week I’ve been hired in three different class action cases by a company for cases brought by a dozen different plaintiffs’ law firms. While Consovoy McCarthy is the first among equals, there are more equals than I can name.

 

One of the thing -- Erin mentioned a point -- I see that we have a line up, and I’ll stop talking after this.

 

Hon. Timothy M. Tymkovich:  Yeah. We’ll start taking questions in a moment.

 

Hon. Seth P. Waxman:  Maybe, judge, it was you who asked the question about directors and is it stereotyping to think that if you want to have a woman on your board of directors that’s stereotyping. I have been giving some thought to this issue of directors and the interest in companies to diversify what at least historically have been pretty nondiverse boards of directors. And I don’t mean nondiverse solely in terms of race or demography or gender but in terms of perspectives.

 

It’s entirely -- to my mind it’s good business strategy to want to have leadership, including outside directors that reflect -- that will bring to decisions a diversity of perspectives and experiences. Whether you could say, well, the next two directors are going to be women or the next two directors are going to be African American is, I think, a different question. It is true that Title VII only covers employees, and directors are not employees under the law. But I think the advice that I’ve given is and I think this is not only good business sense but good legal advice is that you cannot -- with directors as with employees you can’t make a demographic characteristic the decisional point.

 

Now, Patrick’s point that we all know that people think in terms of -- because of the way our society is constituted. And as I said at the outset, American society is now bewilderingly diverse and yet very, very conscious, maybe as conscious as any country in the world -- conscious of race and demography. And so if we have to come up with a system in which people don’t do what they’re inclined to do as human beings, which is be conscious of differences, this is mission impossible. We’re dealing with a world in which we’re talking about human beings and the job, the responsibility of corporations and governments is to acknowledge the diversity, acknowledge the current preoccupation with these distinctions, and find programs that channel that into something productive.

 

Patrick Strawbridge:  I would’ve thought that was the point of the Civil Rights Acts, to rise above what human beings are otherwise inclined to do.

 

Hon. Timothy M. Tymkovich:  All right. Let’s take some questions from the audience. Could you identify yourself before you ask a question and keep it short? No speeches. Give me a question with a question mark as one of our other moderators said. Let’s start here.

 

Kai Alberg (sp):  Kai Alberg from Washington State. I’ll start my question with a quick practical example, ask what the panel thinks of it. At a conference last year the HR officer of a private company called Virgin Orbit stated that she was implementing diversity both racially and with sexual preference at each work team, not just company-wide. When asked by somebody from the audience what she would say to a white male who could not get promoted at that company, she said you haven’t shed your white privilege yet. I won’t even talked to you.

 

Company filed for bankruptcy less than a year later. Everybody was laid off, including this lady. But the question is in the absence of any government involvement or government contracts, is there a cause of action for an employee who either cannot get hired or cannot get promoted if he does not fall in one of the favored classes that are being sought?

 

Erin E. Murphy:  Certainly.

 

Hon. Seth P. Waxman:  That’s easy.

 

Patrick Strawbridge:  Yes. Title VII.

 

Kai Alberg:  What would the cause of action be in what statute?

 

Tammy McCutchen:  I hoped to stump him.

 

Hon. Seth P. Waxman:  It would be race discrimination. I’m sorry, but you’re white and you haven’t abandoned your white privilege so you’re not eligible for this job --

 

Hon. Timothy M. Tymkovich:  Is that one of the easy cases?

 

Tammy McCutchen:  I hope to stump you more. Tammy McCutchen, I’m with the Labor and Appointment Practice Group, former management side employment lawyer, former senior DOL official, former in-house counsel who was a government contractor and rewrote affirmative action plans. So Patrick, here’s your next lawsuit.

 

The regulations under Executive Order 11246 require government contractors, of which there are many, to do an analysis of their hiring versus available applicants using census data. And if your hiring departs by 2 percent from the available applicants, you are in danger of losing your government contract. Now, DOL says no quotas, but you can imagine when there’s a government contract at issue there are quotas. All of the panel, does this survive SFFA?

 

 

Patrick Strawbridge:  I would suggest it shouldn’t. Seth might disagree.

 

Hon. Seth P. Waxman:  Well, I’m not sure --

 

Patrick Strawbridge:  We probably don’t have enough facts to give you actually --

 

Hon. Seth P. Waxman:  Yeah.

 

Patrick Strawbridge:  -- legal advice, of course.

 

Hon. Seth P. Waxman:  I mean, if the government is basically saying you are going to suffer adverse contracting consequences if your hiring diverges by more than 2 percent from the available demographic from which you are hiring, to me that’s easy, which is the government, they can’t do that. On the other hand, if the government says, look, government contracts are a privilege, not a right, and we aim as a government to have a society in which by entirely lawful means demographic characteristics don’t become ipso facto one way or the other advantages or disadvantages or credentials or non-credentials and we’re requesting this information for that purpose to keep you conscious of that, that’s not an actionable -- but I don’t know what this Executive Order said either before or after you improved it.

 

Tammy McCutchen:  The Executive Order talks about affirmative action but doesn’t define it. The regulations define it as you cannot have a statistical disparity between your hiring and the census data on available applicants.

 

Hon. Seth P. Waxman:  Well, that’s stupid. There are all sorts of reasons why --

 

Tammy McCutchen:  It’s been that way since 1965.

 

Hon. Seth P. Waxman:  As Patrick is well familiar, count one of SFFA’s complaint against Harvard and what constituted probably 70 percent of the evidence at trial was a claim that Harvard was intentionally discriminating in admissions against self-identified Asian American applicants, a claim that lost in the district court, the court of appeals, and the Supreme Court. But the fact of the matter it was not an available defense to Harvard to say, oh, well, Asian Americans make up 6 percent of the U.S. population but 33 percent of the matriculating Harvard classes. What do you mean? You can still have discrimination even though there’s a statistical disparity. Everybody understands that. And so the way that you’ve described this Executive Order seems odd to be charitable.

 

Hon. Timothy M. Tymkovich:  We’ll take a question over here.

 

Frank Cyber (sp):  Frank Cyber from Chicago. And it’s a follow up question to Tammy’s question. Please comment on the continued viability of 11246 in light of the decision from the Supreme Court.

 

Patrick Strawbridge:  I do agree with Seth that if you’re going to tie liability or the loss of a contract, some kind of penalty under a government program, to the failure to hit a particular target even if there’s a margin of error of 2 percent, I don’t think it’s viable. That’s my answer to that question. I frankly wouldn’t have thought it was viable before SFFA for the reason I said at the very beginning of this juncture.

 

Frank Cyber:  But are the mandates that we have affirmative action programs just because we’re government contractors? Is that still viable?

 

Patrick Strawbridge:  Well, again, the devil’s in the details. Some aspects of a quote/unquote affirmative action program may well do it. If it’s described exclusively as it was by the prior panelists, I would say no.

 

Frank Cyber:  Thank you.

 

Hon. Timothy M. Tymkovich:  Over here.

 

Francis Menton:  Francis Menton. I’m the Manhattan Contrarian. Also, my perspective on this comes from 40 years with a large law firm, Wilkie Farr. So I think all the panelists have agreed that making race the explicit criterion for hiring is illegal, but isn’t failure to make race an explicit criterion for hiring even more illegal? And isn’t really that the substance of the problem?

 

So my perspective from a law firm, if we did not aggressively do affirmative action and go beyond that and explicitly hire minorities with lower grades, lower test scores, etc. -- if we did not clearly do that, we would not have one single Black associate. No law firm can survive that. You get complaints from the government. You get complaints from private plaintiffs, and you think you can defend that on the ground that, hey, we just applied the same criteria to everybody and made offers on the exact same basis? Well, the other firms are all aggressively recruiting. You’re not going to get one single one, and you can’t survive it.

 

Hon. Timothy M. Tymkovich: Come to a question.

 

Francis Menton:  Am I right or am I wrong?

 

Hon. Seth P. Waxman:  I think you’ve invoked large law firms, and so I think this question really falls in the first instance to Erin who also seems to have a particular perspective about large law firms, having been an emigre from a large law firm and now the named partner in a soon to be large law firm.

 

Hon. Timothy M. Tymkovich:  Erin, comment?

 

Erin E. Murphy:  Look. I think that the comment/question kind of reflects part of the problem. The perception that you could never have any diversity in a law firm if you don’t apply a different set of standards to people of a particular race, I don’t think it’s true. May the numbers not be where law firms want them to be? That might be true. But I think there’s a vast gulf between saying the numbers might not be where we want them to be and saying there’ll never be anybody who’s in the firm that has a different perspective.

 

And if that were really true, I think what the Court’s perspective on this is there’s a broader problem, then, that needs to be fixed. We don’t kind of have the band aid solution of okay, we’ll have one set of criteria for some applicants and one set of criteria for another. And if you really had a firm that came forward and said for us to make this decision would require us to apply two completely different criteria, which would violate Title VII, I don’t think a court’s going to hold that it’s a Title VII violation to not engage in a Title VII violation to fix something that was not intentional discrimination on the firm’s part in the first place.

 

Hon. Seth P. Waxman:  So I would just add that having spent half of my professional career in a very small law firm and now half of my -- well, of my private practice career half in a boutique firm and half in a large firm, I’m pretty conscious of hiring and recruitment and what’s going on. And one of the things, I think, that successful law firms large or small have found is that how well you did on your standardized test scores and what your grade point average is -- when we’re talking about being a success in private practice, they don’t correlate very well at all.

 

And the question of what law firms are looking for when we go recruiting is somebody who seems to have the potential in a broad range of skills, interpersonal and otherwise, that could make them effective lawyers and trusted advisers to clients. And it’s remarkable how poorly that correlates with grades and test scores. And that’s what we found both in my small law firm and my large law firm.

 

We’re not looking at -- if you look at the people at Wilmer who become partners versus the people who we hire coming in, it’s not -- there’s no correlation whatsoever to where you went to law school and where you finished in your class. We try to hire people who went to good law schools and had good legal training and did well in their classes. But just like universities, with the exception of a place like Cal Tech which given its mission is looking for the highest achievers with respect to the STEM disciplines, universities are also not evaluating which applicants are most likely to be successful graduates and members of society based only on one or two particular metrics. And that’s how it’s done.

 

Patrick Strawbridge:  There’s another question which I want to get to. I’ll just briefly say that one of the points I think the question gets to that it’s very much worth reconsidering is the wisdom of disparate impact viability, which is what I gather is really the concern and the rock and the hard place that you’re stuck by there. So if you read especially Justice Scalia’s concurrence in Ricci talking about the equal protection clause, I think there are harbingers for future legal disputes down the line on that point.

 

Hon. Timothy M. Tymkovich:  Next question.

 

Andrea Lucas:  Hi. Andrea Lucas. I’m a commissioner at the EEOC, so obviously I have a vested interest in this discussion. But I wanted to ask Mr. Waxman -- I wanted to push back a little bit on your discussion that it’s fine for companies to generally promote diversity simply based on the idea that it’s good for clients or customer preference or things like that. The EEOC has long had a position that -- and Title VII has long had the position that customer preference and client preference does not support racial classifications.

 

So I just wanted to flip it on the head for you. If all of the social science said that homogeny was good for companies, would you feel comfortable with your clients having general statements saying, well, if this person understands majority culture or the general white culture or they’re going to sell better to our homogenous clients, would you feel as comfortable that not serving as evidence that there might be intent of discrimination, even if there was no racial classification?

 

Hon. Seth P. Waxman:  Can I just interrupt you for one second? Because at four points during your question the door opened, and we have apparently 100,000 people screaming right outside the door. So I don’t know about others in the room, but I didn’t hear enough of your question. Could somebody bar the door for a second and give me what your question is?

 

Hon. Timothy M. Tymkovich:  Note to Federalist Society.

 

Andrea Lucas:  My question is why is a general customer or client or societal preference for diversity a legally relevant question? If you’re selling to exclusively white clients, we would never say that that was justification for only hiring white salesman or white lawyers; right? Why is all the social science that you’re point to or customer or investor preference or any of those things legally relevant to a push for diversity?

 

Hon. Seth P. Waxman:  Well, the question I think is not whether it’s legally relevant. It is --

 

Andrea Lucas:  Or permissible. Why is it permissible?

 

Hon. Seth P. Waxman:  The question of legal permissibility is you cannot use race qua race as an employment factor, period, whether you’re selling to all white people, all Black people, or all people whose names begin with vowels. The question is whether as a business, given the nature of your customer base and the nature of the kind of internal work culture you want to build, whether diversity and a feeling of inclusion is consistent with your mission.

 

You are not the government. You are a private entity that’s entitled to have and express its own values so long as they don’t violate the law. And so taking into account that you are let’s say a consumer products company or a consumer services company that is serving a diverse population and therefore it would be good to have people in the company without engaging in stereotyping have a sufficiently diverse understanding of the world in which they’re selling into is entirely fine as long as you don’t cross the prohibited line.

 

Hon. Timothy M. Tymkovich:  Let’s take a question here and then I’ll come back to you.

 

Questioner 6:  A question about the decision itself, SFFA. The Supreme Court took the pains to draw up -- the majority took the pains to draw up a footnote explicitly stating that the holding did not extend to the military academies. While not explicit, the implication is because of the correlation with employment that those institutions have. And of course Justice Gorsuch’s concurrence, joined I think as I remember by Justice Thomas only, was a concurrence. What’s the confidence level that the current majority of the Court actually would extend the reasoning of the case to private employment?

 

Hon. Seth P. Waxman:  Patrick, he mentioned the military academies, so you have to answer this.

 

Patrick Strawbridge:  The military academy provision in Students for Fair Admissions is now subject to an actual test in two actions that our firm has filed against West Point and Annapolis. Although, I understand your question to be about extension to private employers. Well, my view is it’s not necessary to extend it to private employers because universities were always the exception, not the rule for at least this diversity interest justification, which I guess is sort of what the point of my opening remarks are.

 

I do think and I can confirm in litigation it is being cited by courts as relevant information for setting forth the standard, at least for governmental decision making but also in areas such as 1981 litigation. So I do think it is going to have relevance. I think the principles that it relies upon are drawn from other aspects of law, including in the employment context, so I don’t think it’s irrelevant.

 

Erin E. Murphy:  Yeah, no. That seems right. The interesting question -- I think it’s pretty clear once the Court says we’re interpreting Title VI as consistent with the Constitution, you’re going to get to the same place as Title VII. And the law already was what it was.

 

I think there’s some interesting questions more about 1981. It’s just things haven’t been answered as much in the 1981 context, and the statute is actually worded quite differently. It’s quite different from the modern civil rights laws because it specifically applies to say that you have the same rights as whites. And so they’re just aspects of it because it’s a statute from 100 years earlier that are different and raise some different arguments that haven’t actually been. I think that’s been one of the -- more of the open question in these cases has been what exactly -- does all of this apply the same way in the 1981 context, which matters a lot for both. It can arise in the employment context itself but for all the things that are not covered by Title VII.

 

Hon. Timothy M. Tymkovich:  All right. Last question.

 

Elizabeth (sp):  Hello, my name’s Elizabeth [inaudible 01:34:33]. That’s actually what I was hoping to ask about. It’s Christmas season almost, and so all the holiday catalogs are arriving. And I’ve noticed a lot of companies are particularly choosing and advertising and carrying products by companies owned by certain demographic groups.

 

And obviously that’s not employment based, so I wonder about these other sorts of quotas outside of Title VII. I think as the panel’s made clear, Title VII’s pretty clear. But what about other preferences? I think Uber offered some preferences for products carried on its platform based on the race of the owner of the company, for example. So I’m wondering how it looks outside Title VII for companies making decisions based on race and gender.

 

Patrick Strawbridge:  I’ll just briefly say it can be very dependent on what the particular state that this is originating in. There are some state laws that are more protective and more expansive than others. California in particular has a relatively expansive prohibition on race and other demographic factors being used in business transactions, but it does depend on those cases. I think we all agree there is some level of advertising or recruiting even if it is intended to expand the audience for a product or to increase the recruiting base for a university or an employment that will probably fall well on the safe side of what you can do. But the devil is in the details a lot of times with both.

 

Erin E. Murphy:  Yeah. And the only thing I would add is there is a level at which you start to bump up against some First Amendment interests of the private company, and I think all that gets a little bit trickier when you get further away from traditional employment decisions or very traditional contracting.

 

Hon. Timothy M. Tymkovich:  I’m sorry. I don’t think we have time for a last question, so would you help me thank our excellent panel? I have two public service announcements. One, Union Station is out. Capitol Hill Washington Hilton. And also there’s a very fine historical document exhibit upstairs by the Remnant Trust, and there’s a copy of a 1350 Magna Carta. So go check that out when you have a chance during a break. Thank you. Thanks for joining us again.

 

 

11:30 a.m. - 1:30 p.m.
Thursday General Luncheon

2023 National Lawyers Convention

Cabinet Room, Chinese Room, District Room, East Room, Senate Room, State Room
The Mayflower Hotel
1127 Connecticut Avenue NW
Washington, DC 20006

Share

11:30 a.m. - 1:30 p.m.
Do States Enjoy a Special Solicitude?

2023 National Lawyers Convention

Topics: Federalism • Separation of Powers • State Courts • State Governments • State Constitutions
State Room
The Mayflower Hotel
1127 Connecticut Avenue NW
Washington, DC 20006

Share

Event Video

Listen & Download

Description

Over the last two decades, states have played an important and increasing role in federal policymaking through state-led litigation. Unsurprisingly, a state’s Article III standing is often a hotly contested question—with increasing attention from the Supreme Court and what some might argue are scattershot results. Are states subject to traditional standing analysis, as the Court said in Biden v. Nebraska (2023)? Do they get “special solicitude,” as the Court observed in Massachusetts v. EPA (2007)? Or are there concrete injuries that the Court simply will not remedy, as in United States v. Texas (2023)? Is there a common thread to the Court’s standing analysis and—more importantly—what does the original public meaning of Article III have to say about state-led litigation?

Featuring:

  • Mr. Kyle George, Principal, Kyle George Law Group; Former First Assistant Attorney General, State of Nevada
  • Mr. Eric Hamilton, Solicitor General, Nebraska Department of Justice
  • Prof. Christopher J. Walker, Professor of Law, University of Michigan Law School
  • Moderator: Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod, United States Court of Appeals, Fifth Circuit

Overflow: Cabinet & Senate Rooms

Speakers

Event Transcript

Elbert Lin:  Can I have your attention? We're going to go ahead and get started. All right. Are we good? Okay. Thank you. Good afternoon. My name is Elbert Lin. I am a partner in Hunton Andrews Kurth. But, relevant for today's proceedings, I am the chair of the Federalism & Separation of Powers Practice Group, which put together the panel that you're going to hear from today.

     

      I have three very limited responsibilities. First, for those who need CLE, I'm supposed to remind you that you have to check in and check out every day. And you do that by scanning the QR code that's in your program or on placards that are around here. So if you haven't done that, you should go ahead and do that.

 

      My second responsibility is to briefly advertise the Practice Groups. So, as I mentioned, Federalism & Separation of Powers Practice Group put together this panel. Practice Groups, in general, have put together some of the other panels. And we also do a lot of the programming that you see online through The Federalist Society throughout the year. It's all staffed by volunteer people like me who are practicing lawyers. And so, if you're interested in getting involved with that, please reach out to Nate Kaczmarek.

 

      And then, finally, I have the honor of introducing our moderator, Judge Jennifer Elrod. She has asked—or I perceive it as an order—that I keep it short, and so I will do so since I'm in the business of doing what judges ask of me.

 

      Since 2007, Judge Elrod has served as a circuit judge on the United States Court of Appeals for the Fifth Circuit. Prior to that job, Judge Elrod was appointed and then twice elected judge of the 190th District Court of Harris County, Texas, where she spent over five years presiding over more than 200 jury and non-jury trials. Judge Elrod is a graduate of Harvard Law School, where she was an active member of the Harvard Federalist Society, an Ames Moot Court finalist, and a senior editor of the Harvard Journal of Law & Public Policy.

 

      And so, without further ado, please join me in welcoming Judge Elrod, who will introduce our esteemed panel.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  Thank you. Thank you so much.

 

      Well, you've come to lunch to hear a discussion and perhaps participate in the discussion on whether states enjoy a special solicitude. So, by a show of hands, do states enjoy a special solicitude? Raise your hand if you think yes. Raise your hand if you think no. Raise your hand if you were just looking for a lunch to attend today that didn't have a full room. Okay.

 

Prof. Christopher Walker:  Are we going to do that at the end too?

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  We are going to do it at the end too. Exactly.

 

      Unsurprisingly, a state's Article III standing is often a hotly contested question with decreasing attention from the Supreme Court, and what might -- and what some might argue are scattershot results. Are states subject to traditional standing analysis, as the Court said in Biden v. Nebraska in 2023? Do they get special solicitude, as the Court observed in Massachusetts v. EPA in 2007? Or are there concrete injuries that the Court simply will not remedy, as in United States v. Texas in 2023? Is there a common thread to the Court standing analysis? And what does the original public meaning of Article III have to say about state-led litigation? We're so blessed to have such fine panelists to be able to help us navigate that.

 

      And I want to first thank the Federalism & Separation of Powers Practice Group for bringing this together and bringing together these experts to discuss the topic. Separation of powers is a principle near and dear to many of our hearts. And as Justice Scalia explained so many times to so many student groups and others, it is the structure of our constitution and our separation of powers that protect our freedoms in America. So thank you for those of you who spend your time studying and thinking about separation of powers issues.

 

      Without further ado, our panelists are as follows: Christopher J. Walker is a Professor of Law at the University of Michigan. Prior to joining Michigan Law faculty in 2022, he spent a decade teaching at the Ohio State University Moritz College of Law. He previously clerked for Justice Anthony Kennedy of the U.S. Supreme Court, worked on the Civil Appellate Staff at the U.S. Department of Justice, and served on the Senate Judiciary Committee staff for the Gorsuch Supreme Court confirmation. I think that's all three branches of government. He teaches and writes on administrative law and federal courts. He has also chaired the ABA Section of Administrative Law & Regulatory Practice and serves as one of the forty public members of the Administrative Conference of the United States. He also blogs—I don't know when he has time to do that—at the Yale Journal on Regulation. Please welcome in joining Chris Walker, professor.

 

      Next, we have the privilege of being joined by Kyle George. Kyle serves as a Principal Attorney at the Kyle George Law Group and comes to us with extensive experience representing agencies. He previously served as Nevada's first Assistant Attorney General under Attorney General Aaron Ford, where he supervised over 100 attorneys across nine divisions. And he was responsible for legal representation of Nevada's state agencies, boards, and commissions and participated personally in civil litigation and regulatory and administrative proceedings. Kyle George has served as a General Counsel to the Nevada Governor, counsel and policy advisor to two members of Congress, Chief Deputy District Attorney, a litigator in private practice. And he currently advises clients on state and federal regulatory matters and government affairs and relations. He's also a chemist, and we were talking about how that affects his practice. He earned his J.D. from Georgetown, and he holds a bachelor’s and master’s degree in chemistry from the University of Nevada, Las Vegas. And he served as the president at his school when he was at UNLV, so congratulations, Kyle George.

 

      Finally, and not least, but last, we are pleased to be joined by the Solicitor General for the State of Nebraska, Eric Hamilton. As Solicitor General, he is the highest-ranking litigator for the State of Nebraska and the principal legal advisor to the Attorney General. Before joining that Department of Justice, he served as Assistant Solicitor General in the Texas Attorney General’s office, and he argued cases in our neck of the woods, in the Fifth Circuit. He was also an Associate Counsel to the President in the Office of the White House Counsel. He practiced at Williams & Connolly in Washington, D.C., and he clerked for Justice Thomas M. Hardiman on the U.S. Court of Appeals for the Third Circuit. He holds degrees from Stanford and the University of Nebraska-Lincoln.

 

      We have a distinguished panel.

 

      Professor Walker -- or may I call you Chris, as you said?

 

Prof. Christopher Walker:  Yes. Better. Better.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  Could you tell us what in the world are we talking about? What is special solicitude of the states? It's very alliterative, but what does it mean?

 

Prof. Christopher Walker:  Yeah. And I think to understand it, we have to kind of go back to standing more generally. So I'll kind of give you my fed-courts lecture in 60 seconds of standing.

 

      So, under Article III of the Constitution, it says that federal courts have judicial power to hear cases and controversies. And what do "cases and controversies" mean? Well, during the Rehnquist Court and the early years of the Roberts Court, we got a lot more clarity from the Court on standing as a constitutional constraint on judicial review. Lujan v. Defenders of Wildlife kind of comes immediately to mind. But there are a number of cases, especially in the environmental law context, where the Court came in and said, "There are three really, really important principles when it comes to our judicial power. Now, we're not out there to just issue advisory opinions. We're not out there to hear general grievances that could be done through the political process. Instead, we're here to hear cases and controversies, and because of that, you have to have three ingredients: injury, causation, and redressability."

 

      Injury is that it has to be direct and concrete and particularized. So, if it's abstract or generalized, that's not usually going to be enough to get you into Article III of federal court. Injuries also have to be actual or imminent, as opposed to speculative or hypothetical.

 

      Causation, it has to be that the injury is fairly traceable to the alleged violation that you're saying happened.

 

      And, finally, redressability. Whatever relief you're seeking has to be likely to remedy that injury in some degree. In other words, speculation or probabilities aren't going to be enough here.

 

      And so, as conservatives or originalists—maybe we'll talk more about originalists—our understanding of Article III judicial power was cases and controversies only, not advisory opinions, not diving into issues that could be solved by the political branches. And where we took a wrong turn was in Massachusetts v. EPA. And you all know the case. This is about whether the EPA can regulate climate change. The EPA decided that it couldn't, and the State of Massachusetts brought suit to force them to regulate -- to issue regulations dealing with climate change.

 

      Jonathan Adler, in a Virginia Law Review article, kind of tells the full story of what happened. I'm not going to repeat that here, but I want to give you the basic story. Massachusetts, in its briefing, argued that it had standing and kind of hinted it might have some special standing. But it didn't actually cite the key cases on that. There might not be any, but it didn't go into that. At oral argument, not surprisingly, my former boss, Justice Kennedy—who is a big state's rights, federalism person. I love him for that. I think states are very special in our federal system, in that sense—asked a key question to say, "What's your best case?" and didn't have a great answer to our argument. And he said, "Well, what about Georgia v. Tennessee Copper? Does that give you state special solicitude standing?"

 

      Justice Stevens is sitting there—an evil genius, Justice Stevens. He's such a wonderful—and he knows, like, "I have an in. There's my fifth vote." Justice Kennedy loves states. He loves federalism. He grew up in this idea that each state should exercise its power against the federal government. And so, you have this opinion that comes out where Justice Kennedy -- that's written by Justice Stevens, but Justice Kennedy casts the deciding vote -- where Justice Stevens writes for the Court, "States are not normal litigants for the purposes of invoking...jurisdiction." They have special solicitude for standing purposes.

 

      I'll note as a side note there are accounts that afterwards that the career officials at the EPA, who have just lost the case, celebrated. Maybe there was champagne. Maybe that's a -- maybe that's a topic for another panel at a convention in the future.

 

      The academic commentary from originalists and from rabid center scholars was scathing that this upended the standing doctrine and not just because it recognizes states have special standing, but it watered down the requirements of injury, of causation, and of redressability in ways that would do great damage if it extended to other cases. And that's what we have like today. And we see that in the case that we'll talk about from the Supreme Court this last term that you see this kind of rising up, perhaps again, of special soliciting standing where states aren't treated like normal litigants. They're allowed to aggregate the claims of all of their citizens or allowed to raise other types of sovereign interest along those lines. But I think we'll get into the details in a minute. But that's the basic idea of how state-special solicitude standing differs from what we think of ordinary individual standing.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  So does special solicitude apply to all of the prongs of standing, or is it just a prong-one tool?

 

Prof. Christopher Walker:  I think it's all of them. So if you think about Massachusetts v. EPA and get -- drown the other. Go read the Virginia Law Review article. But even though -- so on injury, you can understand your -- one way to have special standing is if you just aggregate in the interest of all your -- all the individuals there.

 

      So they'd originally said, "It's a coastline case." And the Supreme Court -- just to be clear, Justice Stevens said, "Direct injury to the coastline is one. But there's also injury to all the citizens that the state has within. There is another." And so, you do have the injury to be able to aggregate, but you also have causation of addressability of it's really hard for an individual plaintiff to go in and say, "If you force the EPA to regulate, my property values are going to be higher." It's a lot easier to go in and say, "Well, I represent the whole state, all of" -- at least someone's going to have their property values along those lines. So I do think it actually infects all three prongs of the standing analysis.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  And one more question if you don't mind.

 

Prof. Christopher Walker:  Yeah.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  Is it different than whenever people articulate that they have special parens patriae or special sovereignty concerns? Or is special solicitude just one way of grouping all of those concerns?

 

Prof. Christopher Walker:  Yeah. I view it as one way of grouping all of those concerns. I'd be curious if others disagree. But I think it's a mish and a mash of the various different types.

 

      And to be clear, states have had exceptions for certain types of standing that we might go through long before Massachusetts v. EPA, where there's a sovereign interest or some very, very limited parens patriae interest. But I do think that's just -- virtually, EPA really just kind of blew it all up.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  Okay. Well, Chris seems to think Massachusetts v. EPA was the end of the world. These folks who used to be in the solicitor general's offices or still are -- would you say that it's the end of the world? Or was it the beginning of all things good for states?

 

      Okay. Kyle, would you like to take this one or --

 

Kyle George:  Sure. I'll take this one. So as a starting principle, the answer is yes. States do enjoy a special solicitude. End of panel. Have a great day. So thank you.

 

      But I think the more nuanced question is, really: When should it be applicable? Under what circumstances is it appropriate to set and so on? So Massachusetts v. EPA, I think it was an unfortunate case to really bring this principle forward because of certain issues. I think the biggest weakness in that case is, perhaps, the redressability part. And I think in the sense they do note that, that this standing fails as a matter of redressability, perhaps more than the concept that states have a quasi-sovereignty that entitles them to some standing that ordinary citizens would not.

 

      I do think going back a little bit further, and perhaps I'm victim to that trap set by the brilliant justice, but I do think that this is truly a states' rights issues. When states ceded some of their sovereignty to join a federal system, I think that we have to retain some check on the federal government. And this is a mechanism by which we can do so. So I do think that conceptually, it's a valid principle. I do think that that particular case is a little bit flawed because of other defects, but not to the underlying sovereignty that I think underpins special solicitude.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  Did you have any initial thoughts? Is it a good thing? Or is it terrible, like Chris says? Is the sky falling?

 

Eric Hamilton:  Yeah. I'm certainly of the view that special solicitude is a good thing for the country. I think you look at --

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  Do y'all both put -- did you all put this in your briefs when you had briefs as special solicitor?

 

Eric Hamilton:  I think you see states talk about special solicitude differently in briefs. You have some states that will actually say special solicitude is relaxing standing. When we talked about special solicitude in the United States against Texas's brief that Texas filed, we said that states, of course, are subject to the traditional standing analysis, but there is still the special solicitude that is overlaying all of that.

 

      As for special solicitude and its effect on state-led litigation, I think it is definitely a positive. There are a lot of cases that would not otherwise be litigated without states as plaintiffs. The private bar has different disincentives to bring litigation that don't apply to state attorneys general. A lot of these cases are very expensive to litigate. Of course, state attorneys general employ public servants. And also, cases can be perhaps not in the best interest of some private clients for other reasons.

 

      MOHELA, for example, the state-created student loan servicing company that Missouri has, of course, is not the only student loan servicing company that was affected by the Biden administration's loan forgiveness plan, but I think other student loan servicing companies can reasonably wonder whether suing their federal government client could have a negative effect on that relationship. So I think it's --

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  Can you tell us a little bit about -- more about the Biden v. Nebraska?

 

Eric Hamilton:  Sure. So Biden v. Nebraska is a case that Nebraska, as well as a group of states, brought challenging the Biden administration's loan forgiveness plan. And the state coalition had a few theories of standing. One was that -- one was specific to Missouri. And it was that this state-created student loan servicing company was injured by the fact that it would now be processing fewer student loans. But then, there were also other injuries alleged. For example, the group of states alleged that the forgiveness plan will actually reduce their tax revenue because the loan forgiveness is deductible, and the states all fixed their -- or at least, this coalition of states fixed their income tax to whatever the federal income tax starts with.

 

      And it's very interesting what the Court did in choosing to limit its analysis to MOHELA and not go into the tax theory that the other states offered because, I think right now, the fight really isn't so much about special solicitude. The United States hasn't asked the Supreme Court to overrule Massachusetts against the EPA. It hasn't asked the Court to walk away from that term. But the real fight is over theories like that tax theory, what the federal government would call indirect injuries. And the Court stayed away from that and, instead, decided the case on a theory that looks somewhat like you might see private plaintiffs bring.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  Okay. And do you think that the parens patriae and the sovereignty theories are just wrapped up into this special solicitude? Or do you think they're distinct theories?

 

Eric Hamilton:  You see them talked about both ways. I think that really goes to: Are states correct when they are saying that special solicitude is actually relaxing standards? Or are we just talking about these uniquely state injuries, like injuries to my ability to -- well, the states, of course, gave up immigration authorities in joining the Constitution. And so, there are special injuries that flow from the state's decision to join the Constitution and cede some of their sovereignty.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  Right. And that's what Kyle said something about that earlier. And that reminds me of the -- I see one of my very distinguished colleagues, Judge Smith, in the courtroom here today in the lunch room.

 

Prof. Christopher Walker:  Can I jump in?

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  Yes.

 

Prof. Christopher Walker:  Can I jump in on that?

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  And it makes me think about the DAPA case where it was on that: you gave up your sovereign rights on aliens, and the state argued that it interfered with that. And they relied on Massachusetts v. EPA for that proposition.

 

      Go ahead.

 

Prof. Christopher Walker:  Yeah. I wanted to jump in on Biden v. Nebraska because I -- they took a wrong turn there.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  Who took a wrong turn?

 

Prof. Christopher Walker:  The Court, the majority of the Court, when it comes to standing.

 

      And, MOHELA was -- it's a weird setup under state law. It's an instrument of the state, but none of what they've gained or lose goes in the state coffers. And it operates kind of independently, kind of sealed. To be sure, they would lose about $40 million here, although tuition's going to go up, law professors are going to get paid more with student -- I shouldn't disclose. I have a conflict of interest here that can't -- student loan cancellation will only help me. So they're going to get money on the back end. So there are other reasons why they wouldn't want to sue because, at the end of the day, the gravy train's going to just keep on running. And the state didn't have a connection to say like, "We, the State, are going to lose money. We're going to be directly harmed standing in the shoes for MOHELA."

 

      And the Court actually doesn't even go there. Chief Justice Roberts does one of his kind of nice tap dances around it all and says, "Well, the harm is actually based on MOHELA, which the State kind of controlled but doesn't really. But, well, okay, they're part of the State. And, but more importantly, it's going to hurt all the citizens of Missouri," and brings it back to special solicitude standing, even though they don't use those words.

 

      And Gorsuch, in United States v. Texas is like, "We're not using these words."

 

      And Alito's like, "Wait a minute," in his dissent in the United States v. Texas, "why aren't we talking about Massachusetts v. EPA?"    

 

      I view this as a really, really, really wrong turn. And just because the Court doesn't use the magic words "state special solicitude standing," they're, in essence, just lobbing on to the overexpansion of that.

 

      And I don't know if you all have reactions on that, but -- and I was just going to put a plug. This isn't just me. Go read Jed Shugerman's article in the Cato [Supreme Court] Review. Go read Ann Woolhandler and Julia Mahoney's forthcoming article, where we all kind of look at this and say, "There's really no way to read Chief Justice Roberts' opinion other than a Massachusetts v. EPA analysis."

 

Kyle George:  Yeah. If I may comment on that, I think some academicians have actually said that the fact that the Court is not using that term, it signifies that it's been eroded in subsequent cases since Massachusetts. I don't know that's true. I think it's -- first of all, to the judge's previous question, I think that parens patriae and state special solicitude, it's a Venn diagram. There's a lot of overlap. But there are some portions of each one of those doctrines that falls outside the overlapping areas. And we don't really need to get into those. The overlap is where we're concerned today.

 

      I lost my train of thought on that one. Do you want to jump in? Do you want to say anything?

 

Eric Hamilton:  Sure.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  Did the Court lose its way?

 

Kyle George:  I'm sorry?

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  Did the Court lose its way in finding that MOHELA --

 

Kyle George:  No. So -- oh, yes. Yeah. The point I was making is that the Court has been really reluctant to wade into this issue. They threw this bomb out there—this grenade that exploded with Massachusetts v. EPA—and since then, they have kind of sidestepped all the consequences that have come from that -- that have flowed from that. But I don't think it's been eroded directly. I just don't think they've found the right case to really expand on the doctrine. As I indicated at first, why I think the issue with the EPA case was redressability was problematic. I think each of these cases—there's another injury, for example, in MOHELA—might be problematic. So the Court, I think, is biding its time for the perfect case where it's a little bit more cut and dry. We can have a clearer pathway on what special solicitude means because the bad facts, a bad case, a bad law. This is one of those that we just haven't quite found it yet. So did the Court lose its way? No.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  So, Kyle, you think that they want to expand it rather than put a nail in the coffin and say, "No. We're not doing that anymore"?

 

Kyle George:  I don't think it needs to be expanded. I think it needs to be more sharply defined under what circumstances appropriate. There are some who believe that it should be used solely for procedural defects. There are others who believe that the states should have a much broader power. And, curiously, this is one of those doctrinal things that isn't -- it doesn't fall on ideology. Both conservative and liberal states have relied extensively on this doctrine in the last—what—dozen years?

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  Well, Eric, do you think the Court lost its way in Biden v. Nebraska?

 

Eric Hamilton:  No. And I --

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  Sometimes it's a softball.

 

Eric Hamilton:  Yes, the relationship between Missouri and MOHELA is unique and, perhaps, specific to states, but there still is a tie between the two. The Missouri state government had a role in supervising MOHELA. And MOHELA was kicking back money to the state in the end. I still don't necessarily see that as part of special solicitude, more a wrinkle unique to that particular plaintiff.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  Okay. Because --

 

Prof. Christopher Walker:  Can I just real quick on that? So in United -- you have this -- I think we hear everything in United States v. Texas because that comes out, I think, a week before Biden v. Nebraska.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  Can you tell us about United States v. Texas?

 

Prof. Christopher Walker:  Yeah. You see, United States v. Texas is an 8-1 decision where the Supreme Court says, "You, State of Texas, don't have the ability to challenge the Biden administration's enforcement" -- immigration enforcement priority policy memorandum. "You can't do it. That's not something you traditionally -- recognizable as an injury. And we're not going to do state special solicitude standing." Only they don't say that.

 

      The one dissenter is Justice Alito, and Justice Alito's like, "What the heck? Good for the goose; good for the gander. Massachusetts v. EPA. It might have been garbage, but it's our garbage now, and let's use it. And by the way, we just used it -- or we're going to just use it in a case next week." Read his opinion. He's talking about the Biden v. Nebraska. "We're going to use it there, although we're not going to say it by name."

 

      Justice Gorsuch, joined by Justice Thomas and Barrett, write to respond in a concurrence and say, "Oh, no, no. This isn't special solicitude state standing." And I just want to read the quote.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  Yeah.

 

Prof. Christopher Walker:  And Justice Gorsuch says, "Before Massachusetts v. EPA, the notion that States enjoy relaxed standing rules 'had no basis in our jurisprudence'" quoting Chief Justice Roberts's dissent in Massachusetts v. EPA. "Nor has 'special [solicitude]' played a meaningful role in this Court’s decisions in the years since. Even so, it’s hard not to wonder why the Court says nothing about 'special solicitude' in this case."

 

      Alito would say, "Because you're all hypocrites, and you're using it -- and you're using Biden v. Nebraska in a week."

 

      "And it’s hard not to think," Justice Gorsuch continues, "too, that lower courts should just leave that idea on the shelf in future ones."

     

      Which reminds me of Chevron deference debates, which I know a lot more of this -- where the Supreme Court, well, use tool -- wants the lower courts to use the tools, but when it gets to the Supreme Court, they don't have to follow the same rules. And I kind of just want to ask if you're counting that; Kavanaugh and the Chief Justice are the only ones that are silent here. I think Jed Shugerman might say they took the Fifth on whether they're actually applying special solitude standing. And I really do think that's the dynamic you have with these two cases. And it's really hard. Whether you think there might be other grounds to justify standing in Biden v. Nebraska, I think it's really hard to read Chief Justice Roberts' opinion and not think that he's basically relying on Massachusetts v. EPA. I guess that's where I'm at.

 

Kyle George:  Can I ask a question based on that? So why is there this hesitation to actually say those words out loud? Is it because of lack of desire to expand it, sharpen it, want to claw it back? What's -- do you have any theories on why that is?

 

Prof. Christopher Walker:  Yeah. I do think, like Chevron being a flashpoint for the conservative legal movement, Massachusetts v. EPA was a big flashpoint. So I think there could just be a political story here.

 

      But I think there's something deeper. I do think that most of the conservative justices of the Supreme Court still hold up Scalia and Rehnquist as the standard bearers on judicial review and don't want to turn their back on what they think is probably the original understanding of Article III. It does not distinguish in the text between states and individuals. It just says what judicial power is and really kind of rely on that kind of deep history understanding that he had that developed and really sharpened during the Rehnquist Court.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  Well, as an inferior court judge -- so when it says, the "lower courts should just leave that idea on the shelf," what are we to do? And that's Justices Gorsuch, Thomas, and Barrett. Are you supposed to write briefs that encourage us to not leave it on the shelf? And are we supposed to -- what do we do with this?

 

Eric Hamilton:  Well, of course, it's a concurrence, so Massachusetts against EPA is still good law, and the federal government hasn't asked the Supreme Court to put it on the shelf. But I do think you're seeing that states recognize they can't just walk into court and wave the special solicitude flag and expect to get a favorable ruling on standing.

 

      And so, that's why I think, for me, the very interesting takeaway about United States against Texas is, you had the parties really very focused on the concept of indirect injuries and whether the chain of causation that Texas had put out there to establish standing was enough. And special solicitude was a part of that argument. But what the Court ended up doing is not taking that argument on. Instead, it focused on an argument that really doesn't have much at all to do with the fact that Texas is a state. So now, backup argument for the federal government that got two pages of briefing in their brief. And so, you still see very much alive this question of to what extent can states rely on these indirect injuries?

 

      And, sure, Justice Gorsuch speaks negatively of the special solicitude term, but in the end, he lands exactly where Texas wanted them to land, which is these indirect injuries were proven in the district court, and they're enough to get Texas into court to challenge the prioritization [inaudible 00:31:45]. And then the same thing, of course, is true with Justice Alito's dissent. He would have also allowed Texas to sue on indirect injury. So I'm very optimistic about the future of state standing after United States against Texas.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  So it's a rose is a rose by any name. Is that what we're saying? Or you don't call it that, but --

 

Prof. Christopher Walker:  Don't use the magic words.

 

Kyle George:  Right.

 

Prof. Christopher Walker:  I think Chief Justice Roberts would say, "Read all these opinions and make all the special solicitude arguments, but don't use the magic words."

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  So that's what -- was that what you would advise other SGs? Or would you just keep using the words?

 

 

Eric Hamilton:  No. Yeah. I would continue to use "special solicitude," but don't put all your chips -- don't push all your chips in on that term.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  Yeah.

 

Eric Hamilton:  And you do see courts of appeals that will use that term. The Fifth Circuit used the special solicitude term in the Migrant Protection Protocols case that went onto the U.S. Supreme Court. The Ninth Circuit used the special solicitude term just last year in a challenge that Arizona brought to the COVID stimulus tax mandate. The COVID stimulus had this provision in it that said, "Okay, states, we're going to send you money, but don't use any of that money to offset a tax cut that you enact." And the Ninth Circuit's opinion explicitly said special solicitude in finding that Arizona had standing.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  Yes. And, just to be clear, we're not talking about any particular cases here today. We're talking about these theories and methodologies. And you know that we learned in the last session—if you went to it—we learned that judges, inferior intermediate judges, they follow the Supreme Court regardless of what they think the Court might do on another day, and that's their duty. There was some very interesting discussion on that in just the last panel.

 

      Any further comments on this before we go to: What is the original theory of state standings? We're going to talk about that because this conference is about originalism. So, but before we do that, any further comments on what litigators should do or not do?

 

Kyle George:  I think the professor's ready.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  Okay. So what is the original theory? Why is this -- why does this -- you seem pretty animated, Chris. You don't like it, and I don't think it's just because you were pointing out, in your view, it's good for the goose, good for the gander, or someone thinks that. And so, why are you animated about this? Is it because it's not originalist?

 

Prof. Christopher Walker:  Yeah. I think -- yeah. When we go back to the original understanding of what judicial power is, what a case or controversy is, it's really got to have limits. And those limits are actual cases and controversies. For some, that is a direct injury that's fairly traceable to -- and can be redressed by the Court.

 

      And that doesn't mean that states don't have certain interests that are different than individuals. I think my biggest issue with state special solicitude standing is when they try to aggregate the interests of all their citizens, and it's probably more of the parens patriae. Although I think regulatory, there's some other areas, too, we might talk about.

 

      And I think the Brackeen case from last term gives us a nice window into that. I don't want to be gloomy. I think the Court's aware that this is hard and that they need to kind of cut back. But in Brackeen, the Court said, "Hey. Under the Child Indian Welfare Act, the State can bring a challenge under an anti-commandeering principle. The State itself is being forced to do something under federal law that violates the Constitution."

 

      And no one's disagreeing with that. That's in the interest of the State. They're directly harmed. But what they can't do is bring an Equal Protection Clause challenge because states don't have equal protection rights. The only theory you have for that is if you're saying, "I'm standing in the shoes of my citizens or my residents, and I'm bringing the case on behalf of them."

 

      And I think -- and Woolhandler and Julia Mahoney are completely right on this that if individuals can bring the case -- individuals can bring the case, the State should have no role. And if individuals can't bring the case because they don't have a concrete direct injury, states also can't bring the case. You can't water down those requirements. And I just think that's the way that we have to understand case or controversy.

 

      Now, I do think there are some contrary arguments—and Jed Shugerman makes them, and you've kind of -- both of you have made them—that maybe we should read the Constitution differently, and it was built against the federalism.

 

      And I'll stop there because I think Kyle or Eric might want to jump in. But I do think there might be some novel new structural originalism arguments that could be made. I've read them. I haven't been convinced by them, but you kind of discard the original approach that we have. But maybe there's something there.

 

Kyle George:  No. I think you teed that up wonderfully. I do think the Constitution should be read more widely, particularly the Tenth Amendment in this instance. I do think that that reservation of rights to the states does play into this argument.

 

      So when we look at Article III standing strictly as that, I understand under originalism you'd really want to be as narrow as possible. But the reality is that we can't ignore part of the Constitution to interpret the Constitution. And I think that it's important to include Tenth Amendment analysis and what it exactly does mean to retain that police power in these instances.

 

      And that's where it becomes more nuanced and more troubled. If you read it in isolation without the Tenth Amendment, you form one conclusion. But once you fold that in, it becomes a lot more difficult to devolve and to really deconvolute. And that's, I think, where are our difference is. I don't know that we necessarily disagree on the strict rating of just that Article II standing -- Article III standing part in isolation would lead to that outcome. I see it as, yes, but we also have to read in other aspects as well and understand the larger structure of federalism to understand what the outcome should be.

 

Eric Hamilton:  Yeah. I'll just expand on Kyle's answer, which I agree with. I think the Tenth Amendment is powerful evidence that states are special here. And you see that in other places in the Constitution too. States, of course, ceded some of their sovereignty under the Constitution. I'm not aware of another entity in the Constitution that does that. And also, while the Constitution gives the federal government power to regulate individuals and organizations, it doesn't give it the power to direct orders to the states. So you see in the text of the Constitution, the states are unique, and that factors into the standing analysis when states are bringing cases.

 

Prof. Christopher Walker:  Can I just comment?

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  Sure.

 

Prof. Christopher Walker:  I guess, I'm a huge states rights person, American Pie. I'm all there, right? But if it is true -- I've always found these structural federalism arguments and the Constitution really frustrating because if it is true that the Founders cared a ton about states, and that's all over the Constitution—and it is—how we elect senators, how we elect -- it's all over the place, don't you think they would have also included an Article III if they really wanted to say, "States are special there too?"

 

      That's what I struggle with is, you had a whole structure. You had a negotiation. And the fact that it's not there anywhere kind of gives me pause on trying to read it in when it's a very -- in a lot of ways I agree with you. States are all over the Constitution. They're not there, though. And I kind of wonder -- read that silence which way -- obviously, I think you read the silence differently than I do, but --

 

Eric Hamilton:  Yeah. Look, I think there's a lot we have already read into Article III. Injury, traceability, redressability, those terms, of course, aren't used in Article III. So this doesn't feel like a huge stretch for me.

 

Kyle George:  Yeah. And I would also respond to that. I think that presumes infallibility of the Founding Fathers. I know it's difficult to say out loud, but the reality is they could not have foreseen every possible scenario. As someone who's been active in the legislative process for quite some time, every law that's written has some unintended consequences. And, unfortunately, this may have been one that was just not envisioned when they were drafting the Constitution.

 

      The other part to that is I would also -- to follow up on Eric's good point, I do think that since the Constitution itself, we've used case law to define what that standing -- what standing means. So the Constitution kind of just gives a word, and then case law has developed it.

 

      It's not immutable. We can change our understanding of standing through case law. So I don't think that we're locked into some definition on a given point in time because we know the words are there, and the words are immutable. But the understanding of it or the scenarios to which they apply can change as new scenarios come up. And that's the beauty of what we do. That's the entire practice of our profession, that, "Oh, man. We hadn't contemplated this scenario before. Now how do we apply this to this document?"

 

      If you're an originalist, and you say that document doesn't change, doesn't evolve, well, then we have to find a way to square those two. And that's what this is. This is a new situation that was not previously envisioned, and the reality is, again, if you are a believer in states' rights, that we have to ensure that we don't render states impotent in their ability to counter the federal government. And this is one way to do that without violating the Constitution in my viewpoint.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  Do you believe that there is any historical basis, separate and apart from your understanding of the Tenth Amendment's role in the Constitution, for this understanding of this deference to the states?

 

Kyle George:  As we look at each other.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  Yeah.

 

Kyle George:  I'll --

 

Eric Hamilton:  You go ahead.

 

Kyle George:  You go, Eric.

 

Eric Hamilton:  Okay. You do see this argument that, "Look. There's novelty to the state-led litigation we're seeing today. And you didn't see this decades or centuries ago." And this is an argument that the federal government made in United States against Texas. And Texas's response was, "Well, there might be other reasons why states are bringing more lawsuits now." One is you have the federal government taking a much more expansive role in individuals' lives but also the way states operate. You have a federal government preempting traditional areas that states operate more often now. And also, there are other practical reasons that states might not have been litigating more. One is jurisdiction, federal question jurisdiction, other than one year, did not exist until 1875, and it had an amount in controversy requirement until 1980.

 

      Another issue is the cause of action. The APA's enactment in 1946 would have eased some concern that states, perhaps, had before that time about their cause of action.

 

Prof. Christopher Walker:  Half-baked ideas aren't good, but I kind of -- actually, they're fun though.

 

      So I'm thinking about the last panel we had on Originalism on the Ground, and you bring up 1875, and I just kind of wonder what role does the second founding play in this? You had a dramatic shift of state to federal power. It didn't change at all Article III, or it doesn't say anything about judicial review, but I kind of wonder. And I'm not actually making an argument. I just kind of wonder where that fits in.

 

      I will say Julia Mahoney and Ann Woolhandler, if I read their article correctly, would say that it would be good if we narrowed back state standing in the parens patriae or aggregation sense, at least bar it when it gets to the United States. But maybe you can allow it against other individuals or companies or entities. But there's something special about the United States, which, I think, is the exact opposite argument that you both were making. But I'm curious how that all fits together and if the second founding has anything to say about special state standing.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  Any takers?

 

Kyle George:  Not it.

 

Eric Hamilton:  Yeah. I don't know. I haven't really thought about the second founding, specifically, and standing. I'll point out the distinction you're drawing with parens patriae, of course, you see that in the Snapp case that points that out. Yeah. I think there are a lot of interesting questions right now about the extent to which parens patriae still is a viable theory against the federal government and quasi-sovereign interests. Sovereign interest seems to be a pretty, I think, better agreed-upon basis for standing.

 

Kyle George:  Agreed. I think that's one of the reasons I drew a distinction between the parens patriae and special solicitude because parens patriae, then -- it really does favor the federal government, I think, versus states. So that's why I think there's a carveout between the two.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  So the authors that you talk about, their article that -- I've read their article, too, and it seems to say that there's some problem for the Court if it takes too many of these cases or adjudicates too many of these cases; that it hurts the reputation of the Court in some way. Is that true?

 

Eric Hamilton:  No. This is another argument that you'll sometimes see the federal government make. They'll say, "Oh, the states are here. And they're trying to pull the courts into a political process when they've lost the political fight already." And my response is that I don't know how that addresses the fact that the student loan forgiveness plan is ultra vires. What is the political tool that states have to undo or, I guess, enforce the law? And Justice Alito talks about this some in his United States against Texas dissent explaining that Congress isn't going to be able to hold up nominations or impeach a president over something like the student loan forgiveness plan as a way of enforcing the limits of the statutes that Congress has enacted.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  So does that matter that there's not a -- there's no way to get a redressability on this if we didn't take this -- if this approach wasn't taken that there's no one who can adjudicate this? Does it matter?

 

Prof. Christopher Walker:  Kyle, do you want to jump in?

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  Kyle?

 

Kyle George:  You can go first, Chris, and then I'll --

 

Prof. Christopher Walker:  I've got to play my part I've been assigned, which I almost entirely agree with. But part of the problem for me is -- we live in a very different world where the President has a lot of power to make law through agency action. And it gets hard for me to kind of square the reality that we have got other constitutional and normative issues going on that lead to executive branch overreach without Congress's role.

 

      And on the flip side, I completely agree with the scholars that say that expansive state standing is just going to be a mess for courts. It's going to undercut the idea that courts shouldn't be just issuing advisory opinions about what the federal government's doing whether it's good or bad.

 

      If it's a general grievance that affects everyone in the state, that's something that we should do through the electoral process. And the more courts are doing that, the more political they look, the less they're doing the role of deciding concrete cases and controversies, and I think that's a big problem.

 

      The Founders expressly rejected the idea that the Supreme Court would review every law before it goes into effect. And we adopted an approach where you had to be injured, go to court, have -- and the like. And I do think the state standing if we read it too broadly -- and I don't think Eric and Kyle are really reading it as broadly as others are, but if you read it too broadly, it's basically any time that citizens -- the majority in the state doesn't agree with what an elected president wants to do within their discretion—even though no one's actually directly harmed or the harm isn't redressable through courts—they'll really be able to have an Article III court declare who should have won the election. I think that's a really bad way to run a democracy and to use an Article III judiciary that's tenure-protected and not politically accountable.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  So is the reason we're in this position -- is it all Congress's fault?

 

Kyle George:  So the answer to that question is always yes.

 

      Congress certainly -- I believe that Congress can more sharply define that type of standing. I do think they have the opportunity to do that, and I would have -- I would not take issue if they were to do so. I do think the Constitution does give Congress the power to define the contours of federal courts, and that's pretty clear.

 

      Is it Congress's fault? No. I don't think in this instance it is for that reason.

 

      I just want to touch on your previous question really briefly -- the reputational on the courts if they weighed into this. I think it's slightly a copout to categorize controversial issues as political questions. And to be clear, there are times -- this is a political question, and courts shouldn't have weighed into it. But I do think that that doctrine has been weaponized on occasion to avoid dealing with hairy legal issues. There's a real question of law that needs to be settled, and I think it's a bit of a copout to say that's an entirely political question. And, yes, there are times it is. But there are times it is not. But those who don't want an adverse outcome will claim that -- will put it under the umbrella of a political question when it's not. So I just wanted to touch on that previous question because I think it's an important issue not to weaponize political question.

 

Eric Hamilton:  I'll add a little bit to the question of whether Congress is at fault. I don't know that "fault" is the right word, but it is notable that Congress, of course, enacted the APA and created a cause of action for those who are injured by federal regulation. And that's significant in the standing context because, when you look at Massachusetts against EPA, one thing the Court really leans on is the fact that Massachusetts had a procedural right under the Clean Air Act, and so you have seen some analogized to the APA and the procedural right that states have there.

 

Kyle George:  The danger with that, though, is that the question is: Is this an inherent right of states, which I would argue that it is as a quasi-sovereign, versus it's granted to states by Congress. I actually think it's the opposite. I think Congress can take away that power. But, if they don't take it away, it does reside with the states. So it goes one way but not the other in my analysis.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  Okay. I think we're going to be opening up for questions soon if you want to get to the microphone to ask your question about whatever scenario you can imagine for these very experienced litigators and thinkers in this field.

 

      In the meantime, I'll note another academic professor, Tara Grove, has argued that states should have standing to sue only to protect federalism principles when the federal government preempts or interferes with the enforcement of a state law. But she argues that states should not have special solicitude to challenge how federal laws are enforced because state attorneys general have no special insight or interest in the operations of the federal government.

 

      Sorry about that, but that's what she says.

 

      What do you think of this argument? Does it strike you as a standing doctrine that is consistent with the structure of the Constitution? Or is it too stingy?

 

Kyle George:  Yeah. So what I would take note of in that statement is that she doesn't disagree with the concept -- again, my original point. She doesn't disagree with the concept of special solicitude but questions when and where it should be applicable. So I do think in some ways it's perhaps an unintentional concession on the existence and need for special solicitude, but that's as much as I'm going to say on that. The rest of that question is a little bit hairy, I think, the more difficult to address.

 

Eric Hamilton:  Yeah. Yeah. Obviously, that isn't my view. I suppose the Snapp case comes to mind. So the Snapp case talks about states' broad authority as parens patriae and to assert quasi-sovereign interest. Now, of course, the Snapp case has a footnote saying that the states can't use parens patriae against the federal government, but we know from Massachusetts against EPA that quasi-sovereign interest still survives, so that argument really strikes me as something that cuts against both old and relatively new precedent.

 

Prof. Christopher Walker:  I would just add on, I have not given this a lot of thought, but Tara has, and so has Julia and Ann, and they've got an interesting back-and-forth -- or better said Ann Woolhandler and Julia Mahoney their paper out of -- they actually -- they would go further and say that there shouldn't be standing—if I read their paper right—even when the enforcement -- the federal law would preempt state law. And their point is that, in those cases, those cases will make it to -- there will be a case or controversy going to the Supreme Court the minute that the State decides to actually enforce their law that is allegedly preempted by a federal law.

 

      So there, I think, if I read their paper right, their argument is that should -- they're like, "Hey, Tara, we love you. You're awesome. We agree on most of this stuff, but here are -- think about this: If a state wants to have that challenge, they enforce their state law, and the regulated entities going to bring a lawsuit saying -- or in that enforcement action saying, 'That state law is preempted." There you have a case or controversy that'll make it to the Supreme Court.'"

 

      So it's interesting that they would -- back even further than say, "Nope. All this stuff is off the table when it comes to enforcement."

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  But doesn't that leave -- make a time period where those who are affected by the regulation at issue are really in a -- they're in limbo. And does that matter?

 

Prof. Christopher Walker:  I don't know. Is that a feature or a bug?

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  I don't know.

 

Prof. Christopher Walker:  In some ways, it's kind of a feature. Maybe this isn't the right crowd for that -- to allow for facts -- to have a factual development of a record so a judge can actually issue a decision based on a pretty clear case, as opposed to a kind of Abbott Labs pre-enforcement review when you don't actually even know how the company's going to -- I don't know. I tend to think that there's some value to having an actual factual record before you when you're deciding a case.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  Okay. We don't have anybody at the microphone still. Oh, we do have somebody at the microphone.

 

Prof. Christopher Walker:  I thought we were controversial on that.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  Yeah. No.

 

Prof. Christopher Walker:  I'm going to say something crazy.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  You all have a good -- we don't -- we're okay if we don't get questions. But it looks like we do have a couple.

 

      And, please, follow the rule that you ask a succinct question. Thank you.

 

Questioner 1:  Certainly, Your Honor.

 

      Thank you for the panel, all of you. I have a question for Professor Walker to press on something he said in his opening remarks, which was I think in sum, that special solicitude bears on each of the three elements of standing.

 

      And my question is: Why is that so for redressability? I think we've seen from the cases that this makes a lot of sense in the context of injury in fact and causation. Those are more malleable concepts. They're a little more underdeterminate.

 

      Redressability seems like a light switch to me. It's either on or it's off. You see this in Texas. It is a binary question whether vacatur is a remedy that exists under the APA. It is a binary question whether that remedy is barred by 1252(f)(1) if it does exist. There just seems like less malleability. And because there's less malleability, it doesn't seem like special solicitude is working in redressability cases. So could you say a little more on why you think it glosses redressability and how?

 

Prof. Christopher Walker:  Yeah. And I joked with Jonathan Adler before that now that I'm at the University of Michigan, I was going to have him like -- have a thing in my ear and kind of steal some signs because he's thought about this a lot more than I have.

 

      But, no. When you think about redressability, you're right that it all kind of bleeds together. If your injury is the entire state might have some injury from climate change that could be remote potentially addressed by the EPA trying to regulate climate change, assuming all the predicates that maybe they could. Maybe the EPA would make a difference in our -- the redressability also gets watered down because now they're saying, "Well, can the Court actually address this?"

 

      Well, what's the injury? What is it redressing? I think that's kind of where I was thinking of redressability. And I think Jonathan Adler, in his Virginia Law Review article, goes even more into detail than that, that they do kind of bleed together. And it's the idea of when you ask what's redressable, you have to figure out -- you go back to the injury, and you have to kind of tie those together. I don't know if that's a -- do you have a better answer than that, even though you don't agree with it?

 

Eric Hamilton:  Not really. I think some of this comes from the fact that states often will suggest theories of standing that the federal government calls indirect. And so, whenever you end up with a chain that is part of your theory of an injury, well, then when you're trying to go the other way and figure out how redressability works, it can get muddier.

 

      But you still have cases like Department of Commerce against New York where there is a chain, but the Court is still able to find that, okay, well, if there's no citizenship question on the census then New York State's turnout isn't going to be depressed, and then, in the end, you end up with more federal funding than you might not otherwise get.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  Okay. In the back of the room.

 

Matt Bowman:  Thank you. Matt Bowman with Alliance Defending Freedom.

 

      It seems like there's a common thread in a lot of these cases, even all the way going back to Lujan, that these are challenges to federal administrative agency actions. And I wonder if that's not a coincidence. Do you think that there's a significance to that thread and whether what seems to be this Court's increased scrutiny of federal agency action, such as through the clarification of the major questions doctrine, is playing a role in its deciding what the contours of standing are?

 

Eric Hamilton:  I think the APA is perhaps one reason that we see state litigation against federal agencies. And the APA has some unique remedies, in particular, vacatur. So that can be somewhat of an incentive for APA litigation.

 

Prof. Christopher Walker:  Yeah. I really like that question. I'm not supposed to say that. I like all questions. Whatever.

 

      There's an interesting line of argument that states shouldn't have special standing to challenge congressional laws, but they should for agency action. And I don't know how that -- I don't see a constitutional hook for that. Maybe there's an APA hook for that.

 

      But it does address kind of my more underlying concern of, in a second-best world, where we already have an administrative state that looks dramatically different than, I think, the founding generation or the second founding generation would have ever imagined, how do you address that, the fact that agencies are doing things that, in the past, wouldn't have been done at all, or, at best, would have required more direct legislative authority? So I don't know. But I think that's a really interesting thing to think through. And I can't remember off the top of my head who has made the argument that we should treat statutes and regulations differently.

 

Kyle George:  Yeah. And I find that an interesting argument as well. And I'm not quite sure where I fall on that. On one hand, members of Congress are elected by people from their states. And, therefore, you can say they are the voice of their citizens, whereas regulatory actions are more divorced, more removed, or distanced from the people itself. And perhaps that's the reason that there's a carveout or there's a distinction between regulatory action versus congressional.

 

      I do think it's an interesting theory, and I would like to spend more time in the future kind of fleshing that out in my own mind because it feels -- intuitively feels like there's some legs there, but I haven't quite navigated that yet. But, again, I too like that question because it's an interesting one that talks about representation of people going back to the fact that states are the embodiment of the people more so than the federal government. And therefore, if a person elected by the people act on their behalf, it's different than if an administrative agency does.

 

Prof. Christopher Walker:  Yeah.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  Okay. Professor Somin.

 

Prof. Ilya Somin:  Ilya Somin, Scalia Law School, George Mason University.

 

      When I was a young law professor, and I used to argue for loosening standing requirements, it was mostly liberals who agreed with me. Conservatives didn't like it. And now it seems like it's at least partly reversed. But I have stuck to my guns.

 

      And so, my question is: Why instead of having special solicitude for the states, why don't we just simply make access to court easier for everybody, whether they're lucky enough to be a state government or not? Because it seemed to me in the current doctrine of ridiculous anomalies, such as even $1 of a supposedly particularized injury is enough to get you standing. On the other hand, $430 billion of harm to taxpayers is not, even though the harm is just as tangible and real.

 

      I know the argument is made, "Oh, the political process can handle it." But all the time courts hear all kinds of cases that potentially the political process can address. So why shouldn't we at least have taxpayer standing for cases where there is an allegation that the government is engaged in illegal expenditures? If the legal theory is wrong, it can be thrown out on Rule 12(b)(6) or other such substantive grounds. But it seems -- I don't understand why we can't just open the doors to other people who clearly have injuries at least as severe as those that are taken when they're supposedly particularized. Thank you.

 

Kyle George:  So I'll take the first shot at answering that one because I think that idea is slightly terrifying.

 

[Laughter]

 

Professor Ilya Somin:  I find it exhilarating.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  He gets that a lot.

 

Kyle George:  Slightly. Slightly.

 

Prof. Christopher Walker:  He really gave it a lot of work there.

 

Kyle George:  I know. I'm being gracious here.

     

      It's terrifying because then it threatens to undermine every single executive action. And we have an executive government that is already massive in size. And the idea of litigating every single decision by the executive branch under various additional standing rules, like taxpayer standing and so on, is terrifying because of the sheer volume of litigation that would result.

 

      And having worked in the state government, where it's certainly scaled down, I can tell you that we deal enough with frivolous lawsuits, or at least litigation that I would define as frivolous, and to amplify that or to scale it up to the federal government, to me is a daunting proposition. And I think that's -- in my mind, that would be a little bit too -- a bridge too far.

 

      Speaking from my political hat—not purely legal—there might be, certainly, basis in law to support that argument, but I can tell you just as a matter of practicality and politically speaking, I think that's problematic.

 

Prof. Christopher Walker:  What could go wrong if every time one citizen does not like one law that's been passed or one -- goodness. The courts would have a lot of fun with that. We'd have a lot of trust in courts.

 

      I do want to, though, push -- I do think this underscores why state -- an extreme version of state special standing is also wrong. As I understand, it's kind of more like, "Well, we're not going to let millions or hundreds of millions of people sue individually, but we'll let 50 sue." And I think that -- some of the same arguments that might terrify you about individual standing being whoever doesn't agree with the policy that's been made, I think also applies to states in really dangerous ways. And, again, I don't hear you pushing for the really extreme version of state special standing, but I do kind of worry that's where we end up.

 

      Now, on the flip side, maybe there's some good arguments when a state decides to bring a lawsuit, and an attorneys general has to decide who is politically accountable, who at least represents a majority of the people, and there are certain types of political checks that limits the dispute that a court hears to more democratically accountable "actors" as opposed to just some random -- I don't know. I don't know. But I do kind of worry at least extreme version has the same problems as Ilya's question does, although Ilya's all in. You should have --

 

Professor Ilya Somin:  See it as a feature, not a bug.

 

Prof. Christopher Walker:  We should have had you up here to be like, "Everyone should be able to sue."  Yep.

 

Professor Ilya Somin:  They should. But I should turn over the podium to --

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  Okay. In the back of the room. Thank you.

 

Charles "Chip" Miller:  Yeah. Good afternoon. Chip Miller with the Institute for Free Speech.

 

      How do you square this tightening of special solicitude for the states, particularly by SCOTUS, while other courts or a lot of federal trial courts, [inaudible 01:29:14] courts are expanding standing almost like parens patriae for like municipalities, and you have these class actions or mass actions on behalf of supposedly every political subdivision in the country bringing claims against opioid industries and things like that?

 

Prof. Christopher Walker:  Have you thought about this stuff, or --

 

Eric Hamilton:  I'm not sure I heard the question.

 

Prof. Christopher Walker:  Yeah.

 

Eric Hamilton:  It's how do you square state standing with class action?

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  With the class mass actions and class actions -- did you want to elaborate a little bit?

 

Charles "Chip" Miller:  Yeah. Yeah. So all these are being brought now on behalf of municipalities and political subdivisions. And so, they seem to be getting more standing than they've had in the past while, at the same time, there's this restriction that seems to be being placed now on the states more -- seems to be a contrast.

 

Prof. Christopher Walker:  So we should have a whole panel on this for class actions because I think it's one of the worst developments that's happened in American law in the last like -- maybe that's overclaim. But the way municipalities are leveraging state standing in the way that plaintiff's litigation's working to continuously work with cities I think is deeply problematic.

 

      And, of course, that's a matter of state law. Legislatures can do a much better -- state legislatures do a much better job legislating to make it clear that municipalities can't do that. I'm a local guy -- I teach local government law. I think this is like, "Can a city actually enter -- agree to hire an outside lawyer on a contingency-fee-basis without going through -- can we referendum that?" There are all these fun questions when it comes to municipal class actions and the way that municipalities assert standing and then bring lawsuits that really needs a lot more attention from the academy and from the real world.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  Any other comments now? Okay.

 

Yes, sir.

 

Questioner 2:  Ah, great. A terrific panel. And I really appreciate the engagement. And, Chris, I thought you made several really important arguments about the Fourteenth Amendment and reconstruction changing the scope of state sovereignty. I guess my question is still the way that you're structuring the default rules.

 

      So Article III cases -- it's not like Article III has concrete imminent injury and traceability and redressability. Those are all interpretive, historical, originalist moves from a very open-ended text about cases and controversies. And so, you're setting up a default rule. Why didn't Article III mention special solicitude for state standing? The question is: Why should that be the default rule? It seems like as long as there is some fit to case and controversy, then the Tenth Amendment would still apply. And so, this also is about reconstruction.

 

      The default rule goes the other way with state sovereignty. The Fourteenth Amendment only abrogates state sovereignty with respect to what is enumerated in the Fourteenth Amendment. So, if anything, the doctrine cuts the other way. State sovereignty is preserved, and the Fourteenth Amendment—at least our interpretation of the Fourteenth Amendment—only narrowly abrogates state sovereignty. So I just wanted to ask you about those default sections.

 

Prof. Christopher Walker:  No. I like it. This is the problem with throwing a half-baked idea on the reconstruction's second founding. No. I think on the first, I think you're right. We're dealing with federal questions, so it's a case. What is a case? And you have to figure out what a case is. I think if I just go back to kind of the first move is -- I have a hard time seeing why a case would differ based on whether it's a state or an individual. So I kind of like that.

 

      Now, whether the rest of the prongs are right is an original matter or this is just the administrative way to identify a case and it has a common law feature to it way beyond kind of what I've thought through, but I do still get stuck to the idea that it says "case," and we don't have anything in the Constitution that suggests we're treating states differently there. Although, I can predict some arguments. We've heard some of them already why that maybe we should treat them differently.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  Any others?

 

Eric Hamilton:  Yeah. I just point out that states, I think, are still applying the three elements of standing. I don't see states showing up in court and saying, "Ah, redressability. I'm not going to be talking about that because I have special solicitude." It's, I think, more about how do these three elements mesh onto states, which are one-of-a-kind creatures under the Constitution.

 

Kyle George:  So I wish I'd made my points as elegantly as you did. I think you encapsulated my position on it pretty well.

 

      I think it's tempting when we look at an issue to apply that doctrine to every case. And to just follow up on Eric's point, just because states' solicitude exists doesn't mean that states will just beat that drum each and every time. We can still resort to traditional notions of standing on occasion, but if those are absent, we can use as an additional theory not as a sole theory for state standing.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  Yes, sir.

 

Brian Bishop:  Yeah. Brian Bishop from Rhode Island. I'm wondering -- one of you gentlemen mentioned a kind of theory that had been expounded in a law journal article regarding states potentially having strong standing where their own powers are invaded. And this is one thing that's gray. We're talking about, again, the state trying to tell a federal government how to exercise its powers.

 

      I'm very concerned about whether or not the invasion -- the dormant -- we're so sensitive to federal powers that we have a dormant Commerce Clause should a state, God forbid, come close to treading on a federal power. It seems to me we need a kind of almost a dormant federalism standing for the states to always have standing when the federal government, essentially, evades the police power and attempts to seize it on commerce or regional grounds. At least that would be some check, which we have yet to see on the Commerce Clause power.

 

Prof. Christopher Walker:  I think the Mahoney and Woolhandler answer would be the state can enforce their law, and the individual will challenge that in court, and you will then eventually, if the Supreme Court cares enough about that issue, we'll have a ruling from the Supreme Court that says the state -- the federal law can't intervene in the state.

           

      I think that would be the answer. My guess is that's not going to be satisfying for you because there is the delay involved. But I think that is -- there is an easy way around that if that makes sense.

 

Brian Bishop:  No. It's not the delay that worries me. But I'm talking, not about a state enforcing its own law, but about the federal government making a law that effectively invades the state's prerogative. So it's not at that point up to the state to enforce its own law. The state needs to be able to bring an action to say that the federal government is invading the state prerogative.

 

Prof. Christopher Walker:  Oh, interesting.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  So, hypothetically, if the state -- if the federal government were going to get into the insurance business or something like that or the healthcare business or something, then is that what you're talking about, sir? I'm trying to figure out what would --

 

Brian Bishop:  Yeah. Absolutely.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  -- be a hypothetical --

 

Brian Bishop:   Right. And --

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  -- where sometimes they get into businesses and those police powers, traditional law enforcement police -- even regular -- but the --

 

Brian Bishop:  Criminal jurisdiction even.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  Criminal jurisdiction where I think when my colleagues, some of them started on our court we had a very small percentage of federal criminal laws being part of our docket. And now, 50 percent of our docket is federal criminal cases. And so, it's been a vast expansion of -- I'm not agreeing with you. I'm just trying to articulate --

 

Brian Bishop:   No. No, no. And --

 

[CROSSTALK]

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  -- what is your question as to try to tease out your question.

 

Brian Bishop:  No. Right. And our legal --

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  Go ahead.

 

Eric Hamilton:  Yeah. I think that you do see states show some sensitivity to this. The Kentucky against Biden case in the Sixth Circuit does a great job of -- it just really does a deep history on parens patriae standing and goes through a number of different injuries that Kentucky asserted. And one was—I think what you're touching on—which is, "Hey. Healthcare, vaccine rules, that's our ground as states. That's our traditional space. And not only is it our traditional space, we have contrary vaccine regulations in our state. And those injuries are within parens patriae. They're quasi-sovereign injuries that entitle us to standing."

 

Prof. Christopher Walker:  Yeah.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  Okay.

 

Brian Bishop:  Great. Thank you.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  Thank you.

 

You have the benefit of having the last question of the session. So make it a very good one.

 

Cameron Atkinson:  I will try, Your Honor. Cameron Atkinson.

 

      I was struggling in the context discussing state standing. If it's still possible to formulate an originalist's view of state standing when we have an intervening structural change on how senators and reps are elected to Congress and that we switch from state legislature selecting them to a popular vote and, conceivably, you could see under the original system that a state doesn't like what the government's doing, they instruct their legislature -- their representatives in Congress, "Do something about it." And then that becomes the structural check on federal power.

 

      So I am wondering is state standing in Article III -- is it possible to formulate an originalist definition of that? Or did the Founders understand that it would be more of a instruct your legislator in Congress?

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  That's a really interesting question.

 

Eric Hamilton:  Yeah. I think --

 

[CROSSTALK]

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  And so, does the Seventeenth Amendment etc. impact this interaction and this question in any way?

 

Eric Hamilton:  I think it's a fascinating question. And I was, of course, complaining earlier about, well, okay, if states can't do this, what are they going to be able to do? And yeah. For a long time, I think states' abilities to send representatives to half of the Congress would have been a useful tool. But I don't know that it also goes all the way, especially when you then have actions that are more targeted to executive branch implementation of the law. Senators are going to be constrained in how they can respond to executive branch actions that are -- they perceive to be unlawful.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  Any final observations?

 

Kyle George:  No.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  Okay.

 

Prof. Christopher Walker:  No. This was fun.

 

Hon. Jennifer Walker Elrod:  Well, we should give them a big hand because they've done a lovely job.

 

      And, sir, your question was a good one, so well done.

 

      I need to make a couple of brief announcements before you're excused. There are book signings available on the mezzanine level just after this program. And so, I'm supposed to let you know that there are these book signings, and then the next program will happen.

 

      So thank you all for joining us for such an interesting discussion.

 

 

      This is one of the benefits of coming to these programs at The Federalist Society that feature diverse -- intellectually diverse speakers. And to be able to talk about important constitutional issues with intellectually diverse speakers is a blessing in our country. So thank you.

1:15 p.m. - 1:45 p.m.
Book Signings

2023 National Lawyers Convention

Mezzanine
The Mayflower Hotel
1127 Connecticut Avenue NW
Washington, DC 20006

Share

Description

Baby Ninth Amendments: How Americans Embraced Unenumerated Rights and Why It Matters

  • Mr. Anthony B. Sanders, Director, Center for Judicial Engagement, Institute for Justice

Rogue Prosecutors: How Radical Soros Lawyers Are Destroying America's Communities

  • Mr. Zack Smith, Legal Fellow and Manager, Supreme Court and Appellate Advocacy Program, Edwin Meese III Center for Legal and Judicial Studies, The Heritage Foundation
  • Mr. Charles Stimson, Senior Legal fellow, The Heritage Foundation

 

Speakers

1:45 p.m. - 3:15 p.m.
Defend the Constitution, Save the Planet: The Role of Public Interest Groups in Shaping Environmental Law

2023 National Lawyers Convention

Topics: Constitution • Environmental & Energy Law • Property Law
East Room
The Mayflower Hotel
1127 Connecticut Avenue NW
Washington, DC 20006

Share

Event Video

Listen & Download

Description

The United States adopted its modern environmental statutes in the 1970s. Among other innovations, Congress incorporated citizen suit provisions into the Clean Air, Clean Water Act, and Endangered Species Act. These created causes of action allowing individuals and interested entities to sue to enforce the environmental laws. At the same time, courts took an increasingly expansive view of the private citizen standing to challenge agency actions through the Administrative Procedures Act.

For many years, public interest groups seeking more environmental regulation and government control took the headlines. Lately, public interest groups opposed to expanding government regulation and interested in defending the rights of property holders have achieved numerous litigation successes from district courts up to the Supreme Court. These include limitations on the enforcement reach of the Clean Water Act.

This panel will examine the impact the public interest litigation has had on environmental, natural resources, and property law. It will review its place in our system and consistency with an originalist Constitution, examine some of the notable accomplishments by public interest organizations in the past several years, and discuss upcoming environmental and other administrative law cases now being pursued by public interest groups that may significantly impact environmental and administrative law going forward.

Featuring:

  • Mr. David D. Doniger, Senior Strategic Director and Attorney, Climate and Clean Energy Program, National Resources Defense Council
  • Ms. Stephanie A. Maloney, Chief of Staff & Associate Chief Counsel, United States Chamber Litigation Center
  • Prof. Robert V. Percival, Robert F. Stanton Professor of Law and Director, Environmental Law Program, Francis King Carey School of Law, University of Maryland
  • Mr. Damien M. Schiff, Senior Attorney, Pacific Legal Foundation
  • Moderator: Hon. Kathryn Kimball Mizelle, U.S. District Court, Middle District of Florida

Overflow: Chinese Room

Speakers

Event Transcript

Jeff Wood:  Good afternoon. Welcome to the first day of The Federalist Society National Lawyers Convention. My name is Jeff Wood. I’m a partner in the Washington D.C. office of Baker Botts. I serve as the chair of The Federalist Society’s Executive Committee for Environmental Law and Property Rights practice group. We hold events monthly—sometimes several each month—and produce publications on a wide range of topics about the intersection of constitutional governance, environmental law, and property rights. If you’d like to get involved in this practice group or any of the other Federalist Society practice groups, please reach out to Nate Kaczmarek. He’d be very happy to hear from you.

 

      Our executive committee’s main mission is to host robust debate between leading scholars and practitioners from diverse viewpoints, and today is certainly no exception. This panel event, which is titled “Defend the Constitution, Save the Planet: The Role of Public Interest Groups in Shaping Environmental Law,” will examine the impact that public interest litigation has had and will certainly continue to have on environmental, natural resources, and property rights jurisprudence.

 

      I’d like to take a brief moment to recognize the members of our executive committee who helped to put this event together: Tony Francois, Professor Jonathan Adler, Jeff Bielert, Steven Davis, and John Brightbill. Thank you all for your help with this. And John, I think this is your brainchild for this event, so thank you for thinking of the topic.

 

      One quick note on CLE credits. For those of you who are pursuing CLE, I remind you that to get credit, you need to sign in and sign out each day—once per day. Signing in and signing out can be done via scanning the QR codes that are on your brochures. If you’re pursuing CLE and you have not checked in, please be sure to do so now using the QR code on the back of your convention booklet or on a CLE poster. If you’ve already checked in via the QR code, there’s no need to re-check in, just to be aware.

 

      Now, it’s my real privilege and joy to introduce our moderator for today’s panel, Judge Kathryn Kimball Mizelle of the U.S. District Court of the Middle District of Florida. A graduate of Covenant College and the University of Florida Law School, Judge Mizelle holds an impressive resume of accomplishments. She clerked at all three levels of the U.S. federal court system, including clerkships with Supreme Court Justice Clarence Thomas, Judge Gregory Katsas of the D.C. Circuit, Judge Bill Pryor of the Eleventh Circuit, as well as Judge James Moody of the Middle District of Florida where she now sits on the bench. Judge Mizelle also served with distinction in various roles at the U.S. Department of Justice, including as counsel to the Associate Attorney General and as a trial attorney in the Criminal Enforcement Section of the Tax Division, and she spent time as an attorney with Jones Day.

 

      Fiercely thoughtful, hardworking, genuine in spirit, and faithful to her constitutional responsibilities, Judge Mizelle is widely recognized as a rising star in our nation’s judicial constellation. I’m also privileged to know her as a friend, as well as her husband, Chad. Both were colleagues at DOJ, and it’s a real honor to have her here today. Judge, thank you for your service to our nation and for moderating today’s discussion with our excellent panel. Thank you.

 

Hon. Kathryn Kimball Mizelle:  Well, thank you, Jeff, for that very kind and gracious introduction. And it’s my privilege to get to be here and moderate today’s panel on this topic. I’m going to first introduce our panelists, and then they’re going to each offer some opening remarks from their various perspectives, after which I will moderate for about 30 minutes after their opening remarks, and then we’ll save about 20-30 minutes for questions from the audience. So please be thinking of what you might want to pose to them.

 

      Okay. So first, to my immediate left is Professor Robert Percival, who is the Robert F. Stanton Professor of Law and the Director of the Environmental Law Program at the University of Maryland School of Law. He previously served as a Senior Attorney for the Environmental Defense Fund and is the principal author of a leading environmental law case book, which is now in its ninth edition. Thank you for being with us, Professor.

 

      Next is Mr. Damien Schiff, who is a Senior Attorney at Pacific Legal Foundation and leads its environmental practice group. His litigation experience includes Sackett part two very last term and Katanski v. Norton. Besides litigation, Damien has written academic articles on a variety of subjects, including the Endangered Species Act, the Clean Water Act, greenhouse gas torts, the duty to rescue, and International Water Law. Thank you for being with us.

 

      Next, we have Mr. David Doniger, who has played a prominent role in many landmark environmental law cases, including the original Chevron and Massachusetts v. EPA. He has also served on the White House Council in Environmental Quality and at the U.S. EPA. He’s the Senior Strategic Director of the Climate and Clean Air Program at the Natural Resources Defense Council. Thank you for being with us.

 

      Finally, we have Ms. Stephanie Maloney, who is the Chief of Staff and Associate Chief Counsel at the U.S. Chamber Litigation Center, which is the litigation arm of the U.S. Chamber of Commerce. Before that, Ms. Maloney served as Chief of Staff and Counsel in the Environment and Natural Resources Division of the U.S. Department of Justice and has also practiced law in the Appellate and Critical Motions Practice Group at Winston and Strawn. Thank you for being with us.

 

      Okay. Sure, yes please.

 

[Applause]

 

I’m going to turn it over first to Professor Percival and then go down the line. We do have a diverse set of views here and welcome hearing them.

 

Prof. Robert Percival:  All right. I started practicing environmental law in 1981, after clerking for a Ninth Circuit judge and Justice White on the Supreme Court, and it was just as the Reagan administration was about to come to power. And I ended up getting hired by the Berkeley office of the Environmental Defense Fund because I love California, and they said, “Why don’t you just stay in Washington for a while? We’re going to have a lot of litigation.” And, in part, that was because of the way our environmental laws are designed.

 

      Starting with the Clean Air Act in 1970, almost all the major federal environmental laws have had citizen suit provisions, and they’ve had a real impact in shaping the development of environmental laws. When a study was done of the impact of citizen suits, it showed there had been 2,500 suits filed between 1970 and 2006, and the study concluded that citizen suits were the engine that propels environmental law. They were very important in getting agencies to implement the new laws, which were breathtakingly comprehensive. They granted regulatory agencies vast power to provide comprehensive protection for the environment, particularly the Clean Air Act, and that citizen suit provision was repeated in most of the other environmental statutes.

 

      When the National Environmental Policy Act was passed—signed into law by President Nixon on January 1, 1970—there was a lot of uncertainty as to whether the courts would take it seriously. But in a major decision by the D.C. Circuit, called the Calvert Cliffs’ case, the Court said, in an opinion by Judge J. Skelly Wright, that these laws were just the beginning of a flood of new litigation seeking to ensure that congressional purposes heralded in the halls of Congress did not get lost or misdirected in the federal bureaucracy. 

 

      In 1986, when Antonin Scalia was on the D.C. Circuit, he actually mocked that language by saying, “Lots of laws, and particularly the environmental laws, should get lost or misdirected in the bureaucracy.” And he explicitly said, “We should restrict and make it very difficult for environmentalists to go to court.” Surprisingly, that didn’t come up in his confirmation hearings because this was before we -- every confirmation hearing was a completely pitch battle.

 

      In addition to allowing citizen suits against the agencies to ensure they implement the laws, the citizen suit provisions allowed ordinary citizens to sue violators of the laws and environmental regulations. It wasn’t until the early 1980s that that became significant when the Natural Resources Defense Council—David’s group—started bringing suits in conjunction with local environmental groups to enforce those laws.

 

      A major issue that came up early on was that of standing. Who would have standing? And in the Sierra Club v. Morton case, the Sierra Club tried to establish virtually automatic standing in a case involving the federal government wanting to build -- let Disney build a ski resort in Mineral King. It was one of those cases where you lost the battle but won the war because the Court explicitly said, “Aesthetic injuries can give rise to the kind of industry -- injury that would establish standing.” Even though the Sierra Club hadn’t alleged those, it was able to amend its complaint on remand.

 

      Now, I think, perhaps the most significant decision in environmental law that’s so underappreciated is the D.C. Circuit’s decision in 1976 in the Ethyl Corporation v. EPA case. The 1970 Clean Air Amendments gave EPA explicit authority to regulate fuel additives that will endanger public health. And after extremely lengthy proceedings, EPA had set the first upper limit on the amount of lead that could be placed in gasoline because that was the major source of lead in the air that contributed so much to lead poisoning. And a three-judge panel of the D.C. Circuit voted 2-1 to strike it down, saying you have to have almost a showing of common law tort injury—show a specific person that was harmed—in order for the regulation to be upheld.

 

      But then the D.C. Circuit took it en banc and by a single vote, by 5-4, in a decision written by Judge Wright, the Court had what’s probably the most powerful endorsement of precautionary regulation, and as a result, the first limits on lead in gasoline were sustained. And that ultimately led, during the Reagan administration -- President Reagan had appointed Vice President Bush to head this regulatory relief task force, and he literally wrote to industry executives saying, “What regulations should we get rid of?” A lot of them were his old friends from the oil industry, so they said, “Get rid of the limits on lead in gasoline.” And it spectacularly backfired because data started coming in that showed this almost direct relationship between levels of lead in gasoline and the rate of lead poisoning and lead in the air.

 

      And ultimately, during the Reagan administration, the data was so powerful -- also data showing this was a huge environmental justice problem because low-income and minority groups had substantially and systematically higher levels of lead in their blood, which led George Will to write column called, “The Poison Poor Children Breathe,” that said, “We, conservative Republicans, are supposed to be for equal opportunity, but if we’re going to do something that’s going to exacerbate lead poisoning, it’s going to be a disaster that won’t be equal opportunity for these future generations.”

 

      And ultimately, EPA, during the Reagan administration, decided to phase lead out of gasoline, to ban it entirely. That is widely considered the most successful environmental regulation in the world. Virtually every country in the world bans leaded gasoline. Economists have estimated that if you had to put a price tag on the health benefits, they’re something like two to three trillion dollars per year. And I’m leading up to the modern era.

 

      Look at the Court today. We have a Supreme Court that’s using the major questions doctrine now to strike down the Clean Power Plan, even though EPA had no intention of putting it into effect. And they’re saying there’s this new doctrine that if a regulation has vast economic and political significance, unless Congress specifically ratifies it or grants the authority for it, it’s gone. And in fact, the Clean Air Act, everything in it has vast economic and political significance. And I submit today, if EPA were trying to ban lead in gasoline, that would be considered a regulation of vast economic and political significance—you’re making all the gas stations get rid of their pumps that are designed to dispense leaded gasoline—and it probably would be struck down.

 

      We live in a time of complete legislative gridlock, as everyone in Washington is well aware, so these kind of doctrines -- getting an activist court to intervene to strike down regulations is -- now everything seems to be a major question when people are litigating against environmental regulations.

 

      One final word. I said I prepared an abstract that I was going to discuss standing, and I just wanted to mention the Reagan administration tried to keep environmentalists out of court by saying there could be no organizational standing. But what they didn’t anticipate was all these industry groups with their trade associations would also be harmed if we had no organizational standing. So by a single vote in Auto Workers v. Brock, the Supreme Court rejected that attempt, and that was one case where environmentalists and industry groups were all on the same side because of the importance of being able to bring litigation. Thank you.

 

Hon. Kathryn Kimball Mizelle:  Thank you, Professor.

 

Damien Schiff:  Well, thank you again for the opportunity to be here this afternoon. And PLF, where I work, was founded in 1973, right about the time—as Professor Percival was noting—that environmental law really came of age, especially at the federal level. Statutes such as the 1972 Clean Water Act and the 1973 Endangered Species Act—including the Clean Air Act in 1970—impose significant new burdens. But these two statutes, in particular, impose burdens with the potential for steep civil and criminal penalties on activities that many people would consider just ordinary land use. So for a group like PLF, interested in protecting private property rights, it’s no surprise that we would become very involved in environmental litigation.

 

      And in fact, in the 50 years since our founding, a number of our Supreme Court cases have been about environmental law, some directly concerned with the interpretation of environmental statutes and some cases dealing with the takings implication of environmentally motivated land use litigation. But I think groups like PLF have been successful in making environmental law more respectful of private property rights because we’ve implemented what I consider to be strategic long-term public interest litigation campaigns. Now, to successfully wage such a campaign, I think you need three things in ascending order of importance: money, legal personnel, and a judiciary that’s receptive to strategically selected and timed legal arguments.

 

      So first, as to money, I think in a country of our size and wealth, money’s never going to be a problem, especially for financing public interest litigation that’s interested in high-profile, high-impact Supreme Court cases. After all, the direct costs of litigating an appellate case are really not that great, and if the attorneys staffing the case are willing to work at public interest rates, I think one can easily litigate to the Supreme Court on the cheap.

 

      Second, as to legal personnel, I think it goes without saying that high-level, public interest litigation has always been attractive to talented recent law school graduates. And that’s as much true for right-leaning as it is for left-leaning public interest groups.

 

      But finally, again, what I consider to be the most important factor is a judiciary that is receptive to legal change. You simply cannot change the law through public interest litigation if the courts are not at least sympathetic to the underlying policies that you’re trying to advance and, at the same time, prepared to accept the legal arguments necessary to effect that policy change.

 

      So now, the judiciary certainly isn’t static, and at any given time, courts are more or less open to moving the law in a certain fashion. And that openness depends, in large part, on the type of legal arguments advance, along with the institutional constraints of the judiciary. So a public interest litigation campaign that’s going to be successful must recognize that an intellectually compelling legal argument is often a necessary but rarely a sufficient condition to success.

 

      For example, I think that one could plausibly argue that a lot of administrative action violates the liberty of contract, but that argument hasn’t won in this century and probably will never win again. But one might also argue that that same administrative action threatens the separation of powers, that it threatens federalism, that it goes well beyond the, supposedly, authorizing underlying statute. Now, these two can be compelling arguments and are certainly less ambitious than those grounded in Lochnerism but, again, the timing has to be right. And at least in environmental law, until the late 1990s, the property rights movement’s time hadn’t yet matured.

 

      For example, PLF’s very first Supreme Court case—which we’d like to forget about—Costle v. PLF, a 1980 ruling concerning when EPA must provide a public hearing before issuing a Clean Water Act permit. It was a 9-0 loss for us, with the Court concluding that the agency doesn’t need to always offer such a hearing, even if there are material facts in dispute.

 

      And just a few years later, in 1986, the Supreme Court in U.S. v. Riverside Bayview Homes, addressing for the first time the geographic scope of the Clean Water Act, ruled 9-0 against the property owner, holding that the Act regulates at least some wetlands, despite the fact that the statute mentions waters of the United States not wetlands of the United States and despite the Court’s acknowledgment that wetlands are not ordinarily referred to as waters. 

 

      But then Justice Scalia joined the Court, and I think things began to change. In fact, 1987, when he joined the Court, saw PLF’s Supreme Court victory, Nollan v. California Coast Commission, which was a 5-4 ruling written by Justice Scalia that provided property owners with meaningful protection against extortionate land usage actions. In that case, it was a demand to dedicate private property for enhanced public beach access.

 

      And over the next decade or so, the Court gradually became more receptive to the separation of powers, federalism, and textualism arguments that groups like PLF wanted to make. And in environmental law, in particular, this receptivity bore fruit first in the Supreme Court’s 2001 decision in SWANCC. This was a 5-4 ruling by Chief Justice Rehnquist, which invalidated the Army Corps assertion of Clean Water Act authority over certain abandoned gravel mining pits. And it did so by limiting the statute’s reach to its textual delimitation of Navajo waters but also taking into account Congress’s traditional authority under the Commerce Clause and its respect for the traditional federal/state balance of power.

 

      We at PLF took this as a signal that the time was ripe for a litigation campaign to reform the Clean Water Act because here was a statute that cast a nationwide regulatory net—often snagging ordinary American citizens performing everyday land use activities—that imposed significant permitting costs that threatened significant, sometimes ruinous, civil and criminal penalties for violation of its strict liability standards, and that, in its wetlands regulatory form, really turned the Tenth Amendment on its head, converting EPA and the Army Corps into federal zoning administrators. 

 

      So our 20-year effort to reform the Act through litigation began in earnest with our 2006 win in Rapanos v. United States, continuing with our 2012 win in Sackett and our 2016 win in Hawkes, and culminating this year in our second win in Sackett. Now, again, I attribute our swing of successes mainly to the timely deployment of a strategic litigation plan whose underlying themes would find a welcome audience on today’s bench but that would also respect the judiciary’s institutional limitations. But the arguments that won the day in these cases were essentially textualist and anti-bureaucratic, and those are two things that weren’t very popular in the Supreme Court when many federal environmental laws were enacted, but they have become ascendant today.

 

      And indeed, our wins in the first Sackett and Hawkes cases were unanimous, reflecting a profound shift on the Court towards facilitating greater judicial review of administrative action—a shift that I think was motivated in part by a growing recognition across the bench that there’s a lack of fairness and predictability in the administrative state. And even our substantive win in Sackett two that narrow the scope of navigable waters under the Clean Water Act was unanimous in its rejections of EPA’s preferred standard and unanimous in the Court’s conclusion that the Sackett’s property is not regulated by the Act.

 

      Now, in conclusion, I know that there were three factors for a successful campaign, but there’s actually sort of a 3.5 factor, which is good client selection. In Rapanos, Hawkes, and Sackett, all these cases were those of small individual landowners fighting against what I call the federal wetlands regulatory complex. Each case had a good story to tell, a story that highlighted the inequities of the administrative state, and thus made the Supreme Court want to rule our way. This in turn increased the chance that the Court would ultimately grant cert and then operationalize our Clean Water Act reform plan.

 

Hon. Kathryn Kimball Mizelle:  David?

 

David Doniger:  So now for something completely different.

 

[Laughter]

 

David Doniger:  So I wanted to start -- I want to make three categories of points, but I’ll start with origins. Why did Congress create citizen suits and the courts—as Bob was explaining—recognize their importance in the ‘70s? Well, you all know of the phenomena of regulatory capture. The older regulatory agencies, generally speaking, are charged with regulating a set of industries or companies in a field, and there is nobody else. It’s a bilateral relationship, and it tends to result in capture or accommodation to the -- in many people’s views, too much accommodation to the wishes and wills of the regulated industry.

 

      Well, conscious of that in the late ‘60s/early ‘70’s when these new laws were being considered, Congress made a deliberate decision to try to balance this by giving legal rights to the beneficiaries of the protection that these laws were intended to provide—the reduction in air pollution, water pollution, etc. And in order to make that -- in order to give some heft or some weight to the participation by citizen groups or their representatives, you have to give them legal rights, too. So we have had, from the beginning of these laws, the right to challenge final decisions on a par with the regulated industries, again, providing that we can show that we represent people who are adversely affected by the deficiencies that we are complaining about so we meet standing requirements.

 

      And the citizen supervisions are there to deal with delay—lapses of action by the agencies when Congress has given them express timetables or express duties that follow from factual findings, like if you find that a certain pollutant is dangerous then that triggers a timeframe for issuing regulations about it. And the effect of all this is to keep -- is to avoid capture, to keep the agency suspended. Imagine two magnets and the agency is suspended in between these magnets and subject to pull from the industry side and from the environmental group side.

 

      So I think of that -- I think of what we do, in that sense, as representing the interests of the beneficiaries. We sometimes call that the public interest or the interest of publics—identifiable segments of the public. And so, I think that’s a very important thing to recognize. Why did Congress structure the laws this way, and how have they worked out? They have kept the system dynamic and away from capture to an extent not seen in 50-year-old regimes for regulating trade or communications or other such areas. 

 

      Second point. I want to take issue with the suggestion that what Damien and I are both doing is public interest litigation. I mean, you describe it, Damien, very expressly as looking to defend private interests—private property interests—and you had a telling phrase: client selection, finding the right client to be—I would guess—a poster child -- an attractive poster child for these private property interests. I just don’t think that’s the same as attempting to vindicate the interests of the beneficiaries of the regulations—those who are, in the case of the Clean Water Act, harmed by the downstream water pollution impacts of mismanaging, from my point of view, wetlands.

 

      And the whole point of pollution statutes is that they are attempting to solve a market failure problem, that pollution itself isn’t priced in the marketplace. If you can dump the pollution or the -- into the air or into the water for free, you have no economic interest to manage it or clean it up. These laws are supposed to solve that problem. You can argue that there are other systems for doing that, but that’s the function of them. And that is not, in my opinion, what PLF and similar organizations do. They defend private property interests in lieu of the -- and often with the financial backing of corporate interests that would benefit from the same doctrines. So that’s my rant on that point.

 

      And you made another point, Damien, about the importance of having a long-term campaign and getting the receptive judges. Well, congratulations, Federalist Society. You’ve been rather successful—at least at the top bench in years of late—in getting a receptive judiciary. But let’s not be too highfalutin about what’s involved. To me, it’s clothing nakedly private interested goals in highfalutin “constitutiony” arguments. You know the term that Colbert coined some years ago was “truthiness,” so I would like to propose a “constitutioniness” type of argument. And I think the major questions doctrine and some of the nondelegation doctrines, they don’t really come from -- derive from purists looking at the Constitution and thinking, “What’s the best way to govern?” No. They’re arguments to clothe attacks on modern government, on the capacity of modern government. You might call it the administrative state. I call it modern government.

 

      Why does Congress enlist administrative agencies? Well, even in what I would consider the good old days of the late ‘60s/early ‘70s when Congress was on one of its three or four big historical reform binges, so to speak -- even when they were active, they had no ability to -- they didn’t have the bandwidth or the expertise or the foresight to understand how many different kinds of air pollutants there were going to be, with what characteristics, and coming from how many different kinds of industries would emit them. And they wouldn’t know when science would emerge that causes something to be seen as dangerous that was previously thought as safe or even vice versa.

 

      But they needed -- for the government to function, you could not have all of these decisions made by Congress. They can’t even -- they can’t even pass continuing resolutions now. That’s how enfeebled they are. And we need -- if we’re going to keep up with the challenges of the modern world, we need a modern government. Now, I think there are some very important democratic safeguards in modern government of this kind. One of them is the whole Notice and Comment system, which requires that they take stakeholder input and information and consider the views and the ability of industries, other private interests, or interests like ours to go to court and get, at least, some degree of scrutiny of bad decisions or corrupt decisions from the agencies. So those are really important safeguards to keep the system democratic.

 

      One last comment. Chevron. I didn’t know what I was getting into when I took that case. NRDC v. Gorsuch was the original case, by the way. Justice Gorsuch’s mom was the beneficiary of the Chevron decision. Her decision would have been struck down if Justice Gorsuch’s kind of doctrines now had been in effect at the time. But Justice Stevens was doing something else. He looked at the -- at some of these same D.C. Circuit judges that Bob has mentioned, and he said -- and it was true in those cases. There were three previous decisions about the definition of an air pollution source. And he said, “Judges, you are meddling too much in what are essentially policy decisions. They should be left to the political branches. Judges should not be importing their policy views of what’s the best way to control air pollution or not into a question of statutory construction. And if there’s latitude for a policy judgment left by Congress, it’s the agency, within bounds of reason, that should have the first -- should decide that question.” That’s why I lost that case because they gave the agency that latitude.

 

      But in the initial years, it was embraced by all the conservative judges and scholars as the right way to go. And only in, basically, the late Clinton, maybe early or late Obama period, did your movement decide that this was a terrible travesty, and it should be reversed as violating separation of powers—and god knows what else—and the role of judges. These are all rationalizations for a discomfort that the conservative movement has acquired when policy judgments are made by more liberal governments. Think about whether you want the same constraint if there are ever conservative Executive Branches again.

 

      So I would -- I don’t know what to expect in Loper Bright and Relentless. Relentless would’ve been the absolute best name for a case of this kind ever.

 

[Laughter]

 

      But the question I would pose is if one is going to change or wholesale abandon the Chevron doctrine, what will be the new rule? Will it be: judges should go back to inserting their policy judgments? Do we want Judge Kacsmaryk in Texas to be second-guessing the FDA on the safety and effectiveness of the morning after pill? You might. I don’t. And do you want the randomness of outcomes that comes from the selection of judges in different districts?

 

      So I think we need to keep policymaking in the hands of political branches and keep -- and I say that even knowing that there are times, like in the Trump administration and the Reagan administration, where the policy direction of those administrations was completely uncomfortable to me. But I still think it’s better. So that’s why we filed a brief in Loper Bright, saying, “We’re the party that lost in Chevron, but we think you should be very careful about opening the floodgates to what Stevens was trying to shut down, which is lower court policymaking in the guise of deciding questions of law.” So I’ll stop there, and I’d love to engage with you all on this.

 

Hon. Kathryn Kimball Mizelle:  Thank you, David. Stephanie?

 

Stephanie Maloney:  Thanks, Judge. And if David has those thoughts about PLF, then I could imagine his thoughts on the Chamber, so I’m looking forward to hearing those.

 

[CROSSTALK]

 

David Doniger:  You’re at least a business organization.

 

Stephanie Maloney:  [Laughter] I just want to start with some words of thanks to The Federalist Society and my fellow panelists for today’s conversation. It’s really a pleasure to be here with you all. As many of you in this room know, the U.S. Chamber Litigation Center brings direct legal challenges against federal agencies for their overreach. We fight for business and free enterprise in the courts. Bringing lawsuits is one of the most important tools we have to combat the enormous regulatory burdens that businesses are facing today. If we can knock out these regulatory obstacles, then we clear the way for businesses, large and small, to keep doing what they do best. So we’re taking that responsibility seriously.

 

      Since last summer, we’ve filed eight new lawsuits. Just today, we sued the NLRB over their Joint-Employer Rule. We’ve successfully sued EPA and the Army Corps of Engineers over their WOTUS Rule. We’ve sued the SEC twice. We’ve sued the State of Connecticut, and we’ve sued the FTC, the CFPB, and HHS, so quite a bit of the agency alphabet soup.

 

[Laughter]

 

Stephanie Maloney:  I’d like to start off this afternoon by telling you just a little bit more about our energy and environment litigation and then explain how that fits into our broader fight against government overreach. As a historical matter, most of the Litigation Center’s regulatory challenges have involved energy and environment issues. Currently, we have ten pending lawsuits where EPA is a party, although quite a few are in various stages of abeyance. But we regularly litigate perennial issues under the Clean Water Act and the Clean Air Act, such as the various standards EPA sets for national ambient air quality, EPA’s emission standards for power plants, and the definition of the Waters of the United States.

 

      At least on WOTUS, we’ve recently managed to secure some real clarity around the text of the Clean Water Act. For decades, WOTUS regulations have been the subject of regulatory and legal ping-pong. The agencies tasked with enforcing it and the courts tasked with interpreting it have wrestled with what exactly is a WOTUS? As a result, businesses of all sizes, along with individual landowners, have been put in a precarious situation, subjected to vague and changing rules that often require them to hire expensive experts and consultants that will advise on whether they need permits to use their own land. If they guess wrong—as Damien mentioned—they face potentially severe, even criminal, penalties.

 

      PLF litigation, on behalf of the Sacketts—and unanimous decision in the Supreme Court—demonstrates those exact difficulties, and it has helped to define the statutory provisions that limit the geographic reach of the Clean Water Act and thereby limit EPA. But PLF has not had to litigate alone. Earlier this year, not content to wait for guidance from the Supreme Court and Sackett, the Biden administration chose to finalize a new WOTUS rule. The Chamber led a coalition to challenge that rule. We partnered with the Kentucky Chamber, along with the Georgia Chamber and other associations, and we coordinated with the State of Kentucky to file a lawsuit in the Eastern District of Kentucky. Our lawsuit highlighted the rule’s impacts, particularly on small businesses.

 

      For example, we described mining operations, an aluminum factory, and a Kentucky-based pig farm that would be forced to expend time and resources, assessing whether their activities implicated the new vague multi-factor standards of the WOTUS Rule. Given the immediacy of those harms, we also moved for an injunction. In May of this year, the Sixth Circuit granted us an injunction, pending appeal, that prevents EPA and the Army from enforcing the rule against members of the Chamber and our coalition partners. Given the various definitions of the rule that now apply amongst the various states, EPA has posted a nationwide map, which shows the particular WOTUS Rule that applies in a particular state. And our favorite feature of the map is that it expressly recognizes, no matter the state, the members of the Chamber and our coalition partners are protected by our injunction.

 

      So this sort of environmental litigation remains important. But today, when we think about the agencies and the rules that are making headlines and keeping general counsels up at night, it’s rules coming from the SEC, FTC, CFPB, even the Federal Acquisition Regulatory, or FAR, Council. The present administration has increasingly empowered executive agencies to stray far outside their areas of expertise, resulting in a host of legally vulnerable regulations.

 

      For example, you have the SEC trying to set climate action and human resources policies, while you have the FTC trying to set workforce policy by proposing to prohibit non-compete agreements nationwide. This administrative mission creep is troubling. Agencies are increasingly asserting power beyond what Congress could reasonably be understood to have granted. Whatever you think about the underlying merits of this social agenda, such agency actions raise significant separation of powers concerns. Simply put, it’s the question of who decides.

 

      Businesses value predictability and stability in the law. Congress promotes that kind of regulatory environment when it appropriately exercises its Article I powers, enacting statutes that clearly define legal responsibilities. The role of the Executive and its administrative agencies is to execute those clear statutes, making relatively minor, gap-filling, interpretive judgments, and the judiciary must say what the law is, using traditional tools of statutory construction to faithfully apply statutes as written. Thankfully, from district courts to the Supreme Court, we have a judiciary that seems inclined to do just that.

 

      At the same time, we’re seeing a federal regulatory agenda more aggressive than ever. We’re seeing a judiciary more inclined to curb it back. We have courts that are skeptical of agency mission creep and that have expressed a willingness to enforce those structural limitations so that each branch of government stays in its respective lane and administrative agencies do not impose regulatory burdens that exceed lawful bounds. Now is the time to make favorable precedent.

 

      This is an environmental law panel, but as all of you know, so much of environmental law centers on administrative law. If we can develop favorable administrative law in any context, it will give us real leverage in our fights against EPA and other agencies. By way of example, I’ll mention just two recent wins we’ve had, reining in administrative overreach.

 

      First, just last month, we set favorable precedent for arbitrary and capricious challenges. We handed the SEC an important legal defeat by scuttling the agency’s stock buyback rule. The SEC, in May, finalized a rule that required public companies to disclose their daily share repurchases and the reason for buying back that stock. We sued, arguing that the SEC had violated the APA by failing to quantify the rules, costs, and benefits. The Fifth Circuit agreed and skewered the SEC for failing to substantiate the rule’s purported benefits. The panel remanded the rule to the agency to correct its defect within 30 days, and we’re pretty sure it won’t be able to.

 

      Second, earlier this year, we developed helpful precedent on when an agency manual update can be challenged as final agency action and won on major questions doctrine. This was in our challenge to the CFPB’s update to the Unfair, Deceptive, or Abusive Acts or Practices section of its Supervision and Examination Manual. The district court found the manual update adopted a new binding legal position on UDAAP prohibitions that made it final agency action. The court then agreed that the action exceeds the CFPB’s statutory authority, applying the major questions doctrine, and finding no clear congressional authorization for the vast economic and political power claimed by the CFPB. As a result, the court vacated the manual update and enjoined the CFPB from pursuing any action against any of our members based on the update.

 

      Going forward, these lawsuits are really the tip of the iceberg. We’re expecting many more rules to be finalized this year and next. In fact, we keep a running list of rules to challenge as they’re proposed. We won’t be able to sue over all of them, but we expect to sue over some. A few are the familiar issues I mentioned at the top, the PM and Ozonex. Others are new, such as EPA’s efforts to designate PFOS and PFOA as hazardous under CERCLA. We regularly talk at the Litigation Center about this being an important moment, both because of the need to push back against much of what the administrative state is up to but also because this is a Court that’s particularly inclined to curb administrative overreach.

 

      And I’ll flag just two potential wrinkles in closing. First, in many of our lawsuits, we partner with state and local chambers to secure venue in the best courts for regulatory issues, but the venue provisions of the Clean Air Act require that nationally applicable EPA actions be filed in or transferred to the D.C. Circuit. And venue matters, particularly for litigants who are looking to avoid reflexive judicial deference to administrative agencies. So we may see venue constraints slow agency accountability in the lower courts, even as we can achieve real success on the Clean Air Act in the Supreme Court—think West Virginia v. EPA.

 

      Second, many of us have referenced major questions doctrine and, at least, from my perspective, it remains an obviously powerful tool to fight extreme agency overreach. But not every example of agency overreach will present a major question, and there’s a risk to overusing the doctrine and potentially diluting its force. The Supreme Court has done some real work in flushing out the major questions doctrine between West Virginia v. EPA two terms ago and then last term when it applied the doctrine in the student loan cases, but the doctrine is still very much unsettled in some important respects.

 

      Justice Gorsuch’s concurrence in West Virginia laid out a non-exclusive list of triggers for the doctrine’s application. Justice Barrett’s concurrence in the student loan cases framed the doctrine as an interpretive tool rather than a substantive canon. So we’re seeing some differences in approach amongst the justices. That’s all to say that when we have litigants raising major questions doctrine as a matter of course rather than as strategically appropriate, we increase opportunities for courts that are hostile to this still-developing doctrine to narrow its application and undercut its effectiveness. We need to be strategic in its use if we hope to realize its full deregulatory potential. Thank you.

 

Hon. Kathryn Kimball Mizelle:  Well, thank you all for those opening remarks. I want to start our conversation with something that each of you, I think, has touched on, which is the foothold of any citizen supervision as standing under Article III. And my question is: what is the future of that litigation? Has the Court solidified the injury in fact aspect of standing, such that that’s not going to be a pressure point in the law going forward? Is it looking now to something more on the traceability prong? Or is the law fairly stable in these citizen supervision plaintiffs?

 

Prof. Robert Percival:  Well, I can start out with that one. I think, actually, when the Laidlaw decision came down 7-2, with only Thomas and Scalia in dissent, it basically sent a signal that to establish standing, you shouldn’t have to show that you could win a common law tort action because of the environmental violation. And now that Justice Scalia’s not on the Court anymore and Justice Gorsuch has a reputation of not having been a real bear for keeping people out of Court, it’s kind of calmed down a bit.

 

      But the case I would flag is the Texas Citizens Lobby case that the Fifth Circuit is hearing en banc because that was a case where citizens living near an oil refinery alleged thousands of Clean Air Act permit violations, and it’s been a long struggle over almost a decade. At first, the court found some violations but refused to even penalize them because it liked the refinery. That got reversed and then they found something like a thousand violations. A fairly substantial multi-million-dollar fine was levied, but then it went back up to a Fifth Circuit panel, and ExxonMobil is arguing that for each of the thousand violations, you have to find a specific plaintiff who can say they saw the violation exactly how it affected them. That’s madness. That’s like going back to -- well, let’s just scrap the permit requirements and go back to a common law system where you have to bring a common law tort suit and prove that it’s more probable than not that a particular violation caused you injury. If the Court starts becoming sympathetic to that, it’s going to make it virtually impossible to enforce some of these environmental laws.

 

Hon. Kathryn Kimball Mizelle:  That was the case, actually, I was thinking, with regards to the traceability. Is that something that’s being pushed in other courts across the country that you’ve seen?

 

Prof. Robert Percival:  That’s the one that I’m most aware of.

 

David Doniger:  Well, the one reflection I have is on Massachusetts v. EPA, and I know there’s another panel about special solicitude and so on. I think if you actually read the Stevens opinion functionally, he found that Massachusetts had concrete injury, loss of beach, traceable to sea level rise, traceable to climate warming. If anything, in the—what is it -- 15 plus years since then, climate science has gotten tighter and tighter and tighter. And I actually think it would be -- it’s very plausible that all the judges would find, “Oh yeah. That problem has become real enough that we can see the connections and the injury traceability and remedy,” and would uphold that. I would note that though there were state and public interest groups in that case, the holding on standing went only to Massachusetts.

 

      There’s a D.C. Circuit decision by Chief Justice Srinivasan, NRDC v. Wheeler, which held that—in a challenge by NRDC to a regulatory relaxation on the control of chemicals called HFCs, hydrofluorocarbons—we had demonstrated the contribution to -- their contribution to warming, the impact of warming on climate, and the exposure of specific individual members of ours to those kinds of damages. And they upheld NRDC’s—and, by implication, other public interest groups—standing to bring climate-related challenges. Now, that’s not the Supreme Court, but it’s an important decision.

 

      And I just think you have to get real about this. If the basis for denying standing is actually denying climate science—in that case—then that’s not a very sound legal proposition. Now, it’s our burden -- it was our burden to establish that science, and we did. We had expert affidavits from some of the nation’s top scientists for each step in the chain. And I think -- I would be very upset if standing was used, again, to try to stop citizen groups, who represent the beneficiaries of these laws, from having legal rights. We’ve got to keep -- it’s functionally very important to keep the administrative agencies suspended between the regulated and the beneficiaries of the regulations.

 

Damien Schiff:  If I could add just a bit to that. I’m in sympathy with what David has just said because -- and his early remarks, too, about his noting that Chevron, at one point, was considered sort of a conservative doctrine. And I think we realized that it’s not really a conservative doctrine, it’s just a bad doctrine.

 

[Laughter]

 

David Doniger:  It’s a neutral doctrine.

 

[Laughter]

 

Damien Schiff:  I think the same thing is true of standing. I mean, really, the sort of canonical theory of standing and injury, in fact, and traceability and -- I mean, all that’s made up. That’s essentially, sort of, a prudential common law gloss that I think, perhaps, a reckoning is going to happen such that -- and quite right. I think David is right. I think that it’s not appropriate for citizens who clearly have an injury that nobody would say this is made up—that we’re just sort of going through the motions—those citizens deserve a hearing. And for what it’s worth, you look at -- almost all states recognize some version of citizen standing. It’s not as if we have tyrannies going on or kangaroo courts in the 50 states, so I think that it is appropriate to reassess standing.

 

      Now, I will say there’s been some interesting scholarship recently about whether statutory standing—sort of this zone-of-interests test—needs to be reexamined and whether maybe some APA cases that the challengers might need to show something more than what they have under the data processing test. But setting that aside, as a constitutional matter, I would welcome a reexamination of that.

 

Stephanie Maloney:  And I’ll just add that the Chamber Litigation Center, to some extent, I think, probably has a different perspective on standing than Damien does and that some of my other friends --

 

[CROSSTALK]

 

David Doniger:  Because you guys are always in it.

 

Stephanie Maloney:  -- up here do. As a trade association, we file lawsuits on behalf of our members, so we’re suing the regulators on behalf of—to use David’s phrase—the regulated industry. As part of that, there is some division amongst the circuits about the need to disclose and identify a particular member who has specifically alleged harms. And so, even as we’re seeing the Supreme Court possibly be reconsidering the special solicitude given to states for their standing, part of what we’re doing at the Litigation Center is thinking strategically about whether there is or should be or deserves to be a need to identify particular members. Right?

 

      Obviously, it’s difficult to be a company—a business—who’s raising your hand and challenging the regulators. So do we need to be identifying, by name, members who are impacted, or is there First Amendment associational protections, whereby we can proceed, setting out the harms that members are facing but not needing to identify them by name? So I think we’ve seen this Supreme Court have very robust approaches to the First Amendment and associational protections. We saw that in Americans for Prosperity, so it’ll be interesting to see how the Court’s—what seems to be—reconsideration of standing doctrine will come up against its robust First Amendment doctrine.

 

Hon. Kathryn Kimball Mizelle:  Okay. Stephanie, you mentioned, from the Chamber’s perspective, there’s concern about agency mission creep. And David, you talked about, I think, the opposite concern of agencies becoming captive to the industry that they’re regulating. I’m wondering what concerns Article II or otherwise do any of the panelists have with things such as consent decrees in this space? Is there any sort of collusive aspect between the potential regulated industry and the agencies?

 

David Doniger:  Can I start on that?

 

Stephanie Maloney:  Yeah.

 

David Doniger:  Well, where do we use consent decrees? Let’s take a typical case where an agency has a deadline specified in the statute, either a calendar date or a date that a clock started—let’s say, eight years earlier and then the deadline has expired—for revising or issuing some rule. It’s a pretty clear legislative mandate to do something by that deadline. And usually, in those cases, you walk into the court not with a brief, more or less, but with a calendar, and you say -- and everybody can see the deadline has been missed. What is the remedy? If it goes to the judge and both sides are arguing—the agency’s going to say I need two more years, and we’re saying it could be done in six months, and so on—the judge can decide. Often, the parties can work out an agreement that they -- a settlement that they would agree to. Normally, settlements are favored in -- as a means of avoiding litigation, and I think that’s totally normal.

 

      One thing that was added—I can’t remember if it was in ’77 or 1990 amendments to the Clean Air Act—was a requirement that those kinds of settlement agreements, whether it’s a settlement agreement or a consent decree proposed -- that those should be aired in a public deferral register notice for comment by anybody else who’s affected so that in the case of a -- well, so that the judge of the case could decide whether there’s some reason why this resolution that’s been worked out by the main parties of interest shouldn’t be followed. And I’m not aware -- I am aware that it’s very standard to do that, and I’m -- I think it’s very infrequent that comments are filed opposing those deadlines. It happens. And I think it’s even more infrequent that the judge says, “This timeframe that the two”—the agency and the plaintiff—“have worked out is some reason or other unacceptable.” But that’s the role the judge can play if a third party has come up with a really good argument.

 

      I don’t think it’s collusive in any sense other than that all settlements, all peaceful resolutions have -- what started out as lawsuits are -- can be described as collusive. So I reject the notion of -- the criticism of sue and settle and collusive agreements. Congress created these deadlines and also created the authority for citizens to—who are legitimately affected—go to court to seek to enforce the deadlines when they have been missed. And that’s a very important function in the law.

 

Stephanie Maloney:  So just, David, one response, which is I think you were critical of Damien’s characterization of PLF as a public interest law firm as opposed to, from your perspective, litigating on behalf of private individuals. To me, to some extent, these sorts of consent decrees are analogous in that you have activist environmental groups that are suing agencies because they think that their priorities—about what ESA listing determinations should be, for example—should take priority over what the public representation, in the form of the agency -- what that thinking is. So just one point of observation.

 

David Doniger:  If the agency truly believes that—I’m making this up. There’s ten things on their list, and the plaintiff has brought the tenth, least important thing, it will go, at first, to the plaintiff and say, “I’ve got nine things that are more important. Don’t you agree?” And if we don’t agree, then it could end up going to a judge, and the judge can weigh the competing priorities of the agency—those kinds of arguments—in deciding what deadline she should issue.

 

Hon. Kathryn Kimball Mizelle:  Professor, you’ve written about this, I think. Do you have any comments to add?

 

Prof. Robert Percival:  Well, I was on a panel two years ago at this convention about it. And I urge you watch that tape because it was a lot of fun. But one of the things I mentioned -- the subject there was this interference with state and local governments. But just look at my own city of Baltimore. I live in D.C., but I teach in Baltimore. The Baltimore police had a lot of corrupt cops who were arresting people in order to rob them, especially suspected drug dealers. And fortunately, a lot of them are in prison now. But it was only the federal consent decree that the Baltimore Police Department entered into with the Justice Department that has really started the reform of that very corrupt department.

 

Hon. Kathryn Kimball Mizelle:  Several of you have mentioned the major questions doctrine. What role is that going to play, going forward, in litigation—from both sides of the aisle, perhaps?

 

[Laughter]

 

Stephanie Maloney:  A big role.

 

David Doniger:  Yeah. Well, probably a big role. But I think -- I agree with Stephanie that it’s a mistake for the litigants to just shout major questions in a crowded theater and try to stampede the audience. I’ve seen some really laughable efforts. There’s one case involving a company that makes defeat devices to overcome the -- to replace the pollution control devices in cars—or defeat them—so that the cars will run more like race cars. And they claim -- they sort of shrouded themselves in -- I mean, these are the most amateur second, third, fifth tier NASCAR people in world. They tried to make this into a major question because, somehow, this would interfere with the ability of NASCAR people to enjoy car racing. It didn’t get any traction.

 

Prof. Robert Percival:  Well, and my understanding is that in his disbarment proceedings in D.C., John Eastman is claiming it’s a major question whether he can be disciplined by a bar association, which shows you -- and now that Congress is in such gridlock, the consequences of ruling that something’s invalid because of the major questions doctrine is all the work the agency put into carrying out the law is gone. And the fact of the matter is if you look carefully at the environmental laws, they were intended to have vast economic and political significance.

 

      The Supreme Court unanimously, in the American Trucking case, rejected a nondelegation challenge to the National Ambient Air Quality Standards, which are what guarantees healthy air quality for the entire United States. You can’t imagine anything with greater economic or political significance and -- but that’s what the statute expressly gives EPA the authority to do, and it’s so essential to why our air is so much cleaner than in other countries like China that we’re the envy of the world. 

 

Stephanie Maloney:  So I’ll just add that, to me, legislative gridlock is not statutory authorization for agencies to pass sweeping regulations.

 

[CROSSTALK]

 

Prof. Robert Percival:  No. I agree with that.

 

Stephanie Maloney:  But on major questions doctrine, I noted that we’ve brought quite a few lawsuits recently. We’re going to bring quite a few more. We’re approaching the doctrine pretty strategically. So, for example, in the lawsuit that we just filed today against the NLRB over its joint employer rule, that’s a pretty perennial issue that we litigate. We didn’t raise it there. There will be others like that, to where we’ve litigated in the past, we’ll continue to litigate it in the present, and it’s just not going to inform those lawsuits. But there are other big ones where we’re seeing agencies do very new things—think a lot of what the SEC is doing, where we’re thinking strategically about deploying major questions doctrine there.

 

David Doniger:  I would just say one last comment about -- somebody mentioned West Virginia. I think you did. It’s important to note that while the Court struck down the design of the Clean Power Plan, it contrasted that quite favorably with the way that EPA had regulated under this -- industries under this provision before. And that was not creating a major question. So there’s an ongoing rulemaking to address Power Plant carbon emissions again, and EPA is trying very hard, and I think successfully, to stay within the pathway that the Supreme Court said doesn’t implicate this doctrine.

 

Damien Schiff:  If I could make just two small points. One is I think that we should also pay attention to what might be per se applications of the major questions doctrine, which I think of now as the federalism canon as being, which Justice Gorsuch noted in his concurrence in West Virginia, and which was employed by the majority opinion in Sackett. And I think they’ll be more prominent, in part, because they have fewer moving parts. You don’t need to show as much—they’re a little more established—but they still have the same clear statement burden placed on the agency.

 

      Secondly, I would say, in addition to groups who want to use the major questions doctrine, I would also urge caution on the enforcement zealousness of certain environmental groups and citizen supervisions because of the major questions doctrine. And I would draw one’s attention to a Fourth Circuit decision from just a few months ago in which an environmental group sued a bunch of fishermen, saying that when they trawl for shrimp off the coast of North Carolina and they throw back some bycatch—which is already federally regulated under the Magnuson-Stevens Act—that that’s a discharge of a pollutant. They’ve taken the fish out. They don’t need these fish. They throw it back. That’s a discharge of a pollutant. And the Fourth Circuit ruled against the environmental citizen suit groups because, in part, of the major questions doctrine, that if the Clean Water Act were to apply to federal fisheries policy, it would essentially make it unworkable, and that would be a really big deal. So I do think that it goes both ways in terms of being careful not to press the law one way or the other in a non-strategic way.

 

David Doniger:  Also, it might be worth thinking through whether, in a future conservative administration, the deregulation of lead in gasoline or something of that magnitude could be considered a major question because of all the harm it inflicts and the financial value of the harm that it inflicts.

 

Hon. Kathryn Kimball Mizelle:  Well, thank you all. I promised I’d leave time for questions, and I think we should turn to the audience at this time.

 

Questioner 1:  So imagine the world where Loper Bright comes out and says Chevron is no more. We’re going to have de novo review or Skidmore or something like that. How does the major questions doctrine play in a world without Chevron, where there is no interpretation of statutes anymore by agencies in that way? Is there still a place where it’s going to have a key role?

 

David Doniger:  Well, just a quick thought. If the agency isn’t interpreting this stuff, if we go to a full-on -- it’s going to be the judges who interpret the statute, then the judges will determine what the scope of the statute is. And then, either in that case or future cases, the question will be whether the agency’s acting within the scope of that. So I imagine the same kinds of arguments about scope of authority or whether agencies are overreaching would be made even if the—let’s call it—first order clarification of what the statute means is by whatever random judge happens to be the one selected.

 

Prof. Robert Percival:  The agency will still have to interpret the statute. The question is just they -- will they get deference? And if you overturn Chevron, then they don’t automatically get deference, and there’s a question --

 

David Doniger:  But they’ll still be offering their advice.

 

[CROSSTALK]

 

Prof. Robert Percival:  -- does the Court agree? Yeah.

 

David Doniger:  Yeah.

 

Damien Schiff:  I just add on that, too, that Cass Sunstein has an article about how there are two major questions doctrines and how the one is just simply Chevron displacement and the other is more substantive. And so, if the major questions doctrine is more of a substantive canon, then I think that Chevron’s overturning won’t have any impact on it. And I do think that that’s essentially what the canon is doing now.

 

Hon. Kathryn Kimball Mizelle:  Yes, sir.

 

Roger Pilon:  Roger Pilon, Cato Institute. David, I was struck by your rant, as you rightly called it, in which you suggested that there were black hats, like Damien and Stephanie, who were promoting these hoary private interests as against folks like you, the white hats, who are interested only in the public interest. I wondered why you use such a political characterization of this when, really, so many of these cases you’ve been talking about are simply rule of law questions in which reasonable people can have reasonable differences about health and safety.

 

      And just as environmental law is a species of nuisance law writ large, you’re going to have health and safety lines drawn. And that falls into two categories: namely the health and safety kind that you’ve mostly talked about, as well as the regulatory takings area, like in the Lucas case where the question is whether a statute that, for example, is justified for promoting tourism can take all but the last use that is available to David Lucas of his property. And there, you can simply say that those public goods are perfectly available, you just got to pay for them. So these are rule of law questions. They’re not simply political decisions as though that’s all that was at issue.

 

David Doniger:  Well, I confess I haven’t thought about the case that you mentioned.

 

Roger Pilon:  David Lucas.

 

David Doniger:  I don’t know anything --

 

Roger Pilon:  Lucas v. South Carolina.

 

David Doniger:  Right. I don’t know about –

 

[CROSSTALK]

 

Roger Pilon:  Opposing council.

 

David Doniger:  Okay. So I’m confessing I can’t speak to that but -- and I didn’t use the phrase white hats and black hats.

 

Roger Pilon:  No. I did.

 

Stephanie Maloney:  And I think I got differentiated from Damien.

 

David Doniger:  Yeah.

 

Stephanie Maloney:  So I’m not sure if I should take that as a badge of honor—should get a gray hat. [Laughter]

 

[CROSSTALK]

 

David Doniger: So the only point I’m making is that -- I hear it in Damien’s self-description of what PLF’s and his own objective is. It’s to seek out and find private property interests and represent them. Now, I suppose you can have a theory that the protection of private property is fundamental to the public -- is an essential public interest foundation to our rule of law and in our governmental structure. Fine. Fine.

 

[Applause]

 

Roger Pilon:  It’s also a constitutional right.

 

David Doniger:  But what do you do with -- what do you do about pollution? What do you do about the real impacts that happen that are not captured and disciplined in any market system? That’s why we have these laws because the tort system was neither -- taking these questions to judges in individual tort cases was inefficient and really put judges in the position where, on any given day, you’d have to learn the science of PFAS or whatever chemical. They don’t know about this stuff, and Congress found the right thing to do—to enlist agencies in order to capture that expertise and that capacity that the tort system simply failed to deliver.

 

Prof. Robert Percival:  And pollution is a threat to property rights. And just to say a word in praise of Damien’s group, which I don’t do a whole lot.

 

[Laughter]

 

Prof. Robert Percival:   There was the case of ARCO v. Christian, I think, in the Supreme Court about five years ago, where the question was: could Montana’s state law that allows property owners who’ve had their property polluted, like the smelter that just had vast pollution around it -- could they recover restitution damages? And it was very interesting. Washington Legal Foundation filed a brief saying, “We’re with ARCO all the way. It’s preempted by CERCLA.” But the Pacific Legal Foundation filed a brief on exactly the opposite side, saying it shouldn’t be preempted, that property owners should be able to have this additional state remedy because their property’s been polluted. And I thought that was a great job.

 

Roger Pilon:  Thank you.

 

Damien Schiff:  If I could just, real brief -- I don’t think anything that we’ve done at PLF has resulted in any rivers catching fire, but I can assure you that stopping the Sacketts, for example, from building their home did not prevent any other river from catching fire. It’s really more of a question of balance, and I think you read, for example, Justice Alito’s majority opinion in Sackett two, his very first sentence almost is that the Clean Water Act, basically—nobody disagrees—has been a success. The rivers aren’t catching fire, and I think that’s great, too.

 

      But at some point, though, there has to be a balance between environmental regulation and making reasonable use of your property, and it’s my view, and I think PLFs view, that the administration state in the last several decades has got that balance wrong. And now the Supreme Court has sort of appropriately rebalanced things. So that really is -- it’s not so much a -- it’s not as dramatic as it might otherwise appear.

 

Hon. Kathryn Kimball Mizelle:  Mr. Gurev (sp).

 

Mr. Gurev (sp):  Thank you. Thank you all. Question about Clean Water Act citizen suits. So an important limitation on those suits is the diligent prosecution bar. I think pretty much every circuit that has dealt with that issue has concluded that there’s some kind of presumption of diligence on behalf of the government when it does something like enters into a consent decree, but none of them are very sure where it comes from. It doesn’t seem to be in the text of the statute. Some of them ground it in Gwaltney. Some of them ground it in like the presumption of regularity.

 

      So wondering, first, if you have any thoughts on how much deference courts should be paying to Executive Branch determinations in context like the diligent prosecution bar? And then second, and relatedly, the remedies in these kinds of suits are oftentimes public remedies. Like, one Clean Water Act remedy is a fine paid to the public FISC. Are there Article II constitutional concerns that should color how courts interpret statutes like the diligent prosecution bar that limit citizen suits?

 

Prof. Robert Percival:  Well, you have to draw a line somewhere but the case where it was easy for everyone to say there hadn’t been diligent prosecution is Laidlaw—the very case where Justice Scalia’s doctrine of standing got stuffed by a 7-2 majority. There was a case of -- the Friends of the Earth had sued this polluter for hundreds of Clean Water Act violations. And the minute they got the notice of the potential citizen suit, they went to South Carolina authorities and said, “Please sue us to preclude the citizen suit.” And South Carolina authorities said, “Oh, we don’t have the time or money to do it.” So they said, “We’ll draft your complaint for you. We’ll pay the filing fee just so we can preclude the citizen suit.” And the trial judge quite properly said, “That’s not diligent prosecution. That’s just an effort to try to defeat the citizen suit because you have such a cozy relationship with the regulatory agency instead of honoring your permit.”

 

      Now your second question was --

 

Mr. Gurev:  Article II --

 

[CROSSTALK]

 

Prof. Robert Percival:  Oh, well, yeah. That was -- Scalia claimed citizen suits were unconstitutional, and yet our very first Continental Congress adopted qui tam provisions that allowed ordinary citizens to stand in the shoes of government to recover judgments on behalf of the government. And so, the rest of the Supreme Court pretty much -- I think that’s kind of a dud letter now. Citizen suits are so well established, and they have been since the early days of the Republic.

 

Stephanie Maloney:  I’ll just add -- you mentioned qui tam suits. If folks read Polansky last term, at least in the False Claims Act, the Court seems open to reconsidering the constitutionality of qui tam lawsuits. So I think -- like major questions doctrine and standing doctrine, this is another area where we’re seeing this Court think critically and deeply about questions that, to some extent, have seemed longstanding.

 

Hon. Kathryn Kimball Mizelle:  Yes, sir.

 

Frank Shepherd (sp):  Yes. Thank you. Frank Shepherd. Just following up ever so slightly on, I think, what the first question was. It strikes me that -- it strikes me that the -- with respect to the Chevron doctrine, one of the basic propositions is that if a judge can read that blessed statute and understand it, he or she should not look at -- should not defer to what some agency, unelected person has to say. Don’t you think, Mr. Doniger, that that’s a valid -- a pretty valid criticism of the Chevron doctrine?

 

David Doniger:  Well, what you’re getting at, I think, is -- the criticism is about Chevron step two. Everyone agrees that Chevron step one -- read the law; see if it’s clear; use all the tools of statutory construction, text, context, structure, maybe even legislative history to figure out what that statute means. That is the first obligation of the Court to grapple with that. And if the Court concludes that the law is clear, whether or not that’s the agency’s position coming in or sometimes is our position -- the law is clear, and the agency has not followed it. That’s the first inquiry, and that should be robust.

 

      And in our brief, we said, “We have no problem with the idea of reminding the lower courts that you need to grapple with step one, or the step one question.” And it’s only if you see in the statute that Congress has left a range of policy space for the agency to choose among -- a range of reasonable policy space to choose among to solve the problem that they saw in a general way, in a way that’s particular to a particular pollutant or industry, better than some other way. That’s when you defer. Now, is there a criticism out there that some judges are too quick to say, “Aaah. This is a—to use a Scalia phrase—argle bargle, and I don’t understand it, so I’ll defer.” I’m sure that’s true, but it’s not what we are trying to get judges to do.

 

Hon. Kathryn Kimball Mizelle:  Yes, sir.

 

Questioner 5:  Yes. Hi. So we’ve talked about how the citizen suits were implemented to balance against regulatory capture. But with Chevron deference in place and the deference being given to the administrative agency, do we see that these policies are in contrast with each other, where the administrative agency might be captured by the regulated and then they’re deferred to? So is the citizen suit hurt in that way, and which should be favored, if so?

 

David Doniger:  Well, I think of the Chevron deference in the way I just described—as the residual after you’ve checked to see whether the statute really is clear and specific. The Chevron deference there is a neutral principle, and it’ll be used by -- it was used, originally, by the Reagan administration, in my case, to cut back the scope of a major new Clean Air Act provision by 90 percent, just by changing a definition. I thought that was bad. And it’s been used by, let’s say, the Clinton or the Obama and Biden administrations less so now because they don’t make explicit appeal to the Chevron deference. But their interest is in -- to try to do more with this statute, not less. Fine. They still have to be subject to judicial review, and if the law clearly doesn’t allow what they said or how they interpret it, they should lose at step one.

 

      I don’t think the major question doctrine was needed at all because step one and step two do it. And just one quick -- I never understood Chief Justice Roberts’ opinion in, I think it’s King v. Burwell, where he said, “We’re not going to defer.” But then he went through an analysis of what the statute means. And instead of calling that a step one analysis—because he read the whole statute, how all the parts fit together—he concluded that if the federal exchanges didn’t apply—I’m not stating the issue correctly -- but the law would fall apart. It wouldn’t work. And thus, he upheld the government’s position, not as a matter of deferring and not even explicitly as a step one question, but he framed it as -- like it’s for me to decide what it’s going to take to make this statute work. I thought he could’ve reached exactly the same conclusion at step one. And I don’t understand why step two figured into it at all.

 

Questioner 5:  But, I guess -- once we get to that step two and deference is in -- is possible --

 

David Doniger:  We lose a lot of cases at step two.

 

Questioner 5:  Well, yeah. But what I’m asking is does the deference to the administrative agency cut against the interest in having citizen suits because -- and the protection against regulatory capture?

 

David Doniger:  Well, I don’t know the case that these two guys were discussing, the fisheries -- the clean water versus fisheries case, but from the description, it sounds like I can’t quarrel with that outcome. This mission was given of regulating the fish catches, was given to the National Marine Fisheries Service, and this was a sort of clever, sideways effort to get more -- to treat dead fishes’ pollution. When they’re in my refrigerator, they are a pollution.

 

[Laughter]

 

David Doniger:  You don’t need big, new doctrines to reach sensible outcomes.

 

Hon. Kathryn Kimball Mizelle:  I think we have time for one more question.

 

Questioner 6:  Thanks, everyone, for a great panel. My question is what role, if any, does the limited and enumerated power structure of Article I Section VIII in the original scope of the Commerce Clause have to play in the future of this litigation space? Or should it have any role to play in the future of this litigation space, both on the save the planet side and on the protect the Constitution side?

 

Prof. Robert Percival:  Well, I would direct your attention to the concurring opinion by, I guess it’s Justice Gorsuch and Thomas, in Sackett, suggesting that while the Clean Water Act may only be justified by the ability of Congress to regulate navigation and not commerce, it is, in fact, the case -- the U.S. is one of the few major countries that doesn’t have any reference to the environment in their Constitution. Now that’s because most countries have updated their constitutions in comprehensive fashion recently, and we have the oldest written Constitution and haven’t amended it much.

 

      But the Commerce Clause has proven to be the basis for upholding all the federal regulatory authority that’s used in most of the environmental statutes. And, in fact, the Court has had no trouble with that, even in the context of endangered species, where if they’re so endangered they’re not going to have great commercial value or be crossing state lines—the idea being like Justice Scalia mentioned in Gonzales v. Raich—that if the only way you can have a comprehensive regulatory program is to regulate even purely intrastate activity, Congress has the authority to do that.

 

      When I was clerking on the Court, we had this tradition that chambers all ask each of the justices out for lunch, and when we had lunch with Justice Rehnquist, we asked him what his favorite decision was, and he said Gonzales -- what was it? It was National League of Cities v. Usery, where the Court had struck down the application of federal wage and hour laws to employees of a governor’s office. And we said, “Why is that important?” And he says, “It’s an agent in place.” And he outlined -- he had a clear agenda that one of the things he wanted to accomplish on the Court was cutting back on federal regulatory authority. Unfortunately, National League of Cities v. Usery got reversed by the Supreme Court a few years later when Justice Blackman said, “It’s kind of hopeless for us to draw the line of what is a traditional state function and what’s not.”

 

      But in his Lopez decision, he fired the shot across the bow of Congress and then subsequently in the Morrison decision, involving the federal Violence Against Women Act. The Court, in what I think was largely symbolic decisions, said, “Congress has gone too far without drawing the necessary statutory connection to commerce.” But in the environmental area, everything has been upheld. If you want to have an activist court wanting to essentially repeal the environmental laws because of some new constitutional interpretation, and you can’t use the Commerce Clause to uphold them, which was suggested in the concurrences in Sackett, then we’re in a whole other area and query if that’s good for separation of powers if you’ve got the Court essentially repealing the constitutional basis for laws that have been on the books for more than half a century.

 

Damien Schiff:  I was about to make a joke that we’re working right now on a strategic litigation plan to implement that concurrence. No. I think the reality is—and as Professor Percival noted—the Endangered Species Act is a great example. Chief Justice Roberts, when he was on the D.C. Circuit, had that dissental where he talked about the hapless toad, and people thought, “Oh. Well, maybe he’s going to bring some Commerce Clause circumspection to environmental law.” It hasn’t really worked out that way. I think the Supreme Court’s been petitioned a half dozen times on the Endangered Species Act and its Commerce Clause connection, and its denied cert. So I think if there is going to be a change when it comes to Commerce Clause and the environmental law, it will be indirect, meaning the Court will decide something outside of environmental law, whether it’s healthcare, NFIB, or in the criminal law context in Lopez and Morrison. And then in the lower courts, it might be applied analogously to environmental law. But I don’t think the Court, currently, is ready to entertain, positively, that directed tact.

 

Prof. Robert Percival:  I’m glad to hear you say that.

 

[Laughter]

 

Hon. Kathryn Kimball Mizelle:  Well, can we give the panelists a warm thank you?

 

[Applause] 

 

 

1:45 p.m. - 3:15 p.m.
A Creature of Statute: American Antitrust Law

2023 National Lawyers Convention

Topics: Corporations, Securities & Antitrust
State Room
The Mayflower Hotel
1127 Connecticut Avenue NW
Washington, DC 20006

Share

Event Video

Listen & Download

Description

Although a creature of statute, American antitrust law functions in practice as a field of common law. Courts have had the preeminent role in shaping the contours of its application, imposing the “rule of reason” and defining concepts like competition and the use of economic evidence. While antitrust precedents are closely examined by practitioners and academics alike, less attention is paid to whether the developments in antitrust law over the last century are consistent with the text of the antitrust laws. This panel will discuss the meaning of the antitrust texts, how or whether current law is consistent with the plain meaning of the statutes, and what that means for antitrust policy going forward.

Featuring:

  • Prof. Daniel A. Crane, Richard W. Pogue Professor of Law, University of Michigan Law School
  • Mr. Ashley Keller, Partner, Keller Postman
  • Ms. Doha Mekki, Principal Deputy Assistant Attorney General, Antitrust Division, United States Department of Justice
  • Mr. Bilal Sayyed, Senior Competition Counsel, TechFreedom
  • Moderator: Hon. Stephanos Bibas, United States Court of Appeals, Third Circuit

Overflow: Cabinet & Senate Rooms

Speakers

Event Transcript

Mark Meador:  Welcome, everyone. My name is Mark Meador, and on behalf of the Corporation, Securities, and Antitrust Practice Group Executive Committee, I would like to thank you for joining us today. If you’re interested in events like this and antitrust law and policy or incorporations and securities law and would like to get involved with the practice group, please reach out to Nathan Kaczmarek. The more, the merrier. We take all the help we can get. And especially law students, we’d love to have you join us as well.

 

      Before we get started, I do have one brief announcement about CLE. For those of you who are pursuing CLE, we remind you to get the credit you need to sign in and out each day, once per day. Signing in and signing out can be done by scanning the QR codes. So if you’re pursuing CLE and have not checked in, please be sure to scan the QR code on the back of your convention booklet or on the CLE poster. And if you’ve already checked in via the QR code, however, there’s no need to recheck in.

 

      Today’s panel is entitled, “A Creature of Statute: American Antitrust Law.” Although a creature of statute, American antitrust law functions in practice as a field of common law. Courts have had the preeminent role in shaping the contours of its application, imposing the rule of reason in defining concepts like competition and the use of economic evidence. While antitrust precedents are closely examined by practitioners and academics alike, less attention is paid to whether the developments in antitrust law over the last century are consistent with the text of the antitrust laws themselves. This panel will discuss the meaning of the antitrust text, how or whether current law is consistent with the plain meaning of the statutes, and what that means for antitrust policy going forward.

 

      We are honored to have with us Judge Stephanos Bibas to moderate this discussion. Judge Bibas sits on the U.S. Court of Appeals for the Third Circuit. He was previously a professor of law in criminology at the University of Pennsylvania Law School. As director of the Penn Law Supreme Court Clinic, he argued six cases before the Supreme Court of the United States and filed briefs in dozens of others. He graduated summa cum laude and Phi Beta Kappa from Columbia University in 1989 with a B.A. in Political Theory and from Oxford University in 1991 with a B.A. in Jurisprudence. He then earned his J.D. from Yale Law School in 1994. After graduating from Yale Law, Judge Bibas clerked from Judge Patrick Higginbotham of the U.S. Court of Appeals for the Fifth Circuit and Justice Anthony Kennedy on the Supreme Court and was a litigation associate at Covington & Burlington in Washington D.C.

 

      Thereafter, Judge Bibas served as an assistant U.S. attorney in the Southern District of New York, where he successfully prosecuted the world’s leading expert in Tiffany stained glass for hiring a grave robber to steal priceless Tiffany windows from cemeteries. Before his tenure at Penn Law, Judge Bibas taught at the University of Chicago Law School and the University of Iowa College of Law and was a research fellow at Yale Law School. He has published two books and more than sixty scholarly articles. I will now turn things over to Judge Bibas who will introduce the panel.

 

Hon. Stephanos Bibas:  Thank you for that effusive introduction. The most important thing about the introduction is that it did not mention antitrust law. So I’m certainly at a disadvantage relative to our other panelists, and I view my job as getting out of the way relatively quickly to spark an interesting discussion among them.

So anyone who hasn’t been asleep in a cave as long as Van Winkle knows that the last 30, 40 years have seen a real renaissance of textualism and a focus on what the law says and what it means. And this is sometimes misunderstood and misdescribed as strict construction or something like that. But Justice Scalia—perhaps the most noted exponent—makes clear the job of the judge is not to construe things strictly or broadly but fairly according to their terms as a matter of the separation of powers and understanding that the judge’s job is to explicate what the law is, not what it should be, one of those things that The Federalist Society often stresses.

And his response often to saying, “Well, a law is overly broad, or it’d be absurd to enforce the law broadly” was, “Well, if we just enforce it according to its terms, the legislature will step in and fix that.” And that seems to be the approach that courts take in most areas of law. And then we come to antitrust law. And obviously, antitrust law has existed for more than a century. And since the passage of the Sherman Act, courts’ attitude has been, “Well, Congress can’t really have meant that because all contracts involve restraint of trade.” And so courts have treated it as a delegation to themselves, a self-aggrandizing finding of delegation, to make common law policy.

Well, first of all, that’s a little odd. Up until shortly before the Sherman Act, the view of courts was, “Well, common law meant we’re not making law. We’re just finding it, discovering what’s out there.” And that’s not the way they ever approached antitrust law. But is that legitimate at all? And is that what Congress meant? And even if it is legitimate and even if it is what Congress meant, how is it that that approach to antitrust law has continued across multiple other antitrust statutes: Robinson-Patman and Clayton and the FTC Act—many of which have more specific provisions and yet get read as a continuation of this?

And how is it that intellectual fashions—you can look at the late Judge Robert Bork’s focus on consumer welfare, etc.—wind up filtering into the law without any additional lawmaking by Congress? How is that legitimate or consistent with what Congress has done and with the judicial role?

And thankfully, we have a panel -- a very distinguished panel of people far more knowledgeable about this to talk about it. Now, they have very lengthy biographies, and I could spend the whole time here reading them, but I think it’d be more interesting if I just give you the top line on them and let them take it away.

First, we’re going to have Professor Daniel Crane to my immediate right, who’s a professor at the University of Michigan Law School, formerly at Yeshiva’s Cardozo Law School, who has written very widely, published in the major law reviews, including a noted article on antitrust anti-textualism that I think will kick off our discussion about how far we’ve diverged from it.

And then to his right, our second speaker will be Ashley Keller, a fellow former clerk to Justice Kennedy, who was then at Bartlit Beck, and has gone off, founded Litigation Finance, and now has his own firm doing plaintiff side work. I have a hard time keeping track of the name of it, but now it’s Keller Postman. And so he’ll talk a little bit about the limits of textualism and the ways in which conservatives might not fully appreciate common law adjudication.

And then to his right, I’m very pleased to have my former student, Doha Mekki, who is now at the Department of Justice as Principal Deputy Assistant Attorney General for the Antitrust Division of DOJ, supervising more than 350 lawyers. And she’s going to talk some about the practical implications of enforcement, about how enforcement has changed from the Carter administration through the ‘80s, the Drafting Merger Guidelines and relations with the FTC, among others.

And then to her right on your far left, we are pleased to have Bilal Sayyed, who’s the Senior Competition Counsel at TechFreedom and formerly was at the Office of Policy Planning at the FTC and previously in private practice representing in merger and non-merger matters before the FTC, and DOJ, who’s also taught as an adjunct professor at the George Mason Antonin Scalia Law School. And he’s going to discuss some of the difficulties in finding and adopting a textualist approach, some of the courts and businesses experiences with near textual broad readings, and how to be internally consistent in maximizing consumer welfare by protecting the competitive process.

So we’re going to try to start off with relatively brief five to seven minute overviews. We’ll have plenty of discussion back and forth, and then we hope we will have plenty of time for some questions at the end. So, without further ado, Professor Crane.

Prof. Daniel A. Crane:  Thank you, Judge Bibas. It’s a pleasure to be here. So, as Judge Bibas mentioned, my initial remarks will be drawn from this article I wrote called Antitrust Anti Textualism a couple years ago. I will give a very short version of the argument in that article, and the backup and much more detail is available if you’d like to read it.

So, jurists and scholars of statutory interpretation typically fall into one of two broad camps. You have textualists who follow techniques like plain language, grammatical rules, and canons of interpretation in service of determining what a statute means. And you have purposivists who follow a broader set of techniques like looking at legislative history in service of fulfilling the legislature’s purposes.

So, although the debate over textualism and purposivism rages throughout much of the statutory world, that debate has not characterized at all antitrust law. That’s because from the beginning, the courts have followed neither approach. That is to say, they have habitually disregarded both what Congress said and what Congress meant in interpreting the antitrust laws. Rather than being either a textualist or a purposivit, the courts have followed what is largely understood as a common law process, where judges update their interpretations of the statutes based on evolving economic learning over time.

Now, that may be a legitimate way, in principle, to interpret statutes that are open textured or indeterminate, and that’s true in some places of the antitrust laws. But that’s certainly not always true of the antitrust laws. There are many places where the statutes plainly say something or that Congress apparently meant something, and the courts have said or done something entirely different, justifying all of it as part of this common law process.

So in the Article, I give many examples of this. In the interest of time, I’ll just highlight a few here. In the first antitrust case to reach the Supreme Court—Trans-Missouri in 1897—Justice Peckham’s opinion held that Section One of the Sherman Act, which prohibits “every contract, combination, or conspiracy restraint of trade,” means what it says. The word “every” is categorical and does not allow a defendant to argue that a particular restraint of trade is reasonable, since the statute doesn’t mention reasonableness.

Very quickly, however, the Supreme Court backed off of Justice Peckham’s textualism and read a rule of reason into Section One. Now, you don’t have to believe me that this is untextual. The Court has repeatedly said it’s not textual. In fact, at one point, Justice Stevens went so far as to say, “The language of Section One of the Sherman Act cannot mean what it says.”

Now, the rule of reason is the best known example of judicial defiance of legislative text, but maybe it’s the weakest one because one could make an argument that although not textually faithful, the Court at least was faithful to Congress’s purpose. After all, many people in Congress in 1890 said that they were -- they meant to adopt the common law, and the common law did, in fact, recognize a rule of reason.

Now, I think it’s pretty dubious to rely on the legislative history of the Sherman Act. Robert Bork did that and has been pilloried ever since. But even if you try to argue that the Sherman Act and the rule of reason can be rehabilitated on purposivist grounds, the case gets far more difficult—I would say impossible—when we start considering subsequent antitrust statutes.

Let’s take an example from the Clayton Act of 1914. Section Four allows “any person injured in their business or property” to sue for treble damages. Notwithstanding the language allowing a suit by any person, the Court has imposed significant standing hurdles, such as the requirement that the plaintiff be a direct purchaser or otherwise have suffered a direct injury. No effort at all has been made to justify these standing rules based on text, legislative history, or any other conventional technique of statutory interpretation.

The FTC Act of 1914 in Section 5 prohibits “unfair methods of competition.” What’s the important word? “Unfair.” What word has been entirely written out of the statute by a judicial decision? “Unfair.” Over time, the courts have completely read fairness out of unfair methods of competition, even though that’s in the text and clearly what Congress meant. And then we have the Robinson-Patman Act of 1936.

After several decades of enforcing the statute the way it was written, the courts have essentially read it down to go no further than the Sherman Act. I challenge anyone in this room to defend that, either textually or from a purposivist perspective. You just can’t. I could go on, and there’s a lot more in the article. But in the interest of time, let me turn to an even more provocative assertion.

Not only have the courts persistently disregarded the antitrust statute’s texts and purposes, they have almost uniformly done so in a way that has favored big business. Most of the examples in my article are about ways in which the courts limited the reach of the antitrust laws, reduced damages exposure, or made the antitrust laws tools against labor interests.

Now, at this point, people in the room are wondering how this Marxist got invited to the panel. I can assure you I’m not a Marxist. But I do think it’s important for conservatives—and for everyone else, too—to be honest about what has happened with the interpretation of the antitrust laws.

Now, speaking of conservatives, I want to preempt an argument that has circulated at various times, which is that this kind of disregard of statutory intent and purpose must come from conservatives. Certainly, people associated with the Chicago school and conservative judges have been guilty of this. But there are many, many other key actors who are not conservative at all: just to name a few, Louis Brandeis, Harlan Stone, Thurgood Marshall, John Paul Stevens, William Brennan and Ruth Bader Ginsburg—hardly a rogues gallery of conservatives.

So if this is not a conservative push, what’s happening here? My hypothesis is that this is an outworking of two competing impulses in American politics. There’s a Jeffersonian impulse that favors the small, the local, and the distributed. There’s a Hamiltonian impulse that favors the large, the national, and the concentrated. These impulses are in constant tension and contest periodically in different guises.

When Congress writes antitrust statutes, it tends to do so in an aspirational Jeffersonian voice. Then the courts come in and accommodate the statutes to the contending Hamiltonian impulse, and then Congress usually acquiesces. So the system continues in this way without raising much political drama. Now, if that’s all descriptively correct, it does raise serious normative questions like, “Is this all democratically legitimate?”

Let me close with an anecdote that I hope gets at this question. The last time I spoke at the National Lawyers Convention was in 2017, and then Judge Brett Kavanaugh moderated the panel. Right at the end of the panel, I made a very short version of the observation I’ve made today.

In his first antitrust opinion on the Supreme Court, Apple v. Pepper, Justice Kavanaugh started his analysis with the text of Section Four of the Clayton Act and repeatedly rebuffed arguments that would disregard the statutory text, as his majority opinion stated, “We should resolve ambiguity in the direction of the statutory text.” That’s the first time since 1897 that the Court has struck that chord.

My own commitments are textualist in part but also Borkian, which means I would be reluctant to see the courts radically uproot 130 years of federal common law. But as to new and undecided questions, Justice Kavanaugh gives us a textualist path forward. Thank you.

Hon. Stephanos Bibas:  Mr. Keller?

Ashley Keller:  I’m ready to get a little more radical. So, echoing some of Professor Crane’s remarks, I’m not a particularly great Christian, but I try, and I’m going to confess my sins here. I am completely guilty of the hypocrisy that he describes. I consider myself a conservative—therefore, a formalist and a textualist. And yet when it comes to antitrust law, I’ve been going along to get along with this entire common law paradigm that we conservatives would never countenance in any other area.

The logic goes something like what Professor Crane alluded to. “Well, the text of the Sherman Antitrust Act is exiguous. You can’t really tell what a contract in restraint of trade is. What does it mean to monopolize? This must be a delegation to Article Three for them to make it up.” We would never tolerate that in any other area.

We say that the Constitution doesn’t enact Mr. Herbert Spencer’s social statics, even though the words “due process of law” are not particularly self-defining. But apparently, the Sherman Antitrust Act enacts Mr. Robert Bork’s perspective from the University of Chicago and the antitrust paradox. And we start measuring supply and demand and consumer welfare and read all of these rules of reason into the statutory regime.

We wouldn’t say that about the freedom of speech. We wouldn’t say that about just about any other provision, that it’s a delegation to Article Three—no disrespect to the Article Three jurists, the fine ones in this room, who are very intelligent and are perfectly capable of applying the Chicago school to economic principles. But that’s just not the way we conservatives approach any other area of law, and so we shouldn’t do it here.

The Sherman Antitrust Act has particular words. Yes, it’s not a verbose statute. It’s not prolix. So it’s not going to have a lot of definitions that are self-defining. But the normal tools of statutory construction that we would insist upon in every other context ought to apply here. And the repercussions of that, if we’re serious about taking our principles to their logical conclusion, is we have to be a lot less friendly to big business. Article Three courts have to be a lot less friendly to big business.

Now, the first normative point that I would make is that’s just fine if that’s what the law requires, and it doesn’t matter whether it’s good or bad. We should stick to the text and leave it to Congress if they want to change the law. The law is the written text. It’s in the statutes at large. The fact that it’s old is no excuse. We don’t tolerate that with respect to constitutional principles. We don’t tolerate it with respect to other statutes, and so we shouldn’t tolerate it here. And so end of story.

But if you want to consider some of the practical ramifications associated with a more muscular antitrust policy and enforcement regime, there are two things that I would highlight. The first is, we commonly talk about all of these rules being invented as a common law matter being good because they take decisions away from judges; they leave things to the free market; there are going to be error costs if we have judges enforcing the text as written. I think it actually cuts completely in the other direction.

When you make up a rule of reason and say that a particular practice is going to be a violation of the antitrust laws depending upon a whole confluence of measurements that we’re going to hire really expensive experts to litigate, you have just guaranteed that that case gets past the 12(b)(6); it’s going to be litigated through summary judgment; there may be a trial; 10s of millions of dollars are going to be expended, and no one’s going to have clear bright line rules for how they ought to behave because it all depends on whether the jury believed this expert or that expert, that the pro-competitive justifications for the restriction outweighed the anti-competitive effects, which is just Gobbledy Gook.

There’s no clear guidance to businesses as to how they ought to order their affairs. A bright line set of rules which is closer to what Congress enacted is going to be a far superior regime that lowers the costs, at least of adjudicating things in the Article Three courts.

The second point that I would make—and I fully admit that I’ve come to this view recently, and you can say that I’ve confessed my sins, and this is another one which is opportunistic textualism and formalism—but big companies are terrible right now for the causes that we believe in. Does anybody think that it’s good that Meta has the influence that it does, that Google has the influence that it does, that Amazon has the influence that it does? And I don’t care that Amazon Prime delivers goods really cheaply to our houses. They are terrible for conservatives. They are against everything that we stand for.

And so if enforcing the laws as written by Congress and rediscovering that we’re textualists and formalists in this moment brings down some of these companies that are engaged in behavior that conservatives should abhor, that’s a positive thing, and we should all get on board with it.

Hon. Stephanos Bibas:  All right. Ms. Mekki?

Doha Mekki:  All right then. Thank you so much to The Federalist Society for having me at this wonderful event. I, as Judge Bibas mentioned, am the Principal Deputy in the Antitrust Division, and my comments briefly will sort of touch on the practical realities of some of the pathologies that both Professor Crane and my friend Ashley have identified.

I arrived at the Justice Department maybe eight and a half years ago, and I had practiced in a law firm, and one of my first assignments was to prepare some of the legal analysis in a recommendation memo. And I thought, “Well, I’m very well suited to do this. I know how to marshal the law; I know how to do legal research, and I know how to apply facts to the law.” And it turned out that this was my first foray into the culture of antitrust enforcement in the agencies.

And what I learned was that there was an intense focus on economic theories of harm, backing facts into stylized models of economic harm, and comparatively little—really, very little—focus on legal research engaging the actual text of the antitrust laws, be it the Clayton Act or the Sherman Act, which I think we’ll have occasion to talk about how those statutes are actually quite different in terms of their approach and construction.

And I also learned curious things, like people in the agencies weren’t fond of citing Supreme Court precedent that had not been disturbed by the Supreme Court itself or by congressional action because it is old and a real focus on case law—again, to the extent that it was cited—that was adjudicated after the 1980s or so. And so if you are intellectually curious, if you have reverence for the law, if you care deeply and passionately about the American people, as I do, it leads you down a rabbit hole of trying to figure out why things are the way they are or, as the youth say, “Why are we like this?”

And so I agree with so much of what both Ashley and Professor Crane have identified. We are neither textualists nor purposivists. We don’t lean into the legislative history of the Sherman Act very often. I think sometimes you can find interesting statements of normative values in the legislative history. But I will tell you—because I’ve tried to do it—it is ugly reading.

And I have also been concerned about antitrust exceptionalism. I think it leads to particular pathologies that are very uncomfortable for those of us who grew up in the executive branch. Many of you are familiar with the fact that there was sort of a built-up approach to antitrust law and adjudication in the courts. And I’m going to hazard a guess that my friend Bilial will criticize some of that work.

But there is nonetheless a hard departure from approaches to the text and adjudication of the Supreme Court starting around the 1980s. And I think that for all of us who are concerned about things like the rule of law, about democratic legitimacy, I think that we should worry hugely about a regime that gives the executive branch license to depart radically from the text of statutes and from Supreme Court precedent. All of us take an oath on day one to support and defund the Constitution, and we are mandated to take care that the laws be faithfully executed. And I have a lot of concern about what it means to willfully wantonly ignore the law as Congress wrote it and as the high courts have interpreted it.

You should also be concerned about what appears to be a one-way ratchet. I think Professor Crane talked a little bit about this. Again, no matter where you come out on what the Sherman Act is and what it’s intended to do, almost immediately, you have courts saying, “Well, Congress could not have possibly meant what it wrote.” And Congress follows up after passing the Sherman Act in 1890. I think it’s universally accepted. There was frustration about how the Sherman Act was being interpreted, including in the 1911 Standard Oil case.

Just as a small aside, I went down the rabbit hole of looking in newspaper archives and how the reaction to the Standard Oil case was received in the courtroom when the high court read the decision, and there was disappointment. Why? Because the Supreme Court said that only unreasonable restraints of trade were unlawful.

And Congress passes the Clayton Act in 1914, and it’s a list, right? The Clayton Act actually prescribes a set of offenses that violate the Clayton Act. And so here’s Congress again saying “we are serious” about the enforcement of the antitrust laws. And once again, you have courts kind of downgrading what passes muster -- I’m sorry, what is declared unlawful under the Clayton Act.

And then again, you have the Celler-Kefauver Antimerger Act. It’s right in the name in 1950. And it doesn’t take long before courts decide that certain kinds of merger enforcement under Section 7 of the Clayton Act weren’t actually unlawful, notwithstanding the fact that Congress is clear about its concern about trends towards oligopoly, trends towards concentration, and concern that if we do not arrest the trends of concentration and their incipiency, it is a threat to our free enterprise system. And that’s almost a quote.

And then the final point I would raise to all of you and to try to bring this home and why I think this conversation is relevant is that the outcomes haven’t been great in recent years. I did a literature review, and over and over again, you have a thoughtful, bipartisan spectrum of scholars and practitioners who point to areas of the law where the courts have just gotten it wrong and elevated the formalism that the courts themselves have built up to find very strange outcomes under the antitrust laws.

And I should also say someone much smarter than me once pointed out that Americans look to antitrust law when we are uncertain about the future. And it’s not far from my mind that we had a massive economic crisis in 2008 and 2009. There is lots of writing about an uneven recovery. There’s the massive demand side market failure that the COVID pandemic ushered in. And there’s also the really interesting fact. I’m at the risk of sounding a little bit like I’m observing on the outside. I don’t consider myself a conservative, but I think conservatives kind of come to antitrust law because of concern about big tech in particular and concern about the ability of these massive companies to control the information that we consume.

And so going back to some of those normative values, we’re mindful of things like Senator Sherman’s discussion on the floor of the Senate about how monopoly is a kingly prerogative. And if we wouldn’t have monopoly in the form of political power, we shouldn’t tolerate monopoly over the kings, over the necessities of life. And so all of this is very interesting. I’m excited by a new generation of people who are excited about antitrust law. And I look forward to a discussion about how all of this is relevant at the agencies.

Hon. Stephanos Bibas:  Wonderful. Mr. Sayyed?

Bilal Sayyed:  Well, I do disagree with a lot of what I heard. And I think my main disagreement is that it seems very clear to me that the statutes are not an exercise in definitions but in evaluating the effects of certain conduct. I mean, I think it’s a bit of a trope to say the Sherman Act prohibits every contract in restraint of trade, and every contract is a restraint of trade. The focus in Section 1, for example, should be on, “Is this conduct or contract affect a restraint of trade,” right?

So I would ask, in a sense, people who miss -- who I think sort of misread initially Section One of the Sherman Act—and I’ll even ask Doha this because I think there’s an opportunity for Justice to really push back—who on this panel, who in this audience would treat the BMI case differently, right? If you’re not aware of that case, this was the development of a joint license for the use of music, basically, right?

Rather than negotiating with each individual composer or author or publisher, the -- in a sense, the association of these entities agreed to license, in a sense, the catalog of music under specific terms. I mean, the Court says this is literal price fixing but does not adopt that type of analysis. It looks to the effect. Did it restrain trade, right? People, I think, brush too quickly over that language “restraint of trade.”

Every contract is not a restraint of trade. The examples that people give, two lawyers come together and form a firm and decide, of course, they will not compete against each other in the provision of legal services but jointly offer services as a partnership. Who thinks that is a restraint? That allows for a different type of output.

So in the Clayton Act, in the Robinson-Patman Act, there is a list of conduct that may be illegal. It’s not that all tying is illegal. It’s not that all exclusive dealing is illegal but tying or exclusive dealing or price discrimination that has an effect on competition, that lessens competition, or arguably tends to create a monopoly. This is a factual inquiry, not a textual inquiry.

Now, I agree that early case law that developed this distinction about reasonable and unreasonable restraints of trade looks like it’s departing from the statutory language. And I think it does. But I think what they’re trying to do is identify this focus on either is this a restraint? Is this an attempt to monopolize? Is this a monopoly, right? And I want to come back to that.

Scholars have suggested that it is clear what Section Two means, that Section Two is a no-fault monopolization statute. And Bob Lande has done a nice article on this, both himself and with Richard Zerbe. But even there where they look to -- they sort of treat Scalia’s approach -- they take Scalia’s approach seriously and look to dictionary definitions, even there, you see either of two things: a monopoly is all -- and we have very few monopoly cases that turn on whether someone has one hundred percent of the market, or they turn on the ability to exclude or control. And those are factual questions, not definitional questions.

Looking to the text tells you absolutely nothing except that you need to do an evaluation of effects. This doesn’t even seem like a hard question to me. And the focus on textualism strikes me as a red herring and also significant unfamiliarity with how cases develop.

Now, I said there is a period where the Supreme Court attempts something like a textual framing or interpretation of the Act. And this is in the roughly 30-, 35-year period starting in around 1940 and ending in around 1975, where almost every type of conduct was alleged to be per se -- every type of conduct presented to the Court was identified as per se illegal, right?

Again, I’d ask the textualists up here. Topco formation of a joint purchasing entity, and they say, “Look at the mergers that came out in the ‘60s and ‘70s.” There was no effects analysis. It was either this looking to congressional intent that Doha mentions—not in the statute—or quite limited market shares, where the Court just failed to look at the effects of the analysis, right?

Did a merger lessen competition? Did a tying arrangement lessen competition? Did an exclusive dealing lessen competition? Or alternatively, under Section One, did they restrain trade? Even the price discrimination language in the Robinson-Patman Act is qualified by the need to show a lessening of competition or tend to create a monopoly. Now. Robinson-Patman Act jurisprudence went wrong when they accepted that harm to a firm, harm to a competitor is harm to competition. So I’ll stop there.

I will say one thing. I think of myself as a conservative and that I won’t upend 130 -- the development of law over 130 years so casually by a misreading or refusal to fully read a statute. But I’ll also say, even as a conservative, I like Google; I like Meta, and I like Amazon. And it is unclear to me what they are doing that may be outside of their business conduct should require the use of antitrust statutes to penalize them. So I’ll stop there.

Hon. Stephanos Bibas:  So this is a great start for discussion, and I think Bilal and Ashley’s comments—and Doha’s, too—highlight some different strains within conservatism. And we forget that Teddy Roosevelt was a Republican president and was a populist kind of trustbuster. And so when we think about -- Dan called it the kind of Jeffersonian vision versus Hamiltonian—or you could call it idealistic versus Pragmatic. Have conservatives been seduced by a vision of Chicago maximizing economic efficiency cost benefit analysis here in a way that when you look at the Delaney Clause in environmental law, it looks extreme?

Courts find a way to do some kind of -- are we going to really enforce it to the letter, or should conservatives just say, “Look, that’s a matter of whatever comes out of the process. And maybe cutting big businesses down to size is good, or maybe we should just trust in lobbying to take care of it.” So should courts have backed away? Should they still back away from kind of a Borkian maximizing welfare economic efficiency approach in the name of fidelity to these other goals?

Ashley Keller:  You’re asking me? Yes. [Laughter] I think there was a little bit of a straw man in some of the previous remarks. No one is suggesting that there aren’t going to be facts that are relevant in antitrust cases. You can’t just read the text and say, “We’re done here.” The question is, “Are we being faithful to what the words in the statutes at large mean so that we can deduce which facts are relevant for purposes of determining liability at an antitrust trial?”

So I’m not suggesting that the answer is you just look at the words, and you think really hard, and you use the normal tools of statutory construction, and then we’re done. We have lots of statutory regimes where you do that, and then you have a trial, and both sides get to present their views, and there are facts that are relevant.

But the notion that supply and demand and where they meet and the lines underneath that define consumer welfare are the end all be all is just incompatible with what Congress chose to write into our statutes and to make our law. It’s not to say that it’s entirely irrelevant, but those are not the only things that define a restraint of trade. They are definitely not the only things that define what it is to monopolize or attempt to monopolize. And I haven’t heard anybody say that that’s a faithful reading of the statutory text.

So if we’re going to be faithful conservatives, I think we have to apply the same rules in this statutory context that we do in every other context, and then we can have the debate about stare decisis. And obviously, reasonable minds can differ. I think stare decisis is Latin for conservative unilateral disarmament, and I just won’t abide by it. [Laughter] But I respect the other view.

Bilal Sayyed:  Well, okay. I don’t think what I proposed was a straw man. I think what I proposed was the statute says you look at the effects of conduct to see if it meets the requirement of a restraint of or on trade or a lessening of competition. This is an effects-based analysis, not a textual analysis. I don’t think I used the term “consumer welfare” at all in what I said, and I think very few district court, appellate court, or even Supreme Court opinions use the term “consumer welfare.”

And I think is also both -- I can say this for certainty about my practice, and I think I can say this with near certainty for your practice. I never try to evaluate the consumer welfare effects of conduct by a client or -- who a client might be complaining of. I said, “Let’s talk about effects on price, output, innovation, and related topics.”

I drew no triangles in my career as a practicing lawyer or in my time at the FTC. I never measured the area of a triangle versus the area of a rectangle, right? I never did that, and courts don’t do that. Courts do and should do an effects-based analysis. That has been the conservative revolution in antitrust, not the adoption of a consumer welfare standard, right?

It has been the adoption of looking to actual effects rather than just looking at characterization of conduct. And that is conservative, right? Get to the right answer, not some made-up answer. So, again, I think the consumer welfare Borkian approach or discussion is sort of either straw man or red herring. I love the antitrust paradox, but economics has passed beyond that.

Ashley Keller:  Is price fixing illegal?

Bilal Sayyed:  Price fixing is illegal.

Ashley Keller:  Where does the statute say that?

Bilal Sayyed:  It doesn’t say that. It’s an effect. It’s an effects-based analysis.

Ashley Keller:  But how do you know that the effects are negative?

Bilal Sayyed:  How? From empirical analysis.

Ashley Keller:  Every time per se? That’s on the statute either.

Bilal Sayyed:  Okay. So what? We don’t evaluate all so-called “price fixing” as per se illegal, right? I mean, I mentioned the BMI case, the BMI/ASCAP license. That was characterized as clearly per se -- I’m sorry, clearly literal price fixing. But, of course, the Court looked at that and said, “Wait. This increases output; this increases something new,” right?

I would be fine with actual analysis of all so-called price fixing agreements to see what their effect was. The courts have adopted administrative rules to make such trials either manageable or sort of unnecessary to go over the same question repeatedly. But if your argument is it is a conservative position to evaluate every price fixing allegation sort of on an effects-based analysis each time, okay, that’s fine. It doesn’t sound very conservative.

Hon. Stephanos Bibas:  Let’s hear from our other speakers. Doha?

[Laughter]

Doha Mekki:  So I guess I’ve sort of lost the plot a little bit in this discussion. But I think the challenge I’m having with Bilal’s commentary is that you seem to set up the straw man that everything in antitrust or a textualist approach to antitrust means that we just have a framework of per se offenses when it’s actually the case that it’s the very narrow minority of antitrust violations that are subject to a per se framework. And we do fact development and application of facts to the law in the vast majority of our other cases. But I think the issue --

Bilal Sayyed:  I agree one hundred percent with that, to be clear.

Doha Mekki:  That’s good. It wasn’t clear a couple of minutes ago.

Bilal Sayyed:  I said it’s an effects-based analysis.

Doha Mekki:  I think the more interesting issue, though, is I think Bilal’s concerns about what the text of the statute says and doesn’t say. And Dan’s really wonderful article, talks about the common law nature of the term “restraint of trade,” which did have a meaning at common law. And you can look to -- I’m not sure how this room feels about this source, but you can look to the first restatement of contracts that I think is typically held up as authoritative and compelling—at least in its recitation of the state of the common law. And it had very specific meanings.

And we know that the restraints of trade roughly fell into five buckets of malum prohibitum, in an antitrust world, or malum in se. And only one of those, strictly speaking, was economic, right? There were multi-object goals of the restraint of trade. And so from a lot of that, we derive our rules and antitrust. And it’s really, I think, well canvassed in Judge Taft’s opinion in Addyston Pipe in the Sixth Circuit from 1899.

And so I think the more interesting discussion that we should be having is whether antitrust is a body of law that’s a sort of empty vessel to be filled by judges. And I think that is wrong. There are numerous downsides to that kind of approach. And I think it’s curious that the arch-textualist, Justice Scalia, seemed to be okay with that sort of framework.

And I would posit that we’ve never had a strictly textualist approach to antitrust, and it’s really a conversation that is starting now because you have two agency heads, FTC Chair Lina Khan and Assistant Attorney General Jonathan Kanter, my boss, who have pledged to administer the antitrust laws in a manner that is faithful to the text of the statute and the interpretations of the highest courts. And it is curious that there has been backlash about that, and it’s kind of precipitated this debate about what the statutes actually mean and what the goals of antitrust are.

Prof. Daniel A. Crane:  So we’ve been just too polite. I want to pick a fight with all three of my co-panelists. [Laughter] So Doha doesn’t like the outcomes of the recent cases. I kind of do. Ashley doesn’t like big tech. I kind of do. So I’m kind of with Bilal on the merits of lots of this stuff. But Bilal, Robinson-Patman Act. Let me read you the language. I was thinking about bringing slides. We actually have the text up here. Since we’re talking about textualism, I should have done that.

Here’s what the Robinson-Patman Act says: “Anyone who injures, destroys, or prevents competition with any person who either grants or knowingly receives the benefit of such discrimination or with customers of either of them has violated the statute.” The Robinson-Patman Act in 1936 amended the Clayton Act precisely to allow a suit of injury to an individual business person, not to competition generally. And that’s the way in Morton Salt the Supreme Court interpreted.

Morton Salt is an appalling opinion to me as a matter of policy. It is textually correct. And now, the Supreme Court has read that out. Primary line price discrimination is just predatory pricing. That’s Brooke Group. And then secondary line price discrimination requires a showing of harm to competition generally. That’s Ruth Bader Ginsburg in Reeder-Simco.

So, I mean, I get the point about the Sherman Act. We can have that conversation about effects. That may make sense, but it’s really hard to go through the Clayton Act, through the Robinson-Patman Act, to the FTC Act and say, “Well, the text supports a standard of effects and general harm to competition. Certainly, it’s the Robinson-Patman Act.” That is just not plausible in the face.

Hon. Stephanos Bibas:  All right. So, since I’m a judge, I’m interested in what I’m supposed to be doing. Descriptively, is your analysis that we’re, in essence, making policy on what is going to lead to the best effects? And if that’s true, normatively, even if Congress meant to delegate this to us, how under the Constitution do we have the power to make these decisions that have this massive effect on the structure of American business? Or am I being too dark and too pessimistic in my read of the situation?

Bilal Sayyed:  Well, I think you’re being a little too dark. I think there is a framework to evaluate the effects of conduct. And courts do the best job they can—or at least try to do the best job they can—in evaluating effects. I think courts get it wrong when they turn to sort of what I’d call a language analysis of the statutes, right?

If you accept the idea that the Sherman Act, the Clayton Act, and the FTC Act require some type of effects analysis, then I think courts are doing fine. They may get it wrong, but they’re operating within that framework with effects analysis. It’s helpful if the agencies or scholars help develop that framework. Courts should take notice of it, think about it. But this doesn’t seem in any way controversial to me.

Ashley Keller:  Yeah. I mean, Congress knows how to delegate to you the Rules Enabling Act: “Does it screw up the rules of civil procedure all you want? You have that power.” But this was not a delegation. It looks like any other statute.

I mean, I think the answer to your question is, very flippantly, you should decide cases or controversies, and you should rely on us as litigants and practitioners to present arguments to you. And you cannot be faulted for not getting to what I believe is the right answer under the text if we don’t tee that up for you and say, “Look. This is the faithful reading of what the Sherman Antitrust Act meant in 1890. Here’s the proof of it, and here’s why my client wins this case.”

And so it’s incumbent on all of the practitioners here, and I commend Doha and her colleagues for being faithful stewards of, I think, our nation’s antitrust laws and taking care that the laws are faithfully executed. We’ve got to do the work as litigants to empower you to reach the right judgments in cases or controversies. And if we don’t do it, if we just cite the effects and we throw a bunch of experts in front of you and you measure output and you decide, “Yeah. In this two-sided market, I’ve determined that there are more pro-competitive effects than anti-competitive effects because that’s how the case was framed,” then it’s not on you; it’s on us. But we have to do our jobs and give you the tools that you need to properly adjudicate these cases.

Doha Mekki:  I completely agree with that. Look, I think that nobody is concerned. I hope no one is concerned about the kind of ordinary judicial gap filling that I think happens across all manner of statutes and cases that are presented, particularly to district court judges. I think, again, it’s this idea that there was a broad delegation by Congress to the courts to fashion rules.

I think it is in vogue now to think about congressional delegation or non-delegation, such as it is. And my really wonderful colleagues who are sitting out there gave me a lot of adjacent areas of law to dig into and think about how we interpret the Sherman Act. And I went down the rabbit hole of reading the Gorsuch dissent in Gundy. And there’s one part in particular that really jumped out at me—two parts, actually.

The first was a preference for a stricter test for nondelegation but also this line that if the separation of powers means anything, it must mean that Congress cannot give the executive branch a blank check to write a code of conduct governing private conduct for half a million people. And that was a case about a sex offender registry.

And when we think about our job—which is to police the whole of the U.S. economy, a really glorious thing that we are all very proud of—we need to be especially careful about the rules that we expect that Congress has fashioned in the past and the way that we present our cases and ask judges to do their jobs.

Prof. Daniel A. Crane:  Yeah. So I teach contracts. That’s the other thing I teach. And I have no problem with the fact that for hundreds and hundreds of years, the courts followed a truly common law process. There was no underlying statute. Lots of interesting questions about how do you reform in a common law system where it’s inherently based on following precedent. And so looking to the past -- so those are technique questions and legitimacy questions.

But overall, we have a very long common law tradition. I don’t see a real problem with the idea that antitrust law could be common law; sort of the way it’s worked. My problem is that’s not what Congress has said in many cases, and we’re treating it as if it’s this kind of contracts or torts or property common law, which there was a common law restraint of trade preceding the Sherman Act. But since that time, Congress has actually intervened and said more specific things.

So that’s the legitimacy problem I have, and it’s a principle problem, which is why do we get to do it here and ignore what Congress has said here? And then in other areas, when the outcomes are not ones favored by conservatives, we yell and scream about it. So, to me, that’s the principal consistency point. We can’t continue to pretend that Congress hasn’t said to us things in the antitrust statutes that we don’t like. We have a choice to make. What do we do about them?

The other thing I’ll just say is stare decisis, to me, is really important. I think this has come up in several of our points here. Certainly not on the Third Circuit, Judge Bibas, would you have the authority to start reversing what the Supreme Court has said. And even at the Supreme Court level, I wouldn’t be comfortable with, “Let’s start all over again. Let’s go back to 1890 and pretend this didn’t happen.”

It did happen. The question is how we move forward now. And so I don’t think this is so much about getting back as it is moving forward. But I think that what Judge Kavanaugh did in Pepper, as to this issue before me today, I’m going to start insisting a little bit more on textualism really is the way forward.

Hon. Stephanos Bibas:  All right. I’ve got one more question, and then we’ll throw it open to the floor. So please, think of your questions, and we have a microphone in the back that you can line up at if you like.

So let me focus on Doha. Let’s talk about enforcement agencies, as you were just talking about what litigants bring to the court. So the agencies have an interesting role here—and two parts of the U.S. government. Ashley represents some state governments, so maybe you want to chime in on that as well. So sometimes, the agencies join force with pragmatic courts and reading down the statutes. But at other times, like the FTC in the ’70s and ’80s, agencies are fighting more for the plain reading against the courts.

So if the courts are being antidemocratic by reading down statutes, if Congress doesn’t do anything about it, are the agencies a solution here? Are they really helping this conversation to evolve? And is it appropriate for us to be trusting the agencies to vindicate the text of the statutes if the courts, at least historically, haven’t been?

Doha Mekki:  It’s a great question. First, let me exercise same humility and say, “Look, the agencies have participated in this very odd dance that we’ve been doing over the last century or so.” And as we sort of look to the future, fidelity to the law, I think, looks different at the two antitrust agencies.

Again, I grew up in the executive branch. I work at the Justice Department. I love the Justice Department. You feel like you work in the executive branch. Your role is to take care that the laws be faithfully executed. Congress has not given us rulemaking authority. Congress has not given us authority to conduct studies and markets.

Conversely, over at the FTC, their enabling statute gives them -- it is truly a creature of administrative law. And I think there is a greater case to be made that Congress specifically delegated certain of its authorities to the FTC to include case-by-case adjudication of competition statutes, including principally the FTC Act but also the ability to fashion rules, to govern unfair methods of competition or certain UDAP principles, and to conduct studies.

And so I won’t speak for my colleagues at the FTC. But for those of us working in the antitrust division, we can’t disregard the 130 years or so of law that has been built up. In addition to being faithful to the will of Congress, we have a duty to obey the precedent as it exists. And so all we can do is be clear about our intentions, to bring the best cases that we possibly can, to bring compelling narratives, to compel judges to decide in our favor, and to participate in the administration of the antitrust laws in a way that preserves the democratic legitimacy of our work and the democratic nature of our public institution that we hear a lot about.

Hon. Stephanos Bibas:  Ashley, do you want to say anything from the state government perspective?

Ashley Keller:  Not really from the state government perspective, no. I guess the only thing I would say is respectful disagreement with Doha on the idea that they’re bound by judicial precedent. That’s a judicial supremacy point. I don’t buy that. The law that they have an obligation to take care that is faithfully executed is in the statute book. That’s the law. What the Supreme Court says the law is, is not the law.

There may be practical reasons for the agencies not to spend their precious resources, which are limited, tilting at windmills and trying to ignore precedent where they have no chance of success. But the law is the law. The Court’s interpretation of the law is just an interpretation, and it’s only binding in the case or controversy in front of the court. I know that is not necessarily the most popular view outside of the mayflower today, but I bet I have some supporters in the room today.

Prof. Daniel A. Crane:  I can just add one thing. So another question is prosecutorial discretion not to bring cases that you don’t like but that the statutes authorize—so the Robinson-Patman Act. There has not been a DOJ or FTC Robinson-Patman case since the 1980s. Now, there is currently an FTC investigation of Coke and Pepsi under the Robinson-Patman Act. I don’t know what’s going to happen there. But they’re 40 years of destitute, right? We don’t like the statute. We’re just not going to enforce it.

Now, that raises not an interpretive question. That raises a legitimacy question of the take-care question of whether the agencies can just decide not to enforce a statute that they don’t like—so another whole angle on this as well.

Hon. Stephanos Bibas:  All right. So now, we’re going to turn to questions. And as judge, I ask that you announce your name and, if you like, where you’re from and maybe who you’re addressing. But then after that, a question—max three sentences. The sentences may not be concatenated with a series of em dashes and semicolons. And there should be a question mark reflected by a rising vocal inflection at the end of the third sentence.

[Laughter]

Hon. Stephanos Bibas:  Josh Kleinfeld?

Prof. Joshua Kleinfeld:  Can I just walk away at this point? This might be too hard. Thanks, everyone. That was a fascinating panel. My name is Josh Kleinfeld. I’m a professor at Northwestern Law School and now at George Mason Law School as a visiting professor. I have a methodological question for everyone on the panel.

I was finding myself sort of thinking as I sat, “What if the Sherman Act had been a constitutional amendment instead of a statute?” And what if, frustrated with the courts, the country had followed up with the Clayton Act as a second constitutional amendment? And then presumably, as conservatives, we would take an originalist approach, and that would be some mixture of thinking about the -- we’d reconstruct the history of the two amendments; we’d scrutinize the intent of those who passed it, the public meaning of the words they uttered, and the big idea under -- the big idea historically underlying the amendments they passed, the way we do with, say, the Thirteenth, Fourteenth, Fifteenth Amendments.

My question, it’s a genuine question. What would the law look like in this area in that case? And would that be a more promising direction than statutory -- than the textualist approach three of you have proposed on this panel. Thanks.

Hon. Stephanos Bibas:  Any thoughts?

Bilal Sayyed:  I don’t think it’d be more promising at all. And I think the law would probably evolve in the same way it has evolved. Herb Hovenkamp has also looked at this question of, “What did these terms mean at the time they were enacted, which I think is similar to what you would do if this was a constitutional provision?” And my reading of his work and my experience is simply you look to things like -- that you would do an effects-based analysis. And as your analytical tools to perform those effects-based analysis improves, outcomes may change.

There certainly is some opportunity for improvement in the way the courts describe maybe the burdens on a plaintiff or on a defendant. But those don’t strike me as so clearly textual questions or determinative whether it’s a statute or a constitutional provision. But it seems to me you get to the same place, that you do an effects-based analysis because that’s what the law looked like, I believe, in 1890. I’m not clear why people are running away from that.

Prof. Daniel A. Crane:  So one question is, as a general matter, what does constitutional interpretation look like that’s different from statutory interpretation? Obviously, you assume that Framers of a constitutional amendment or provision speak in a different register than when they write their legislature writing a statute.

One of the things about constitutional law and the Sherman Act in particular is that the Supreme Court is described as almost constitutional. There’s sort of this language. It’s the magna carta free enterprise. So it almost has this quasi constitutional status. And so maybe one explanation for why the courts have not been -- had not treated it like an ordinary statute is precisely that they already have thought about it as quasi constitutional. Now, again, that might work as to the Sherman Act—hard pressed to say that as to, say, the Robinson-Patman Act.

Doha Mekki:  So I agree with Professor Crane’s articulation. I think that if you favor viewing the Sherman Act with a static historicism, you might get closer to what a constitutional approach to the Sherman Act actually looks like. I think you’re bringing in some of the normative values of the day. You are bringing in some of the more romantic ideals about the political economy of the day. And I think that is an issue that is often criticized.

People like me are criticized a lot for really elevating those political economy concerns in our rhetoric and in our approach to framing certain kinds of antitrust harms. And just because I can’t help myself, I have to say Jefferson actually wanted a constitutional amendment that would have banned the government grant of monopoly power. And he writes about it in a really interesting way in a letter to his friend, James Madison. It’s worth a read.

Hon. Stephanos Bibas:  Sir?

Questioner 2:  I’d ask what you guys think that antitrust law is basically obsolete and counterproductive in the technical area based on two examples. One is, back in the day, there was a bunch of litigation against the people who made fax paper. And by the time it finally resolved, nobody used faxes anymore except the Social Security Administration and the hospitals. The rest of us had all switched to email. And the second is the case of WordPerfect, which was the most wonderful word processing program ever in 1991, whereas Microsoft Word was absolute garbage.

But through tying by putting MS Word on every computer, they eventually acceptably used their tying to get monopoly -- to get total market share. However, the government didn’t do anything timely fashion. By the time the government told Microsoft that they could no longer do this tying, they were the best there was. And the effect was simply that whenever anybody bought a computer, instead of getting their Microsoft Word automatically built in, they had to go pay $100 on top of the cost of the computer. One more thing based on what you said.

Hon. Stephanos Bibas:  Is there a question here?

[Laughter].

Questioner 2:  Do you think antitrust law is both obsolete and counterproductive in the technological realm?

Ashley Keller:  No.

[Laughter]

Doha Mekki:  I say this as my beloved colleagues are downtown right now litigating the Google Search monopolization case. I agree with Ashley. The answer absolutely is no. And I think the problem you’ve described is really a latency problem, and we can get into the reasons why the agencies might be a little bit slower to wield their Section Two authority.

But I think particularly in digital markets, it is more important to bring thoughtful Section Two cases because digital markets that go to things—like the information that we consume—can lead to real harms that actually threaten our democratic values if they are not reined in. And I would also note that in technological markets in particular, you think about a technology like Search, and we know that technologies that are on the horizon—or perhaps here, like artificial intelligence—are really made worse off due to a lack of competition in certain input markets, like Search, for example.

Prof. Daniel A. Crane:  So this is really off topic since it’s not about the text. But I will just say antitrust law as the big tech is not obsolete today. It will become obsolete because of AI and quantum computing and nanotechnology, but that will not be on Doha’s watch.

[Laughter]

Bilal Sayyed:  Look, I don’t think antitrust is obsolete nor counterproductive. I mean, this is a question that’s come up now—at least this is the second time in my career—and I don’t feel that old. But this came up around the Microsoft case.

I think some of the points you mentioned could be addressed if cases moved more quickly. And while I don’t think there’s a role for Congress in revising or clarifying or changing or the substance of antitrust law, I do think there is a role for Congress to both help speed up the disposition of these cases, either through -- either or both through more judicial resources, maybe more agency resources, and also know civil and appellate procedure-type improvements.

Doha Mekki:  And short of Congress, you can count on the agencies to bring their cases a little bit faster. We have a separate case proceeding against Google in the Eastern District of Virginia where we’re looking at something like a year between the time of filing and the actual trial of that case, which is extraordinary for civil antitrust cases.

Ashley Keller:  That is a great case that you have there.

[Laughter]

Bilal Sayyed:  I just would say one more thing in addition. I mean, I used to think I was conservative. Antitrust is an alternative to direct regulation, and we should get antitrust right to avoid an alternative that Congress and maybe others consider, which is direct regulation of the conduct of these companies or any companies.

Hon. Stephanos Bibas:  All right. Sir?

Jonathan Goldstein:  My name is Jonathan Goldstein. I’m an attorney based in the Philadelphia suburbs with a nationwide practice. My question is, “Is the analytical framework the same for functioning markets and failing markets?” You have two buggy whip manufacturers. They’re the last two. They’re both losing money. They combine. They’re the only one. Now, they’re making wild monopoly profits. And if the analytical framework is the same, should it be?

Prof. Daniel A. Crane:  I mean there’s an answer to that. Justice Holmes’ opinion called Window Glass, hand-blown glass. And it was in its dying embers in terms of the technology, and Holmes basically says, “Go on and do what you want because you’re going out anyway.” Now, your hypothetical imagines that they’re not going out just yet. And so, for a while, they will actually be able to charge monopoly prices, and I think that should still be a problem.

But certainly as to a technology that’s about to be leapfrogged where what would have been an anticompetitive merger a year ago or 10 years ago, it no longer is because they no longer have the capacity to really compete against the new technology, I would go to Bilal’s effects point and say there’s no anticompetitive effect and, therefore, no reason to be worried about it.

Bilal Sayyed:  I mean, I’d say the framework should be the same, and the framework takes account of these types of effects. Is there competition from outside the market? I mean, I can tell you I feel pretty confident that the FTC and DOJ will approve a merger of two buggy whip companies because there are alternatives.

Hon. Stephanos Bibas:  Ma’am? Thank you.

Ilana Kowarski:  Hello, my name is Ilana. I am a journalist with MLex Regulatory News Service. So I’m going to frame the question slightly differently for Doha than for the rest of the panelists.

But my question to Doha is, “Based on your reading of the comments on the HSR form and the Merger Guidelines, where in those two policy documents do you see the possibility of there being changes, and what were the most constructive and interesting suggestions?” And then my question for the panelists is, “If you had one thing that you would like to see modified in a constructive way in the Guidelines or the HSR form, what would that one thing be?”

Doha Mekki:  Thank you for the questions. It will not surprise you that I can’t really answer them without waiving all manner of deliberative process privileges. But I will say, broadly, public comments are extraordinarily useful. We do read every single comment that comes in. I’ve participated in reading comments on the Draft Merger Guidelines, for example, and it is extraordinary even when they are critical because it gives us a chance to improve upon our analysis and make our intentions clearer or better understandable to the public, which is another really important part of our public mission.

Ashley Keller:  I’m for overturning Chevron and bringing back Schechter Poultry, so I don’t have any ideas for what the regulators ought to do.

Prof. Daniel A. Crane:  I can answer very quickly as to the Draft Merger Guidelines. I would strike them in their entirety and bring back the 2010 Guidelines.

Bilal Sayyed:  I second what Dan said on that, although I -- there are some improvements. This is a little beyond your question. But if there were one change I could make in the courts with respect to antitrust cases, it is this, I think, unsupported and mistaken focus on so-called type-one error, right?

The courts—I don’t know what they do outside antitrust—but the courts should, in an abstract way, say, try to minimize the costs of both type-one and type-two errors, right? You don’t want to over enforce; you don’t want to under enforce. And right now, at least in the Supreme Court, a few opinions suggest that courts themselves, appellate courts, should be focused on concerns about over enforcing the law. And that comes out of nowhere. And I think that has probably been a significant detriment to the development of the law in a manner that correctly analyzes the effects of a transaction.

Hon. Stephanos Bibas:  Sir?

Enrique Carnero:  Hi. Enrique Carnero. I’m an associate at a large law firm in New York. So my question flows from an earlier exchange between Mr. Sayyed and Mr. Keller. So we assume a per se bar on price fixing doesn’t flow unambiguously from Section One of the Sherman Act. The only way to know that price fixing has a negative effect is by looking at empirical data.

So although allowing each set of litigants to contest that in their own cases might seem awkward or maybe stupid, isn’t it the most consistent with due process to allow each set of parties to do that in subsequent cases? In preclusion, you’re usually only bound by a finding of fact if you got to litigate it yourself. So why do we ignore due process here and just jump to an antecedent finding of fact that if it’s price fixing, it’s always an unreasonable restraint of trade? Thanks.

Ashley Keller:  Yeah. I don’t think it’s a due process violation to have a judge define what a statute means. And so if Section One of the Sherman Act said, “It shall always be restraint of trade, a contract, and restraint of trade if there’s price fixing,” you get your due process to say, “I didn’t do that,” but you don’t get due process to interpret the words of the statute. That’s for the Article Three judge.

And so the point of my exchange was to say, “Where do these per se versus rule of reason ideas come from? They’re not flowing from the statutory text.” So I don’t have a dog in the hunt with respect to per se versus rule of reason on price fixing. I’m much more interested in grounding what courts do in what Congress actually wrote into our statute book and then, of course, give litigants their due process within the framework of what the statute means and put the plaintiff to his or her burden of proof. They have to tick off these elements.

But those elements should flow from the statute, not from judges looking at economic literature and say, “Hey, Bob Bork was a really smart man”—and I take a backseat to no one in my love for the late great Bob Bork. But he defined all of this and showed that it’s better overall for consumer welfare in society if we have these sorts of rules. Therefore, that should be the rule of antitrust. That’s not how we should approach statutory interpretation.

Prof. Daniel A. Crane:  I’m going to needle Doha here again—sorry—on per se rules. So one of the virtues of per se rules and due process is that as to price fixing—which is how we’ve enforced this now for many decades—the rule is very clear. I mean, what price fixing is, when it’ll be criminally enforced, that is, whether or not it’s statutorily faithful as a matter of just notice to the world, it’s very clear.

Now, needling Doha here, Jonathan Kanter at DOJ has made clear he wants to start bringing criminal Section Two cases for monopolization, and there are no per se offenses. So either you have to create them and then it becomes clear what they are, or you have to rely on some kind of an effects analysis in bringing a criminal case, which I think would really raise serious due process issues.

Doha Mekki:  I have to respond to that. Look, Section Two is a felony statute. We don’t have to reach back into the common law because Congress has declared that whoever monopolizes, attempts to monopolize, conspires to monopolize, shall be guilty of a felony, right? It was a misdemeanor until 1975 and then now is a felony. And even if you have doubts about that, Congress reauthorized the penalties under ACPERA in 2005. And so I would challenge you to think about Section Two in the criminal context as being no different than any of the myriad offenses under Title 18 of the U.S. Code.

Prof. Daniel A. Crane:  Yeah. Textually, what Congress meant and said, to the earlier point, I mean, I don’t disagree with you. In terms of due process, in terms of notice of what that looks like, I think there will be serious challenges if you start bringing criminal section two cases as to conduct that relies extensively upon effects analysis.

Bilal Sayyed:  I’d also just note that the courts have sort of moved away from per se categorization of conduct. I mean, it’s not that all price fixing is per se illegal. I mean, I gave the example of the BMI and ASCAP joint licenses. It’s so-called naked price fixing, which it may raise the same question.

But in many cases, parties who do some kind of joint-venture contract that does fix prices, they do, in fact, get to argue that the conduct doesn’t restrain trade. It creates additional output, new output. So the courts, in some sense, are sort of moving to give more process in antitrust cases for parties to make an argument that they have not restrained trade.

Doha Mekki:  But there’s a framework for that, right? I mean, that’s the ancillary restraints test, right? And that’s been true since 1899. And so if you plausibly allege that your price fixing isn’t really price fixing but it’s actually ancillary to some broader pro-competitive or productive venture, then you have an opportunity to present evidence that gets you into that bucket.

Bilal Sayyed:  I agree.

Doha Mekki:  And so, again, I don’t think that’s the Court’s moving. I think that’s been interpretation of the law since the very end of the nineteenth century.

Bilal Sayyed:  Well, I think it is actually the Court’s moving. I mean, think of some of the price discrimination cases that were criminal. Think of some of the restraint cases that were criminal. I mean, the courts have -- and I will say that ancillary -- the doctrine of ancillary restraints sort of seemed to develop differently than the reasonable -- unreasonable doctrine of Sherman Act. So it has been sitting around since 1899, but it wasn’t really used until, I think, Easterbrook and Bork and Posner in the ’80s.

Doha Mekki:  I think that’s factually not true, but yeah.

Bilal Sayyed:  Well, okay. I think they’re different, and I think they were treated differently.

Hon. Stephanos Bibas:  And for our final question, James Burnham, Vallecito Capital.

James. M. Burnham:  Yeah, hi. I’m James. I’m a lawyer. I just had a theoretical question. So if you look at the text of the statutes voting competition stopping restraints of trade, you might think that the concern was that just excessive consolidation, firms get too big, they become too powerful, they do bad things, and those bad things might be more than just raise prices.

And I’m thinking about Google, Meta, and Amazon, which I don’t like. And all the things they did during the COVID pandemic, as one example, to suppress information, shape public policy, and basically engage in social engineering on a society wide basis—lots of other examples. Is that an antitrust problem because it strikes me as a fairly serious societal problem and perhaps an existential threat to the conservative movement. Thank you.

Bilal Sayyed:  I don’t think it’s an antitrust problem. I mean, there’s nothing in the statutes that seems to touch on that.

Doha Mekki:  But I don’t think it’s open to question that those failures of competition, subversion of the competitive process, can yield second-order harms that are threatening to our social, political, and economic ideals. And so I don’t think anyone was unclear about this, right? You don’t have to look for it in the statute.

Again, you can look at some of the floor debates. You can look at the fact that -- I’m sorry, floor debate for the Sherman Act. You can think about the fact that when TR finally wields section two against J.P Morgan, he says things like, “We have to convince the people that we’re on their side,” right? I mean, there is a -- actually, I should commend Dan again. He has just edited a really wonderful volume of essays about antitrust and democracy and presents really wide ranging views about sort of the political considerations and whether you think they are baked into the statute or sort of exogenous and reflect the sentiment of the time.

There is no escaping that competition is viewed with certain political values that you can find all over the nineteenth century and parts of the twentieth century. And I think there is a resurgence of that that brings people to antitrust, and it sort of yields conversations like this.

Prof. Daniel A. Crane:  Yeah, just one example of that. I’ve worked quite a bit in the last few years on relationship between concentrated economic power and fascism, especially Nazism.

And certainly in 1950, at the time of the seller Celler-Kefauver amendments to the Clayton Act, Congress was very convinced and had a hundred antitrust lawyers working in Germany and sort of collecting evidence that there was a tight relationship between the extreme economic concentration of the German economy during the Weimar period and Hitler’s rise to power. That’s not certainly the only cause, but it was a contributing factor in how Hitler was able to consolidate power.

So, at a minimum, Congress believed—and we need to act on Congress’s belief—that when you get extremely concentrated economic power, it is very difficult to maintain a government without extremely concentrated political power, that is to say, at the end of democracy. So I absolutely think that, again, this is -- whether it’s a textualist question or just a matter of democratic urgency, but we need to think about the relationship between powers of all kind.

Bilal Sayyed:  But this is clearly not a textual analysis of the statute, or am I missing that?

James M. Burnham:  Well, monopolize.

Prof. Daniel A. Crane:  Brown Shoe, the Supreme Court includes it. It’s not textual. It’s legislative history. This goes back to purposivism versus text. So if you are a purposivist and you believe in legislative history—which Scalia did not, but Bork did—here’s the irony. The Supreme Court adopts a consumer welfare standard in 1979 in Reiter v. Sonotone, citing Bork, who’s all about not the text but the legislative history.

And then this is shortly before people like Scalia, of course, argue, “We don’t look at legislative history.” So the consumer welfare standard is not built upon statutory text. At best, it’s built upon a purposivist reading of legislative history. That raises another whole set of questions.

Ashley Keller:  Monopolize or attempt to monopolize there’s your text. I don’t need any history. They’re too big.

Prof. Daniel A. Crane:  It’s an active verb [CROSSTALK 01:28:08].

Ashley Keller:  They didn’t just appear big out of the ether. But that’s not textualist [inaudible 01:28:19]. Give me a break.

Bilal Sayyed:  I think there is a difference between Bork and Scalia on this. I mean, I think people have -- I mean, you can read Business Electronics. Scalia focuses on, I think, an effects-based analysis, not -- which he -- which I believe comes from the statute, comes from the text and not Bork’s legislative history approach in creating the consumer welfare standard.

Doha Mekki:  I would also just note, Congress is allowed to legislate around populist ideas. There are lots of times where Congress is a little bit vague, a little bit folksy, and that has nothing to do with candidates of construction or statutory interpretation. There are ideals baked into the statute. And so I think it is important to remember that this is not the kind of thing that comes from nowhere. And I don’t think any of us who -- I think I’m willing to put myself in this category of favoring a more textual approach to antitrust.

That doesn’t mean that we can’t look to other sources to do the kind of gap filling of what antitrust is supposed to do. I think Business Electronics is the seminal example of the antitrust as a vessel to be filled with policy goals and content by judges. And so, again, it is the oddity of Scalia, the arch-textualist, fashioning sort of a rulemaking power for Article Three. It’s extraordinary.

Hon. Stephanos Bibas:  This has been a fascinating discussion. Please join me in thanking the panel.

 

[Applause]

1:45 p.m. - 3:15 p.m.
Originalist Perspectives on Ethics and the Supreme Court

2023 National Lawyers Convention

Topics: Professional Responsibility & Legal Education • Supreme Court
Grand Ballroom
The Mayflower Hotel
1127 Connecticut Avenue NW
Washington, DC 20006

Share

Event Video

Listen & Download

Description

Article III of the Constitution vests the “judicial Power” in “one Supreme Court, and in such inferior Courts as the Congress may from time to time ordain and establish.” Our founding document recognizes that the Supreme Court stands apart from the rest of the federal judiciary. Yet, Congress has long regulated several aspects of the high court, including its appellate jurisdiction, rules for establishing a quorum, and standards for recusal. Some critics argue that Congress should go further to regulate ethics on the Supreme Court. Some proposals would require the Justices to adopt an ethics code. Other proposals would impose one on the Justices. This panel will explore originalist perspectives on ethics and the Supreme Court, in particular considering these questions: When it comes to establishing or even enforcing ethical standards for Supreme Court justices, is there a role under the Constitution for Congress? Is it true that Congress has the power (or even without that explicit power) regulate the high court's quorum and recusal standards? And, as a matter of prudence, should Congress take these steps? In Federalist No. 78, Hamilton described the judiciary as the “least dangerous branch.” While the Executive holds the sword” and the Legislature “commands the purse,” the courts have “merely judgment.” But can the courts faithfully exercise that judgment when threatened by the sword and pinched by the purse?

Featuring:

  • Mr. David Lat, Founder, Original Jurisdiction
  • Hon. Jay Mitchell, Associate Justice, Alabama Supreme Court
  • Mrs. Carrie C. Severino, President, Judicial Crisis Network
  • Moderator: Hon. David R. Stras, United States Court of Appeals. Eighth Circuit

Speakers

Event Transcript

John J. Park:  Good afternoon. Good afternoon. I’m Jack Park. I’m the Chair of the Professional Responsibility & Legal Education Practice Group. At the outset, you know, where tomorrow is the 248th birthday of the United States Marine Corps. So thanks to all the Marines here and it’s also Veteran’s Day observed, and thanks to all the veterans here.

 

[Applause]

 

Now for CLE credit, you’ve seen the QR codes, you have to sign in and out each, each day and you’ll get credit. As I said, this panel is hosted by the Professional Responsibility & Legal Education Practice Group. What we try to do each year is deliver an ethics CLE and a diversity CLE which is not required everywhere. The balkanization of CLE not being completely applied across the country. In addition, this year and going forward we plan to offer a Teleforum on the state of the legal profession, and that will honor our deceased friend and colleague, Ron Rotunda. If you’re interested in the work we’re doing, please feel free to talk to me or to Nate Kaczmarek.

 

Our moderator this afternoon is Judge David Stras of the United States Court of Appeals for the Eighth Circuit. Judge Stras became a judge on the Court of Appeals for the Eighth Circuit on January 31, 2018. Before serving on the Eighth Circuit, Judge Stras was an Associate Justice of the Minnesota Supreme Court, a position he occupied from July 1, 2010, until this recent appointment to the Eighth Circuit.  While there he was a colleague of Justice Barry Anderson who tells me that everything that Judge Stras does right, he learned from Justice Anderson, and Judge Stras is responsible for what he does wrong.

 

Before becoming a judge, Judge Stras was a member of the faculty of the University of Minnesota Law School from 2004 through 2010. He taught and wrote in the areas of federal courts, jurisdiction, constitutional law, criminal law, and law and politics. He received his Bachelor of Arts with highest distinction in 1995 and his Masters of Administration in 1999, both from the University of Kansas. He also received his law degree from the University of Kansas Law School in 1999 where he served as Editor-in-Chief of the Criminal Procedure Edition of the Kansas Law Review.

 

We’re delighted to have Justice Stras be our moderator today. And Justice Stras, you can take it away.

 

Hon. David Stras:  Thank you. [Applause]

 

     So we have a great panel discussion today. If you notice, the topic is in the news. It’s sort of a rip from the headlines, to steal a Law and Order phrase. I hope I don’t have to pay for that, that mention. But it is a hot topic, and it’s being written about in newspapers around the country. Certainly, a lot of people are paying attention to the Supreme Court. We’re going to talk about a variety of things including what an ethics code of conduct might look like for the Supreme Court. Why there might be an ethics code of conduct. Whether there needs to be a code of conduct and a variety of different hypotheticals along the way. Obviously, there’s a lot of action right now and very little certainty.

 

One of the things, though, that I want you to think about is in my prior life I was an academic. And from 2004 to 2010, as you heard. And one of the things I did in that list was I studied the Supreme Court. And one of the things to understand is that this ethics controversy, if you look at it in a broader sense, is not a new thing. I’m obviously, ethically prohibited from taking sort of any, any stand on this but I do want you to know that there have been attempts throughout history to affect how the Supreme Court is deciding cases to affect what kinds of cases the Supreme Court may decide. It’s a practice called court curbing. Political scientists have written about it. Legal scholars have written about it for the last four or five years. And there’s numerous instances over the course of history where folks have used different tools, usually because they disagree with what the Court is doing to affect the behavior of the justices or behavior of the Court.

 

Perhaps the most famous example is during the FDR, Franklin Delano Roosevelt administration and the infamous “switch in time that saved nine”. There was obviously a lot of attention being put by the Roosevelt administration as to court-packing. Does that sound familiar? So court-packing became a big thing. And the Court ended up moving on its own although there’s historians disagree about precisely why the Court moved, whether it was in fact the threat of the court-packing plan or whether it was some other reason. But these kinds of things have happened over time.

 

We’ve certainly had other justices where ethics controversies have cropped up. There’s been attempts to strip jurisdiction from the Supreme Court and from the lower federal courts when Congress or well, primarily Congress doesn’t like where the Supreme Court is going or the lower courts. And so my whole point is, is you can’t just look at this as a snapshot in time. And I’m probably going way over what a moderator would usually say, but it’s an interest of mine.

 

You have to look at this historically, really over the entire history of the country, to see that these types of thingsnot this precise controversy, necessarily, but these types of things have repeatedly come up over the course of American history, and they just come up in different forms. And so we’re seeing thatwe’re seeing that different form today. And so with that sort of, like, “food for thought”, I will start introducing our wonderful panelists, who I’m sure who will be even more insightful about this topic.

 

So our first speaker—and this is a lot of fun for me because I get to hang out with my friends and have a conversation with my friends. I’ve known most of these folks for a very long time and they’re all excellent.

 

Immediately to my left, who’s going to speak first is Carrie Severino, who is the President of the judicial Crisis Network and co-author of the book Justice on Trial, the Kavanaugh confirmation and the future of the Court. She’s a go-to expert on the confirmation process and has been extensively quoted in the media and regularly appears on all the television networks. She’s testified before Congress, briefed senators on nominations, and frequently files briefs in high-profile cases. She was also a law clerk, near and dear to my heart, to Justice Clarence Thomas, and then also to Judge Sentelle on the D.C. Circuit. I think she’s going to give us a little bit more of a historical perspective and talk about her view on some of these ethics controversies. So I will turn it over to Carrie.

 

Carrie Severino:  All right. Here we go. I feel like especially with Judge Mitchell here, I need to get all the height I can. I’m going to stand up. So one of the parts of my bio that Judge Stras didn’t mention is that I’m also a mother of six kids. So, I’m kind of an expert at answering crazy questions. So, sometimes that’s like after lights out, either deep theological questions or one night it was, “Mom, how is the sun on fire if there’s no oxygen in space?” And I’m like, “uh…”. Or how many days are there until Christmas or my birthday? And it’s a lot of mental math. Or sometimes, thingsmy son came to me the other day, and he’s like, “Mom, is a tomato a fruit or a vegetable?” And I was like, “Wow.” I was a biology majorthis is exciting. I can get into the discussion of botany and what a fruit is. And the next question, “Well, is a potato a fruit or a vegetable?” And then I realize what’s really going on is not sudden interest in botany, it’sare French fries with ketchup, does that qualify as a fruit or vegetable for my nightly requirements?

 

[Laughter]

 

     And I think that’s a good illustration for what’s really going on with a lot of the court-packing or a lot of the Court ethics stuff we’re seeing today. This is not a discussion about some high-minded independent view of what would be the right ethical obligations for the Court. What is the platonic ideal of a disclosure regime or of a recusal regime for justices? Folks, we know the deal. Here’s what’s going on. Again, it’s not about is a tomato a fruit or vegetable, it’s about can I have ketchup. This is not about that. This is about, Senate Democrats in particular, attempting to use this ethics investigation with two goals. One is to try to alter the votes on the Court or the make-up of the Court for any one particular case, and second, to intimidate the justices of the Court and anyone else they can intimidate in the process. You can tell because this is clearly a—thank you. Yes.

 

[Applause]

 

[Laughter] Today’s, this morning actually there was just an ethics hearing or a hearing at the Senate Judiciary Committee dealing with this issue that illustrates this point precisely. Because the justices were ready to throw subpoenas out there against just people who were friends of justices or who had connections with justices, right? And immediately backed down when it became evident that, okay, if you want to subpoena people who have connections with conservative justices, we’re alsoas many members of the Senate Judiciary Committee on the Republican sidebut we’re also going to subpoena and find out about say, what Justice Sotomayor’s staff did in connection with promoting her book. We’re going to subpoena not just Leonard Leo but Arabella advisors and Peter Kessler and some of these huge, dark money groups on the left. We’re going to find outask them where Hunter Biden and Joe Biden were at certain key dates in history. You know, there was a huge list and so many of the Republican senators did a great job of showing up and explaining what was really happening. And suddenly, the meeting was adjourned. Because the interest really wasn’t in how can we delve into interesting ethical connections with the Court or in this case that are tangentially related to the Court because none of their concerns were related to the Court that close either. It was how do we attack certain justices?

 

There is no real problem that has actually been identified at this point. They can point to no case in which wow, it looks like a justice sat on a case where someone they had some connection with actually was involved in that case. Not a thing. They have not been failures to recuse. There have been justices abiding by disclosure guidelines. Maybe they don’t like what the guidelines were but the guidelines for the judicial Conference and the advice given to justices about how to disclose different tripsand this is guidance that was given even handedly to Republican and Democrat appointees was followed, and yet they disagree with that advice but conveniently they disagree with it only when certain justices do it. So there have been cases in history, for example, when Justice Ginsburg sat on almost dozens of cases that her husband held stock in that they didn’t go crazy about. §

 

Now, do I think Justice Ginsburg was corrupt in her votes on those cases? No, I don’t think she probably even knew, right. But I think the fact that they were uninterested in that or uninterested in the fact that she would hear cases from other people at her husband’s firm. That doesn’t trigger her recusal obligations. Let me tell you if Jenny Thomas’s firm had cases before the Supreme Court, we would be hearing a whole lot about how no one who had any interest in that should be able to hear those cases.

 

This really is part of a historical pattern that we have seen, and as Judge Stras pointed out, it comes and goes, right. When you have issues that the Congress is upset with the Court, they’re going to try to reach out and control that other branch of government. We know that exists. The Constitution was designed to protect the Court from things like that. That’s why our judges have life tenure. They’re trying to insulate the judiciary from outside attacks. They want them to be able to be independent in looking at the Court.

 

But we always are going to have seasons when the Congress is going to attempt to influence them. One way we’ve seen that is through the nomination process, and obviously we can look at Justice Bork or Judge Bork; should have been Justice Bork, right? Judge Bork, Justice Kavanaugh, Justice Thomas—that’s one way they’ve attempted, not just to block those nominations because the process -- it’s a similar thing to what’s happening now. They would have loved to block those nominations but if they can’t, they can at least send a message, lay down a marker, and tell that person, “You’re being watched, and we have our eye on you and we still -- even if you have life tenure, we still can affect your legacy in the way that people will look at you.”

 

So that was baseless accusations and things during the nomination process. That’s kind of phase one. We have now seen a renewal of court-packing as a meme, right? As anyone in this room clearly knows, the way our Constitution imagines that the Court is influenced over time and changed over time is basically through the democratic process. The American people elect a president, they elect a senate, those are the people who choose what kind of justices we have. And as in any democratic system, you get the government you deserve. So if we elect presidents and senators that think that the Court should just be a rubber stamp for whatever the president says, that’s what you’re going to get. If you want justices who are actually looking at the law independently and interpret it as it is written and that’s their priority, then that’s what you’re going to get. But the Democrats in the Senate, right now, don’t seem to want to wait for that long process—that process of talking to the American people and convincing them that your view is the best one. They would rather jump to just packing the court. And so there has been introduction of legislation on court-packing, trying to add seats that would just immediately give President Biden a lot of seats on the Court.

 

Now, like with many of these things -- and with the ethics legislation ideas in a vacuum, is there a magic number nine? Seven, eleven, all of those numbers could be good. The concern here is not that there’s -- that nine is a magical number but that we don’t want this changed in a way that is going to undermine the institution of the Court, create a one-way ratchet quid pro quo. Similar things have happened with proposals recently of term limits. I don’t have anything independently opposed to term limits. Judge Stras and I were on a panel a few years ago debating this issue. You know, that’s not a problem independently.

 

What’s a problem is going about it in an unconstitutional manner, which is the current legislation, but also going at it in a way that is designed -- not for good governance reasons to say maybe we need this. Is it a coincidence that term limits are being brought up; not when 90-year-old John Paul Stevens is serving on the Court; not when we have two Democrat appointees in the eighties serving on the Court; but suddenly, when the oldest justices on the Court are Republicans. Again, these are not people who are independently concerned that, hey, maybe you should stop serving after age seventy. They only want to make sure that Justice Alito and Justice Thomas stop serving after they’re seventy, because otherwise they would have also been concerned when Justice Ginsburg was serving into her eighties, when Justice Breyer into his eighties and Justice Stevens into his nineties. I don’t think any of them should have been forced off the Court necessarily, either. I’m just saying they are doing this in a one-sided way, and I think the ethics legislation that is being proposed is the same type of thing.

 

In a vacuum, okay fine, there can be some fine ideas out there, but we have to avoid either ideas that are just clearly run into the Constitution’s separation of powers, including things like having legislature or legislative-derived groups having some kind of control over the independent branch of government. Or one that makes the Supreme Court a little less supreme where you have other judges sitting in decision over where the Supreme Court -- which Supreme Court justices sit on a case. Because as we know, you know, court-packing, that’s about affecting the Court by adding justices and by watering down the number of originalists sitting in any one case.

 

The recusal attempts are the opposite mirror image of that. It’s trying to get justices off a case that you might strategically want to remove from that discussion, because we all are smart enough to know where -- and on some of these issues, which justices are going to be more or less favorably inclined to certain types of arguments. If you know this justice you want off, let’s try to find a way to recuse them. And in many cases, the disclosure -- increased disclosure legislation really is just a way to provide mechanisms to make that easier as well. The more information you have about different -- for example, which stockholdings someone has or different things like that, opens the door then to a host of recusal requirements and demands that will create incredible workloads not only for the Court or triggering unconstitutional designs of systems, but I think also are going to be used and deployed strategically so that there would be a first round in any litigation not about what is the actual merits of the case but who can -- how can we litigate the different people off of the bench. I think that’s incredibly dangerous. And I think we need to be aware, again, of what is really going on.

 

And then finally, I’ll just read some quotes from some of the court-curbing literature that Judge Stras alluded to. This one’s from an article by Barry Freeman, who I think is at NYU Law School, that illustrates exactly what’s happening. He gives the history of court-curbing legislation and attempts throughout American history and says here are some lessons. And here’s a couple of the lessons he identifies. One, you don’t have to actually curb the Court or discipline the justices to see a shift in direction or a tempering of judicial conduct.

 

I think that what’s going on right now is people would love to actually pass this legislation. They’d love to be able to bring a successful bill that would either try to add term limits or ethics legislation or other things, but they know it’s not likely. But they know that might not be the only method of skinning that cat. They want to get to the justices and threaten them in other ways. And try to make them either concerned about how they’re going to be viewed or to send a messagenot just to Justices Alito and Thomas, because I think if you wanted to pick two justices who you could shift in their votes you probably couldn’t pick two worse attempt -- candidates to attempt, right? Not going to happen. However, I think they are sending a message to all of the other justices. They’re sending a message to everyone on a Supreme Court short list anywhere. A message to every appellate judge, to district judges, especially with the way they’ve treated Justice Thomas, to every black conservative in this country, to anyone who is willing to stand up for what they believe to be correct about the Constitution, in particular if you have the gall to be an originalist to say, “We’re going to make this improper in polite society and we’re going to make you unavailable.”

 

And then, finally, his last lesson in this article was, “A little disingenuousness can go further often than a head-on attack.” I think that’s exactly what we’re seeing here. We’re seeing, as he said, “politicians who go after the Court, they understand the American people are in many ways traditionalists about institutions and don’t con easily or well to attacks -- to Court attacks. So they shroud them in some other values just enough to achieve plausibility.”

 

So my call to you all is to lift up the veil. Let’s look at what’s really going on here and not allow these disingenuous attacks on the justices and on the integrity of the Court to be considered further. Thank you.

 

Hon. David Stras:  Thank you, Carrie, that was great. It reminded me of our time on that previous panel talking about term limits and age limits.

 

Our next speaker is Mr. David Lat, is a lawyer turned writer is the best way to put it. He publishes Original Jurisdiction, which is a newsletter about law and legal affairs. He’s written for a variety of publications from The New York Times to The Washington Post and The Wall Street Journal. And he is well known for founding Above the Law, the website. And then also before that a blog we were talking about up here, right before we started, Underneath Their Robes, which was about federal judges. We have some fans here, I think, of that one.

 

David Lat:  You’re dating yourselves. [Laughter].

 

Hon. David Stras:  Yeah. Before entering the media world, David worked as a federal prosecutor, and we were just talking about the fact that I met him when I was a summer associate in New York, like twenty-five years ago. And he was a litigation associate at Wachtel Lipton in New York City. And of course, he clerked for Judge O’Scannlain, who is here sitting in our front row.

 

So, without further ado, I’ll turn it over to you, David.

 

David Lat:  Thank you. Thank you so much, Judge Stras, Carrie, for kicking it off with a very vigorous presentation. I think I’m going to be what passes on this panel for a liberal. I guess I am the most hawkish, perhaps on the issue of Supreme Court ethics code. I do think that the Court should voluntarily adopt a code. I do not support efforts of Congress to either impose a code of Congress’s design or force the Court to do it itself. But I do think the justices should voluntarily adopt a code, and we can discuss this issue in further detail in the inter-panel discussion, I think. I do have some disagreements with Carrie. And so it’s good because I feel like sometimes these panels are just like love-ins. So it’s good that there will be some disagreement here.

 

     So as I can tell from this audience and also Judge Stras’s opening remarks, I know you’re all very into history. So let me talk a little bit about some historical context for some of the recent Supreme Court controversies along with a thesis for why I think they are flaring up now.

 

     Now, I think it makes sense to look at history because if we were to start with the text, there’s not a huge amount of constitutional text that is relevant to the issue of Supreme Court ethics and the ability of Congress to regulate the Court. Certainly, Article III requires -- says that the justices shall hold their offices during good behavior, protects their salary from diminishment. Articles I and II subject the justices to impeachment. Article I does give Congress the power of the purse. So Congress can regulate the Court’s budget. And every couple of years, the justices schlep up to Capitol Hill to sing for their supper and go to some budget hearing and they get peppered with questions on matters unrelated to the budget. The last time this happened was in 2019 when Justices Alito and Kagan went to the Hill, and they did get a question about an ethics code even way back in 2019. And Justice Kagan said, which is basically what is the case today, “We’re looking at it.” So there is this budgetary issue. And, you know, one question I guess I would say is query whether Congress could condition the budget of the Supreme Court on some kind of ethics code or certain other things. That would be Congress using it’s constitutionally provided for power of the purse.

 

So, for example, one issue that we’ve seen flare up in recent years is mistreatment or abuse of law clerks. There’s an organization, the Legal Accountability Project led by a former clerk, Aliza Shatzman, that’s been working a lot on these issues. And I think one of the arguments they make is look Congress is paying for the salaries of law clerks. Congress has an interest in making sure that its money is well spent and that these public servants, these government employees are not abused or mistreated. That does intrude somewhat into the prerogatives of the judiciary, but it is not something that is going to anything decisional. It is really just treating them like many other people who are already in the federal government. And I’m sure in the intra-panel discussion we’ll get into comparisons to Congress and what have you.

 

     So, turning to history, I guess I have a somewhat different gloss on the history compared to Judge Stras and Carrie. I would actually say that if you look at the history of the Court, yes, there are these efforts at court-curbing, but when you look at the specific issue of ethics, I would say that for much of the Court’s history, Congress has allowed the Court to regulate itself. There are some things that happened in the past that were allowed in the past where that didn’t create controversy in the past that would either be disallowed or cause a huge controversy today. My husband, Zach Shemtob, and I wrote an article for The Atlantic in September looking at this issue and -- it’s in the CLE materials. I’m sure you’re all up on those.

 

So, for example, in 1803, Chief Justice Marshall, of course, wrote the landmark opinion in Marbury v. Madison. This case involved the validity of judicial commissions that he himself had signed and sealed which his brother was charged with delivering. By any standard, he should have recusedcertainly by modern standardsbut he didn’t. And this was noticed at the time; Cliff Sloan has written a book about this. And nobody really seemed terribly troubled by this. And then fast forward a century or so, in 1972, Chief Justice Burger had phone conversations with President Nixon about issues that were or could come before the Court, including, for example, busing and obscenity. And nine years later, in 1981, we learned about these conversations. And Berger was still the chief justice, but this did not cause any kind of huge kerfuffle. Can you imagine if we learned today that say, Chief Justice Roberts had spoken by phone with President Trump before deciding the travel ban case? People’s heads would explode. So again, I do think that in certain areas when it comes to ethics, Congress has given the Court sort of a fairly free rein, a fairly, a fairly long leash.

 

Financial conflicts are also nothing new. By the way, I should say that some of these points, actually should probably be positive for conservatives or for opponents of ethics reform in the sense that, look, what the history of the Court shows is that justices across the ideological spectrum have availed themselves of the generosity of wealthy friends which is a point, I think, that Carrie raised.

 

So, for example, in the 1990’s Justice Brennan received $140,000 in basically cash or forgiven loans from a wealthy real estate developer friend, Charles E. Smith. For those of you in the D.C. area, you’ll often see Charles E. Smith Developments. He was a real estate developer and a good friend of Justice Brennan’s. He gave the Justice $140,000, and that was in cash. So I think you could say, look, some of these people love to trot out the sticker price of the trip to Indonesia with Harlan Crow on the private jet. Justice Thomas never would have shelled out hundreds of thousands of dollars to do that on his own. Whereas cash is cash. So for Justice Brennan to get $140,000 in cold hard cash, that is significant. It came outwhen it came out it was on page A9 of The New York Times. This was not front-page news.

 

And more recently, Justices Breyer and Ginsburg have accepted all sorts of trips from billionaires. People who actually have net worths much larger than Harlan Crow. The very politically involved and democratic politics Pritzker family, I think, sent Justice Breyer on seventeen trips. The late Justice Ginsburg went to Israel multiple times courtesy of an Israeli billionaire, Morris Khan.

 

Now look, I think some on the left side would say, well, a lot of these trips were disclosed and some of Justice Thomas’s weren’t. But let’s be honest and, again, I agree with Carrie, let’s really be frank about what’s happening here. I don’t think people have -- I don’t think people on the left are up in arms because of these disclosure failures. They don’t like the idea of Justice Thomas receiving benefits from a very wealthy person.

 

And again, I do have some area of agreement here with Carrie, I do think some of these efforts or calls for an ethics code are in bad faith. And I think it’s probably no coincidence that the two justices that are most raked over the coals about this, Justices Thomas and Alito are the two most conservative. And it’s probably also no coincidence that this is coming after the two of them wrote landmark opinions like Dobbs and Bruen. So, no, I get all of that.

 

So why are we seeing some of this right now? Why are we seeing this, this controversy over Supreme Court ethics flare up? So, I thinkand I agree with Carriesome of this is just bad faith and some of this is basically playing dirty politics. I get that; I don’t deny that. But I think there’s actually another reason, which is what Zach and I explored in our Atlantic piece. I think that one thing we’ve seen in the past couple of years in American politics is the rise of a very strong populace to strain. It was reflected most famously in 2016 when President Trump was elected, but you can see earlier traces on both the left and the right, whether it’s Occupy Wall Street or whether it’s the Tea Party. And part of this populism is a strong suspicion of elites. Elites include both Supreme Court justices and billionaires. And also a questioning of whether these powerful people, these elites, got to where they are because of merit or something else.

 

And so, look at Justices Thomas and Sotomayor. When they were nominated, they were hailed as American success stories. They rose from poverty to Ivy League institutions to the Supreme Court. Nowadays, when you talk about Ivy League institutions and the Supreme Court, it’s really a form of criticism. People complaining that eight out of the nine justices went to Ivy League schools. You can see this shift in sentiment and this real strong anti-elitist strain in American politics.

 

And it happens on the left, too. In July 2021, I published the news that Justice Kagan had extended a clerkship offer to Jessica Garland, who is the daughter of former chief judge of the D.C. Circuit, Merrick Garland, and current Attorney General Merrick Garland. And I thought, wow, this is kind of fine. Like, there’s a long history of well-connected people’s kids getting clerkships and also there’s also a little bit of history of former Supreme Court clerks, like Judge Garland, their kids getting clerkships, too.

 

But anyway, this was actually—this actually caused a lot of uproar on the left. People were really very upset about this and some of the usual leftie people on Twitter called this nepotism, even though there’s no relation between them. And so again, there’s this feeling that everything is fixed, and all of these elites and all of these judges and billionaires are rubbing shoulders and scratching each other’s backs. And there’s just this increased suspicion. And what does this translate into?

 

I think now the American public is less willing to just trust the justices to police themselves. And now, we are also more troubled because of this anti-elitist strain when justices hang out with billionaires. It’s just -- it is, I think, this increased focus on Supreme Court ethics. It is partly about the politics, but I think it’s partly also about just this newfound populism in the American political sphere.

 

Now look, the populism isn’t all bad. I think that there have been instances where it is called out on fairness or inequality in American society. But I think it does have implications for ethics reform. The first thing I would say is faulting the justices for conduct based on standards that did not exist at the time of the conduct is not only unfair, I think it is also counterproductive. What I mean by this is, look, the most likely path because of how this issue has been politicized and because of Republican resistance, the most likely path to an ethics code is the Court voluntarily adopting one.

 

But if you attack the Court in these unfair ways and sort of an ex-post facto applying to things that happened years ago, standards that happened, you know, that are really kind of in place now. For example, now you have to disclose private jet travel, but you didn’t have to before or at least, I think there’s a strong case that you didn’t have to before. If you apply these standards, not only is it unfair to the justices, but it also just makes them more defensive. And if they get more defensive, they are less likely to voluntarily adopt a code, which is really the best way or the most efficient or likely way we’re going to get to a code.

 

The second thing I would say is, look, as long as we have human judges that are real people underneath their robes -- and by the way, there is a contrast here. There’s a lot of research now on AI judges, I don’t know, like Judge Siri or Judge Alexa.

 

[Laughter]

 

And they have actually done studies, Americans do not like the idea of AI judges. We like our judge’s human. And so as long as we’re going to have human judges, there are inevitably going to be conflicts. Human judges are going to have friends who might want to help them. Human judges are going to have spouses who might have lucrative careers like Jane Sullivan Roberts, or who might have strong political beliefs like Jenny Thomas. And human judges are going to have human desires, perhaps for the finer things in life, perhaps for $250,000 RVs. So it is just the nature of having human judges. We are never going to have some kind of pristine world where these people exist in a bubble, untouched by the outside world.

 

So what Zach and I argue in our piece is that strengthening disclosure requirements, as opposed to trying to police the substantive friendships and this gift and that gift, is a more productive way of dealing with ethics on the Court rather than trying to enact some kind of very elaborate system.

 

Here’s, I guess, what I would conclude with. At the end of the day, we have one of the world’s best judiciaries, if not the best judiciary, in terms of independence and integrity. So in the spirit of Edmund Burke, whom I’m guessing is a popular figure here, I would note that the federal judiciary has served our democracy faithfully and well for more than two centuries, so as we consider possible reforms, and again I do believe some reforms are in order, I would say that we should proceed with caution, humility, and a sense of historical perspective.

 

Thank you.

 

Hon. David Stras:  All right. Thank you, David. Our last speaker, but certainly not least is Justice Jay Mitchell who was elected to the Alabama Supreme Court in 2018. Prior to serving on the court, he was an accomplished litigation attorney with Maynard, Cooper, and Gale. He was rated as a top litigator in the United States and received the highest possible rating for professional ethics. Grew up in south Alabama and attended Birmingham Southern College. Served as president of the student bodyand this is something I didn’t know about himplayed forward on the school’s 1995 National Championship Basketball Team, which is pretty awesome.

 

[Laughter and Applause]

 

Round of applause for that one. But no, it’s great to have a state supreme court justice to talk about this because for those of you who don’t know, the regulation of the profession happens on the state supreme court, and I did a lot of that when I was on the state supreme court. So I think hearing from Justice Mitchell will be great.

 

Hon. Jay Mitchell:  Thank you, Judge Stras. Good afternoon, everybody. Thank you for having me. It’s a real honor to be here. I want to begin my remarks today by building on something that Carrie said. Which is that in the current political climate, it can be tough to separate out legitimate ethics questions from the fact that the current SCOTUS ethics proposals are being used as a cudgel to intimidate conservative justices.

 

So to get a clearer view of how judicial ethics commissions work in the context of a healthy, well-functioning government, which many of us enjoy in our home states but what seems to be lacking here in Washington. I think it helps to look at how states have handled judicial ethics questions. Because we’ve been dealing with these questions for decades.

 

Every state has, in some form or another, a judicial code of conduct and a commission charged with enforcing that code. The National Center for State Courts has compiled lots of data on this topic, and what they’ve found is that nearly all these codes and commissions arose in the 1960s or later. Which tracks with David’s observation that apart from bribery or other overt corruption, judicial ethics issues just weren’t on the radar of the American public for most of our nation’s history. And when states did start adopting these ethics codes and commissions, the way they went about it is pretty revealing. Almost all states did so either through the state supreme court’s own initiativethat is, through court-created rules or through a constitutional amendment. Only a small minority of states created a judicial oversight commission via statute. And so far, as I can tell, in all the states that have imposed judicial oversight via statute, the legislature either, one, had express constitutional authorization to discipline judges, or two, simply passed a statute that enabled the state Supreme Court to adopt ethics rules.

 

What this pattern shows is that there is an overwhelming consensus across the nation that the political branches can’t regulate judicial conduct or discipline judges without express constitutional authority. And it seems to me that there are good reasons for that consensus. The first is a pretty straightforward textual one. What’s the point of providing tenure of office protections in two-thirds majority removal requirements as the U.S. Constitution and many state constitutions do, if the legislature can get around them and remove judges by a simple majority vote.

 

The second reason has to do with separation of powers. Just about any time there’s a prosecution of a judge for anything other than outright bribery, you’re going to have to fight against the specter of politically motivated interference in the judicial process.

 

In my own state of Alabama, we had what is probably the most famous ethics prosecution of a sitting judge in recent memory, the prosecution of Roy Moore. Now, many of you may be familiar with the broad outlines of the Moore episode, but I want to describe in a little more detail about how that case went down because I think it shows us just how messy and divisive these types of cases can be. And as I walk through this, I’d like you to just try to imagine how something like this might play out if it happened on the national stage with a SCOTUS justice and what effect that might have on the country.

 

So, Roy Moore started out his judicial career as a little-known circuit judge in Etowah County Alabama. And he made a name for himself when he carved out a homemade plaque of the Ten Commandments, a modern-day Moses. And he hung that plaque on his courtroom wall. Well, when the ACLU found out about it, they filed a lawsuit arguing that Moore’s display violated the Establishment Clause. Now that suit had a bunch of procedural issues, and it was eventually dismissed in 1998. But Moore rode that case to fame, and two years later the people of Alabama elected him to be the chief justice of the Alabama Supreme Court. After his election, he decided to one up himself. He had a huge monument of the Ten Commandments carved in granite. Now I’m pretty sure he didn’t make this one himself, but if you look closely, you can see on the back a little copyright symbol on the back that said, “Copyright, Roy Moore.” [Laughter].

 

In any event, he had this granite monument carved, and one night without telling any of the other justices, he had it wheeled into the rotunda of our judicial building. Now, the monument didn’t sit there long before the ACLU, to no one’s great surprise, filed another lawsuit. And this lawsuit got a lot more traction and a lot more publicity.

 

It went to trial in 2002 before federal district Judge Myron Thompson, who held that Moore had violated the Establishment Clause and ordered him to remove the monument. Moore appealed to the Eleventh Circuit and lost, and the deadline for removal of the monument came and went. But Moore publicly announced that he would refuse to comply with the court’s order. At this point, under the terms of Judge Thompson’s order, the State was facing fines of $5,000 a day until the monument was removed. So the other eight justices of our state supreme court got together and countermanded Moore, ordering that the monument be removed.

 

Meanwhile, an ethics complaint was filed against Moore before Alabama’s Judicial Inquiry Commission or the JIC for short. The JIC is a creature of the Alabama constitution, and it consists of a mix of judges, lawyers, and non-lawyers.

 

The complaint against Moore accused him of violating our canons of judicial ethics by openly flouting a binding court order. The JIC decided that the complaint had merit, so it decided that it would go ahead and prosecute the case in the Court of the Judiciary. Now the Court of the Judiciary, like the JIC, is a creature of our state constitution. It, too, is composed of a mix of judges, lawyers, and non-lawyers, and its function is to serve as the initial trial court to adjudicate any charges of violating judicial ethics.

 

Now at the time, our own Bill Pryor, now Chief Judge of the Eleventh Circuit and one of our nation’s finest appellate judges, was Alabama’s attorney general. And the obligation to prosecute the case fell to his office. Now, as you can all probably guess, Pryor didn’t think that the presence of the Ten Commandments in a judicial building necessarily violated the Establishment Clause, as now Chief Judge Pryor himself has pointed out. Depictions of the Ten Commandments have historically appeared in courtrooms all across the country, including at the judicial building a few blocks from here at One First Street.

 

Nevertheless, as the AG’s office saw it, Roy Moore’s open refusal to comply with a binding court order entered against him was an act of lawlessness incompatible with the judicial oath. And after hearing all the evidence and arguments, the Court of the Judiciary unanimously held that Moore had violated the canons and ordered him to be removed from office.

 

Moore immediately appealed. And the state supreme court consisting of retired judges especially appointed to hear his appeal unanimously affirmed the judgement of the Court of the Judiciary, and that was that. Moore was removed from office. He would go on to serve an office again, get removed from office again for yet another ethics violation, this time related to same-sex marriage, then eventually go on to run for the U.S. Senate, and I think we all remember how that turned out.

 

Now, as I’ve told it, the ethics investigation and prosecution of Roy Moore was basically as clean a process as you can imagine. One, the conduct being investigated involved a clear legal violation where the judge admitted that he was intentionally refusing to follow a binding court order and that he had no plan to change course. Two, the prosecuting attorney was a member of the same political party as the judge being investigated. And the JIC and courts at that time were populated by people who shared similar values. Three, the prosecutor very obviously had no personal motivation for going after the judge, the opposite in fact. Bill Pryor carried out the prosecution knowing full well that it could damage him politically, and despite personally agreeing that there’s nothing wrong with displaying the Ten Commandments in a judicial building. Four, there was express constitutional authorization for everything that the JIC and the Court of the Judiciary did. And five, on top of all that, the Alabama supreme court had the final say on the Court of the Judiciary’s ruling, which mitigated any separation of powers’ concerns.

 

So the stars were as aligned as they could possibly be. And yet, the prosecution and removal of Roy Moore created a political firestorm that spread across not only Alabama but the entire country. So I think it’s worth asking ourselves how this type of scene would play out at the national level where none of those stars are aligned. At the national level, one, none of the current justices have engaged in anything even remotely resembling open defiance of ethics laws. Two, I think everybody with a pulse knows that any charges against a SCOTUS justice based on a yet to be adopted ethics code would be politically motivated. And three, and very importantly, there is no clear constitutional authority for Congress to impose an ethics code on the judiciary, let alone to enforce that code. Under the United States Constitution, the justices enjoy tenure of office protections for life. And the only way Congress can remove them from the bench is through impeachment. So any ethics code is either going to be unenforceable, in which case, it’s what Carrie said, a cudgel brought out for political intimidation. Or else, to the extent it is enforceable, it would represent a transparent attempt to circumvent the impeachment process.

 

Basically, when you combine all these factors, the proposals for congressionally imposed ethics codes seem to be a recipe for a constitutional crisis. Now look, maybe that crisis would be worth dealing with if SCOTUS was facing an epidemic of bribery or corruption. Like, maybe if a bunch of the justices had started sending their ne’er-do-well adult children out to shake down foreign governments or private companies for cash. [Laughter]. I don’t know.

 

But right now I think it’s a solution in search of a problem. Thank you.

 

Hon. David Stras:  All right. Great job, Justice Mitchell. Let me just give you a little lay out. So we have decided as a panel to do a little series of questioning amongst ourselves, and I’m going to ask a series of questions we wanted to get to. And then eventually we will open it up for questions. There’s a microphone over there, and I think there’s one over there. So start thinking about questions you might have.

 

      Let me start with question one, which actually was one we did not talk about on our call, which is, you know, a lot of us talked about history, and this is, after all, originalist perspectives on the Supreme Court. But several of you alluded to this, which is the rules were different for a lot of the behavior that is being focused on in the press. And if you look it is the two, more or less, longest-serving members of the Court who are being put under a microscope. It’s Justice Thomas and Justice Alito. Of course, Chief Justice Roberts was appointed around the same time as well.  

 

      So I wonder, A) was the behavior, and the rules, were they different? Does that explain why people were doing what they were doing, so to speak? And then secondly, why now?  Why are folks coming up and talking about it now? And it might go back to the point that some of you were making, which is to just beat the Court over the head with past transgressions or things they view as past transgressions. So I hate asking compound academic questions, but those two questions go together.

 

Carrie Severino:  I think I made it pretty clear exactly why now is because they’ve lost the control of the Court. I think it’s also another why now is because people like Justice Ginsburg and Justice Breyer, who as you were saying they were -- it was striking to me when I was clerking, you know, the first weekend in July when everyone -- the Court finishes up its term and they were off of it like rats off a sinking ship going somewhere else. Almost all the justices were on flights to, like, Vienna. And Justice Thomas was in his bus, right. So it’s ironic that the people who were doing the most junkets paid for by who knows who, and now we do know some of them and some of them actually did have business before the Court. But, you know, it’s not ironic -- it’s not surprising to me that now that the liberals who were doing exactly the same things, and again I don’t think were guilty of corruption any more than Justice Thomas or Alito are or off the Court, it’s safe. It’s safe for them to do that, and that the threat is much greater because you know who cares when they’re winning and getting what they want. Right now with the originalist majority, that’s when the threat feels greater, I think, for some of these people, and they’re trying to push the Court their direction.

 

David Lat:  Oh, do I have to press this? People can hear me, right? Okay. So in terms of why now, in addition to my thesis about populism and in addition to my agreeing with Carrie about the political issue, I would say that, look, part of it has to do with people like me, as in the media, I think that this is a media-driven narrative in many ways. But here’s why I do think, and this is going to be, I guess, one of the points of disagreement since I guess I should play the liberal on this panel to make it more interesting. So, Carrie said there’s no problem here and we all agree there’s no bribery, there’s no sort of like major, major problem. One First Street is not on fire. But there’s a public perception problem, and it’s not just people on the left. There are a lot of people who are people of good faith. Americans are very common sensical, moderate, reasonable people, and there are a lot of peopleand I would put my parents and my parents-in-lawmy parents-in-law are little more to the left. My parents are a little more to the right, but they’re allthey’re not junkies about this. But if you would ask them, they would say, “Hey, we keep hearing about this Supreme Court ethics thing, and why don’t they have an ethics code?”

 

      And look, I know that perhaps to have an ethics code to sort of appeal to this big majority of just reasonable Americans based on something that was ginned up in bad faith, maybe that’s rewarding bad behavior but let’s be honest, don’t you think the bad behavior’s going to happen, anyway? So I do think that there is this issue for better or worse, the media’s created this narrative. It has affected the minds of very ordinary, reasonable common-sense Americans.

 

      And the second point I would say about this is, look, it imposes no real cost on the Court. Because, as Justice Barrett said in a recent public appearance where she basically all but endorsed having a code, they already are very ethical people who comply with these very high standards. So why not do it?

 

      Now I think one of the counter-arguments is going to be well they’re going to keep moving the goalposts. They’re never going to be happy, blah, blah, blah. And sure maybe that’s true of groups like Demand to Justice, but if you take people, again, like my parents and my parents-in-law, if you actually adopted a code and then somebody tried to say, “Oh well, the code has this thing and that thing,” you know I can basically tell them, explain to them, look, there’s a code, and it’s a very good code and a bunch of people on the far left are just trying to nitpick it.

 

      But as long as there is no code -- which that’s a fact. There is no formal binding, enforceable Code of Ethics at the Supreme Court. As long as there is no code, you’re going to have a lot of reasonable people of good faith being like, “Hey, all these lower court judges have a code, and all these people in Congress can’t accept gifts like senators and whatever. The Supreme Court justices, they’re super powerful. They’re super respected. They’re super smart. Why don’t they have to abide by a code?”

 

Hon. Jay Mitchell:  Can you hear me all right? The one thing that I haven’t seen in any of the reporting that I’ve looked at or from any of the commentators that I’ve looked at is them being able to draw a line between alleged ethics violations and somehow a justice departing from his or her judicial approachjudicial philosophy in the way that they’re deciding cases. And I think the reason that we haven’t seen that done is because it’s not occurring. I think we see a lot of nitpicking going on, and the reason I think I’m inclined to agree with Carrie on this, I think the reason that it’s occurring right now is because, yes, the left has lost control of the Court. They’re mad about it. They’ve tried one tactic, and I suppose will continue to try it in terms of trying to pack the Court and manipulate the numbers. But in the meantime, let’s just try to amp up the misery index on those who are serving. Where justices may feel like, “Hey, this is just unsustainable for me and my family. I can’t go out in public. My wife, my spouse, my kids aren’t safe, and maybe I’ll just call it a day and go home.” I don’t think Justices Thomas and Alito are in that camp, but I’m sure that’s what they’d like to try to generate.

 

      Or maybe they’ll just capitulate and start ruling and creating outcomes that the political branches like better. But I think that’s why we’re seeing this right now. We have a Court there that’sthe majority is originalist in orientation. They really are doing their level best to uphold the Constitution and the rule of law and the left’s mad about it.

 

Hon. David Stras:  All right. Now, we’ll get to some fundamental questions. And the first question is -- we talked about this a little bit. A couple of people alluded to it, which is, “Should the Supreme Court adopt a code, and if the answer is yes, what should it say?”

 

Carrie Severino:  So, I will say no, and here’s -- but I also want to explain a little bit. You know, in response to some of the concerns that I have heard as well, David, from people, like, the idea of, like, “Wow, how come the lower courts are so bound and the Supreme Court isn’t?”

 

      I think there’s also been a lack of understanding of what this Court actually is required to do. The Court is not some kind of wild west where the justices can do whatever they want. They actually do have totheir [Loss of audio 00:57:14 - 00:57:30] just because they have this code of conduct. That’s not the case either. The judges are the ones -- just like at the Supreme Court, who interpret the code of conduct. Violations of the code of conduct are not per se grounds for a judicial misconduct filing. So you can’t just say, “Well, this Judge didn’t recuse in this case that I filed a motion for recusal, so ergo I’m going to bring this before some other commission.” You can’t do that. So I think part of the challenge is, is we’re overstating the amount of -- both the amount of freedom the Supreme Court has because they do have serious requirements and they have a lot of disclosure requirements. [Loss of audio 00:58:01 to 00:58:18]

 

David Lat:  There should be a code and in terms of the content of it, I think it’s very simple. I would have them adopt a code of conduct for U.S. judges, the one that applies to circuit and district courts around the country. Now, there’s a tweak. I will agree with the arguments that when it comes to recusal because there are only nine of them and you don’t want a shorthanded Court every other case, the recusal rules, you know, maybe need to be, you know, maybe the standard is maybe higher because you can’t just pick a judge out of the wheel. But I do think that that code is a very good solid code. And I would just be happy with that.

 

      We can talk -- a lot of people are talking about enforcement and some of the CLE readings that you’ll see there. I think Glenn Fine talks about having basically an inspector general of the Court, which the Court could pick itself if it wanted, going to Carrie’s point about judges regulating judges. But I don’t even necessarily need that right now. I just think that if a justice has voluntarily adopted a code, and it was the code of conduct for the U.S. judges, I would be happy with that.

 

      But here’s the thing I will say, and I know there’s some judges in the audience, like my old boss, and this is my vision for the lower courts and the Supreme Court, and I think some of you are really going to like this. Crackdown dramatically on freebies but jack up your salaries way high. [Laughter and Applause]. Because, like, I think part of this isDavid Brook’s has this concept called, like, Status Income Disequilibrium. When you’re a person of high status but you’re hanging out with these people who earn way more money, and it kind of chafes a little bit. Whereas, like, look, like, if Justice Thomas earned -- the number I have in my mind for the justices is $1 million dollars. If justices earned $1 million dollars, Justice Thomas would not need to take out -- get a gift from his friend or a loan from his friend for the RV. Justice Thomas can just be like, “I want the RV. I mean I earn a million dollars a year.” [Laughter].

 

And the other thing I would say is, look, this has implications for the quality of folks on the bench. And this is -- and the lower courts, I don’t know, how about Judge’s O'Scannlain, what half a mil, would that be good? [Laughter]. Hey, you raised eight kids on, you know whatever it was back then, so. So, maybe half a million dollars for the lower court judges. Because look, right now, we are seeing lower court judges fleeing well before they’re even eligible for senior status. And some of these are the best judges on the bench, and they’re retiring because they have kids going to college and on what they make, they can’t cover multiple college tuitions. Meanwhile, Milbank just raised associate salaries, now a first year is making $225,000 a year. That’s not that much lower than a federal judge. So, I would say, look, crack down dramatically on the freebies, really hold their feet to the fire, no more free RVs, or trips to  Indonesia or whatever, but you get a million dollars.

 

Hon. Jay Mitchell:  I don’t think the Court should adopt an ethics code. I think like most federal regulations, they tend to do more harm than good. And my concern isI suppose the devil’s always in the detailsbut my concern is that even if it’s an internal code at the Court in the form of internal rules or protocols, that’s going to be weaponized in some way as well against conservative justices, even if it’s just the left and the media trying to weaponize it in the court of public opinion. Or enterprising senators across the street deciding that somehow that creates a hook for them to start sending endless, invasive discovery requests or other things. So, I think it’s a bad idea.

 

      That said, if the Court were to adopt one, I’ll just accept that premise for a second, Judge Stras, I think any rules should be bright-line rules. You know, I think vague open-ended rules might work all right. They work well potentially in a well-functioning society or a well-functioning environment. I get concerned about the political environment here in Washington. And I think if you had vague open-ended rules, it would be easy to manipulate and to weaponize. So I think it’s important if the Court were to do that -- and I’m not in favor of them doing that, I think they’re handling things responsibly as it is. But if they did, I think it would be important to have bright-line rules that are easy to understand, easy to follow, easy to apply.

 

Hon. David Stras:  All right. So one thing I think is interwoven in a lot of these remarks is being a justice is a tough job. It’s very difficult. You lose a lot of anonymity. You can’t go out in public. You have security following you around. The friends that you have, I think, sometimes become more distant because of the limitations that you have. And so one of the things I think I worry about -- it’s a great job. I mean, I’m sure it’s a great job, but at the same time there are limitations to what you can do. And so, you know, I worry about is any code going to be enough for Congress in the sense that if they adopt a code they’re going to say for exampleDavid, you mentioned thiswhich is recusal rules. That immediately Congress is going to come out and say why not the same recusal rules. This is outrageous. They’re not having to recuse like lower court judges are having to recuse. So I worry about sort of this ramping up to the point where it really puts a strain on the Court. It puts a strain on the justices where maybe the justices need to go away, you know, to be able to vacation and not put themselves or their family in harm. I don’t know if that’s true or not, but I guess my point is, is it going to be enough for Congress, and are we going to see a gradual ramping up in terms of rhetoric and maybe Congress acting?

 

David Lat:  So what I would say about the code is, look, they’re always going to be politicized, actions, and bad-faith actors. But, if there is a code, unless you are just kind of -- there’s always -- look, despite, you know with problems I have with some of ProPublica’s reporting and they’ve done a lot of these, you know, scoops. You know, there’s always some sort of factual germ and maybe they’ve kind of twisted some things and tweaked some things. They’ve omitted some things, but there’s always something there. Like, okay, Justice and Mrs. Thomas did go to Indonesia. Like, they don’t just make stuff up completely out of whole cloth. Like, they don’t say that Chief Justice Roberts went to Indonesia because I don’t think he did. So if we had a code of conduct, you know, again, this is Justice Barrett’s point, 99 percent of the time there are not going to be any issues. And, if they make stuff up, well then, it can be shot down just like in various Supreme Court confirmation hearings. Things get made up, and they get shot down. So, again, I am not as worried about the specter of just, oh, once there’s a code it’s going to be another thing to hit them over the head. There will be a code. Ninety-nine percent of the time, there’s going to be no question as to compliance, and everything’s going to be fine.

 

Hon. David Stras:  Anyone else?

 

Hon. Jay Mitchell:  Yeah, I think perhaps there is a danger that Congress says whatever you do, if anything, is unacceptable and we’re going to do our own ethics code via statute. As I talked about earlier, I think that would be unconstitutional. There may be some argument under the Necessary and Proper Clause that somebody might try to make. I think it would be a weak argument. And there would certainly have to be careful attention paid to not invading the judicial power under Article III, but I could see somebody trying to come along and make that argument.

 

      But look, I mean, Congress passes -- I mean, arguably passes unconstitutional laws all the time. [Laughter] I think the real question here is enforcement. How, if at all, could Congress enforce it? And I think we would probably end up arriving at a situation that we see too frequently today, sadly, where the investigation and the charging process itself becomes the punishment. Congress says we’ve passed a statute, we’ve got tools in our toolbox, and now it’s going to be endless subpoenas across the street, invasive discovery, showing up at the justice’s office or home to interview them, harassing and pestering their friends and associates until the misery index is amped up so high that the justice says, “No mas,” or, you know, tries to capitulate in some other way. I don’t think our current line of justices would yield in that way, but I think it creates more dangerous conditions where you just have endless rounds of investigation and charging. You know, I can’t imagine that the justices are -- they and their clerks spend so much time trying to decide the weightiest legal cases that we have in the nation, and that takes all their time, all their energy, all their bandwidth, and having to divert from that to deal with Congress and subpoenas and endless discovery, I think, is a recipe for disaster.

 

Hon. David Stras:  Go ahead, David.

 

David Lat:  So I’ll just makeagain, I’m trying to, you know, be the liberal or progressive on this panel. So one point I would make isagain, going to my point about how you can’t make the things up completely out of whole cloth. So I have a podcast for my Substack Original Jurisdiction, and one of my guests was Gabe Roth, who is the head of Fix the Court. And this is one of the organizations that’s always—you know, I shouldn’t say always—that is frequently criticizing various ethical lapses. And some people, some conservatives, you know, have big problems with Gabe, you know, he admitted to me in the podcast, that he, himself is personally to the left, sure. So one thing that Gabe and I did was, I said, “Okay. Let’s go through all of the nine justices and go through all of their, their kind of scandals, and I want you to rate them on a one to ten.” So, you know, Gabe did that. And, you know, he had various numbers, various scandals, etc.

 

But you can’t make stuff up that’s not there. Gabe, who has definitely been a hawk on these things and no one’s going to accuse him of being a squish, when we got to Justice Barrett, he’s like, yep, nothing, like, she’s clean. I don’t have anything. Like, you know, again, is demand justicewhat are they maybe, they’ll like, I don’t know, plant a Rolex in her, like, kid’s stroller, I don’t know. But, like, it’syou can’t make stuff up. And so if the justices just keep their noses clean and stick to the code of conduct for the U.S. judges, the $415 gift limit or whatever it is, again, I think things are going to be fine.

 

Carrie Severino:  I would for -- if you just keep your nose clean and do the right thing and everything’s going to be fine, ask Brett Kavanaugh how that worked for him after he had --

 

[Applause]

 

David Lat:  He’s on the Supreme Court. Like, I said, people, the stuff got shot down.

 

Carrie Severino:  If you took a survey of the American people of how many people think that he’s an alleged rapist or was going around to parties in Maryland, you know, raping young women, a shocking number despite the bizarre implausibility and absolute lack of evidence is probably going to say that’s happening. There are lots of people out there saying that’s happening today. These are real issues. He had been through just six different FBI investigations. There clearly was nothing there, and it still happens.

 

      Take demand justices attempts to get Judge Griffith in trouble, for example. They were going crazy alleging that he maybe had retired at the time that he did because of bribes. Nothing to it, right. He retired because his wife was ill. He wasn’t wanting to disclose her medical condition, and yet they’re forced into it.

 

      Unfortunately, there are just bad faith actors going on here. I would love it if people just were being honest and clear about it, but that’s not what’s happening. This is why Justice Breyer and, as you kind of alluded to, there should be a different standard for recusal than appellate courts. Justice Breyer talked about that. He said, “Look at an appellate court level if someone has to recuse just maybe have a thumb on the scale of recusal because there’s a lot of other judges in line that can sit on that panel. If it’s at the Supreme Court, it’s a set fixed number. We all know kind of where they stand on things. There’s a significantly greater danger of strategic recusals. And we all know from the period when like after Justice Scalia died how bad that can be just from a functional standard.

 

My term on the case, Justice Breyer was recused from an Exxon Valdez punitive damages lawsuit, it was like the largest lawsuit in the history of the universe. And went 4-4 because he had to be recused and that was because of some stock things because his wife like’s an heiress or something. So, but that’s a problem. And it’s a problem having people recused left and right. And I think we are kidding ourselves if we think it’s going to all be good faith. It’s going to be a huge administrative burden. I think already -- you think filing your taxes is bad, imagine if you had to keep the kind of records they already have to keep with respect to disclosure and everything else. It’s a non-zero burden on the justices and burden on the wheels of justice, not to mention the fact that we know it’s going to be abused to attempt to get strategic recusals on the Court.

 

David Lat:  But have we seen them going after very conservative lower court judges.

 

Carrie Severino:  Yes. [Laughs]

 

David Lat:  Demand justiceI mean, you mention Judge Griffith, but like there’s a huge number of conservative judges who are just going about their lives, and they are not subject to any ethics stuff. Like, so, spurious things will be --

 

Carrie Severino:  Matthew Kaczmarek. I mean, there are -- if you get a high enough profile case, you will get people coming after you. And I think that is the problem. And it’s always going to be a low -- and the problem is, the Supreme Court is always on the high-profile cases. There will be people coming after them. And then just, you know, going back to my experience as a parent, sometimes, it’s just like when you knoweven if in a vacuumokay, if they had for the last hundred years or for however, whenever the Code of Ethics was given to which probably wasn’t even maybe it was the 1960s, like you were talking about high time for court ethics things, maybe that’s when the lower courts adopted theirs. If they’d had adopted it then, I think we might not be in as big of a situation. At the moment, I think, if the Court adopted one, it would look like they are capitulating to this kind of senatorial arm twisting and threats and mafiosi style threats against the institution. I think that almost would be a bigger threat to the Court in and of itself because it looks like they are in a chokehold by the legislative branch.

 

Hon. David Stras:  All right. So, we’re going to get to questions after, one, I just want to take a quick survey. Anyone think, we briefly talked about enforcement, does anyone think on the panelI’m sure there are opinions out therebut does anyone on the panel think that Congress should be the one who enforces the ethics code, whether it’s court made or otherwise.  So everyone agrees that it needs to be the judicial branch, or somebody appointed by the judicial branch.

 

[Carrie and David nodding “yes”]  Okay. All right. I noticed people are lining up over here.

 

John Reeves:  Hi. Is this on? Okay. Hello, my name’s John Reeves. I’m a solo appellate lawyer in St. Louis. I’d like the whole -- my question is for the whole panel. I would like to hear their thoughts and comments and whether they agree with recent comments the former Fourth Circuit judge and finalist for Chief Justice J. Michael Luttig recently made in an interview with NPR. And to make sure I don’t misquote him, I’m going to quote him completely and then I will step away. He said, “I believe the federal judges should essentially live like priests or saints or monks. The collegiality that you enjoy on the federal bench is really only among your colleagues on the federal bench. As soon as you step beyond that, you’re at risk of associating with people who could well have matters that come before you or who might well have an interest in the cases that come before you, financial or otherwise.” I welcome the panel’s comments on Judge Luttig’s comments.

 

      You want me to -- whoever wants to go first?

 

Carrie Severino:  Sure. A) I don’t think we should require either vows of celibacy or becoming a

     hermit –

 

[Laughter]

 

-- Particularly on the Supreme Court. I just don’t think that’s appropriate. And B) if we’re seriously so worried that we think people are having any contact with the outside world, they have to be empaneled like a jury for the rest of their lives, I think that’s -- how can we trust these people to decide serious, important constitutional questions? We’re entrusting them with a whole lot more judgement than that, and I think if they are this untrustworthy, then the whole enterprise is doomed.

 

David Lat:  So I really like and respect Judge Luttig, but I do have a couple of quibbles. I agree   

with Carrie that it is not necessarily good for people who are deciding real-world issues to be    so removed from the real world. And I think there’s also again, the disincentive problem. You already earn less than, you know, mid-level associates, and now you’re also going to have to have no friends. It doesn’t sound terribly attractive.

 

[Laughter]

 

But you know—and I can’t remember the lastso gosh, what was the point? Sorry, go ahead Justice Mitchell, let me think.

 

Hon. Jay Mitchell:  Yeah. What I would say there, I agree with both Carrie and David on this, I think first of all you’re discouraging some really well-qualified lawyers and judges from coming to the bench, mainly the extroverts.

 

[Laughter]

 

      If that’s the standard. And we should want extroverts on the federal bench. But I also think you’re losing engagement with the public. I think it’s important -- I mean, first of all, these are human beings, and they are presiding over cases involving human beings. So I think we want them to have engagement with the public through their church or their synagogue or at the ball field or out in the community. We want our judges to do that. It makes them -- I think it makes them better judges.

 

David Lat:  Now, look, I don’t -- just to, I now remember the point I wanted to make. So if a Judge voluntarily wants to lead that kind of life, that’s fine. And it does lead to a very clean absence of ethics problems. It’s kind of the acronym “WWDSD” What would David Souter do?

 

[Laughter]

 

So if you, like, accept no speaking engagements, you go on no vacations other than going to home in New Hampshire. Now, it’s kind of apocryphal that he, like, lived with his mom the whole time but, you know --

 

[Laughter]

 

-- like, if you just, you know, if you just lead this cloistered life and don’t do anything then, yes, you’ll have a very clean ethics record, but I don’t think he was necessarily a better justice than, say, the super-gregarious Justice Scalia.

 

Hon. David Stras:  Yeah. And I just want to add as somebody who’s done jobs at different levels, there are different levels of sort of a monastic lifestyle that you lead at different levels. So the judiciary, right? So a trial judge is going to see a lot more people because people are going to come into the courtroom. A state supreme court justice, you know, will spend more time with the Bar because they have to spend time with the Bar. They have to be on rules committees, and they have to do disciplinarian and judicial ethics things. And then sort of as you go further and further up sort of the chain into the federal system, Supreme Court being sort of the most monastic in part because they’re limited. I mean, you’ve got to have security and everything else. But court of appeals judges, we have a pretty solitary lifestyle, too. If you spend a lot of time on your work, it’s just you, your clerks, and your judicial assistant many days. And then what little human interaction you get outside of that tends to be on nights and weekends. And so, you know, I clerked for Judge Luttig, but I don’t know that I signed up for being a hermit in a cave. So, those are just my observations. I think it’s demanding something that would not lead to good mental health, I think --

 

[Laughter]

 

-- to not have your friends anymore. All right, we’ll go over here.

 

Coach Weinhaus:  Oh, thank you. Coach Weinhaus, Yeshiva University and UCLA. Also, a board member of Legal Accountability Project, but I’m not speaking on its behalf, just to be clear. But appreciate the mention, Mr. Lat. What do you make of the idea of the Supreme Court justices active lobbying through a business league of all federal judges? And the reason I ask is this would follow at least one state supreme court justices. That’s at least what one state does with their Supreme Court and their lower-level judges working together in a business league. And I guess, I particularly like to ask or hear if Justice Mitchell would be in favor in his state of joining judges under him, who he supervises, in a business league for lobbying purposes.

 

Hon. Jay Mitchell:  Do you mean like an association of lower court judges who are like lobbying the legislature for an appropriation or something like that?

 

Coach Weinhaus:  Yes, 501(c)6 Business League Lobbying Trade Association is what that is. And Supreme Court justices or the higher-level judges doing it alongside the lower-level judges.

 

Hon. Jay Mitchell:  Yeah. I’m probably not familiar with the intricacies of your question, but for example, in my home state there’s a Circuit Judges Association, there’s a District Judges Association who will atthey have leadership. They’ll advocate for things that are important to the trial courts. There’s not supervision by our court in doing that, although there is interfacing that goes on with the lower court judges through judges conferences and otherwise. But I’mI apologize --

 

Coach Weinhaus:  My issue is with the Supreme Court justices join those leagues of the lower court judges.

 

Hon. Jay Mitchell:  I don’t know. I haven’t thought about that.

 

Coach Weinhaus:  Okay.

 

Hon. David Stras:  All right. So far, so good. We’re going to go over here, and everyone’s been doing a great job but just keep your questions as sort of just a question so that we can get through as many of them as we possibly can.

 

Harry Lewis:  Hi, Harry Lewis, practicing in New York. The leak of the Dobbs’ opiniondoes the panel have any opinion or comment about how the Court managed that and the outcome of that?

 

Carrie Severino:  Well, it suggests maybe we need an ethics code for clerks --

 

[Laughter]

 

-- not justices. I would have loved to see the person found. I’m relieved to see that we have --I was very concerned that if you don’t respond forcefully to bad behavior it’s going to continue, and I was worried that there would be further leaks.

 

I think maybe what happened is everyone across the board realized that it was both outrageous, it was an offense against the institution, and I think more importantly those who -- I presume the person who leaked it thought they might stop the outcome, and they realized it was also ineffective. And that, of course, is the original sin in any kind of political move. So as long as it’s ineffective, I think it will not continue.

 

David Lat:  What Carrie said.

 

Hon. Jay Mitchell:  I agree.

 

Hon. David Stras:  All right. Let’s go over here.

 

Anna Bergstrom:  Hello. My name is Anna Bergstrom, a former law clerk and now a practitioner in North Dakota. My question has to do with non-judicial enforcement. The panel already barely touched on this, but I would have liked a little more in depth. The judicial code at the Supreme Court and also at lower federal courts. For instance, a little background, then I’ll say my question, so you understand. For instance, I’m aware that the idea has been floated of having Congress appointing an external monitoring overseer of lower federal courts in each circuit to ensure compliance with the ethics rules that they are subject to. That’s my question. What do you believe is the best constitutional argument for a congressionally or an executively mandated ethics code and a potential monitoring for enforcement of that code, and how would you legally debunk that argument? I understand the Justice mentioned the Necessary and Proper Clause and earlier mentioned the Power of the Purse. But I’d like to know more of your thoughts on that.

 

David Lat:  So in the materials, there’s actually an interesting article from Professor Frost of UVA where she makes the case in twenty pages or so, maybe it was -- I can’t remember was it congressional testimony, but she does make the argument for a code including some outside monitoring. I think that she does make the argument that Justice Mitchell alluded to about the Necessary and Proper Clause. She talks about all the ways in which the Congress already regulates the Court in different ways. And she also draws the distinction which you commonly hear from advocates of a code between a kind of decisional independence and between something that is kind of they cast as more like, kind of like housekeeping or something.

 

        And I think they try to say, “Look, we all agree that you can’t say pass a law to, you know, to change how the Supreme Court’s going to rule in something or something like that, but you can do things that are more sort of administrative in nature.” But look, even though I’m the liberal on the panel, I do share Judge Stras’s concern that that’s a slippery slope. You can say, “Oh, I’m just, you know, I’m just regulating, you know, your administrative stuff. But, oh, maybe all the regulation seems aimed at certain justices with certain views.” So, I don’t know that I completely buy Professor Frost’s distinction, but it is one that is made between this decisional independence and between this stuff that just goes to sort of HR and admin and all of that.

 

Hon. David Stras:  Anyone else?

 

Hon. Jay Mitchell:  Yeah, I think probably the argument would be made as I alluded to earlier under the Necessary and Proper Clause of Article I Section A. I think it’s a weak argument. And I think that it probably -- the kind of proposal you’re describing would be an invasion of the judicial power. I also think that, you know, I’m just wondering how that would even be enforced even if it were put into place.

 

Anna Bergstrom:  Justice, if I may interrupt, if I may. One idea I had heard from some judicial overseers -- now, I’m not advocating for this position, so please understand that. But as having an external monitor come into each circuit and so not judicially appointed, and I had heard various concerns about that as I well share. But I’ve been curious about the -- how would we debunk that on a very strong level.

 

Hon. Jay Mitchell:  Yeah. I think any kind of enforcement mechanism that would seek to undermine or circumvent the impeachment and removal requirements, I think would be unconstitutional on arrival, in my opinion. You know, I could foresee a situation where, like some kind of monitoring framework got set up. The monitor spotting supposed violations and somehow the judge or justice is sanctioned in some way for that that would have effectively sidelined him or her without having to go through the impeachment and removal process. So, I just think it’s probably unconstitutional all the way down.

 

Hon. Justice Stras:  All right. Let’s move on over here.

 

Questioner 5:  Justice Mitchell, half of a lifetime ago, the Alabama legislature passed a statute that had real low contribution disclosure limits and potential recusal and it got hung up on whether it needed to be pre-cleared, which shows how old that is. Has the Court had to deal with that statute?

 

Hon. Jay Mitchell:  Yeah. With the Alabama disclosure statute?

 

Questioner 5:  And with the tied recusal?

 

Hon. Jay Mitchell:  Not since I’ve been there. Yeah, and I’ve been on the court now for four and a half years. Thanks, Jack.

 

Hon. David Stras:  All right. We’ll go over here.

 

Francios-Henry Briard:  Yeah. Good afternoon. My name is Briard, I am the President of the French chapter of The Federalist Society.

 

[Applause]

 

        Thank you for that excellent panel. I had two short remarks. The first remark is that you are talking about rules, right, code, rules. To me and to many of my compatriots and I’m sure to many of judges in this country, ethics is not a matter of the rules, first. It’s a matter of spirit. It’s a matter of personal awareness, I think, that’s the main point.

 

[Applause]

 

        The second remark is this one. You know, I had the privilege to have a very close friend here in this country. His name was Justice Antonin Scalia. He has been my mentor for twenty-five years. Justice Scalia came to Paris once in 1999. And I took him to the Conseil d’État, my Supreme Court. I’ve been in the practice of the Court for 36 years. Justice Scalia spent two days at the Conseil d’État and then he say to me, “You know, Francois, these are bureaucrats under the influence of politicians.”

 

[Laughter]

 

        So you have the best Judiciary in the world, and my recommendation, I understand that you are talking about code of conduct and all these things, but my recommendation would be do not make your justices bureaucrats under the influence of politicians. Thank you.

 

[Laughter and Applause]

 

Hon. David Stras:  Boy, that’s a hard one to follow up on. Any comments? I would say, one thing -- I’m just going to go ahead and say it, and I think Carrie has something to say, maybe, too, but—

 

Carrie Severino:  I was just going to say I’ll drink to that.

 

Hon. David Stras:  [CROSSTALK] Getting the waterthere you go—is, you know, I agree with that as far as we have one of the best judiciaries in the world. I mean, I’ve never served on another country’s judiciary. But I feel very good about where we are and the colleagues I have, and their ethics and they try to maintain the highest ethical standards. And I have no reason to believe that anyone on the U.S. Supreme Court thinks any different than I do. And so we just have to be careful about harming a good thing sometimes.

 

Carrie Severino:  Yeah. Maybe I will follow up on that because I think that is one of the risks of all of this enterprise is we really do have a Court that is being -- not just I agree with it because they are being faithful to the original understanding of the Constitution, but we have judges and justices who are trying to do their best by their ethical obligations. And by suggesting that’s otherwise, we undermine the public’s confidence in the Court. So the fact that your family members are all thinking there’s something shady going on when in fact there is not—        and even people as crazy as Senator Whitehouse are not willing to stand up there and say there’s a single case that anyone has voted differently on—that is doing a disservice to our entire country and the institution because then people who ought to be feeling confident and proud of their courts are thinking there’s something going on that isn’t. And we really should be able to be proud of those courts.

 

David Lat:  So I actually agree with what you’re saying, Carrie and I am very concerned with rewarding bad actors and bad behavior. But I also kind of think that we have to live in the world as it is and not as we wish it would be. I think we wish that we didn’t have, say, bad faith political actors and journalists ginning up this narrative, but unfortunately, there are a lot of moderate, normal, ordinary Americans of good faith who are under missed impressions. And if you have a code, at least we can throw that back in the face of critics of the Court and be like there’s a code. They follow it. Have a nice day.

 

[Laughter]

 

Hon. David Stras:  All right. We have one over here. Go ahead.

 

Timothy Campbell:  All right. Timothy Campbell, one of Uncle Sam’s many appellate attorneys.

 

[Laughter]

 

        I have a quick question. So if there was, let’s say hypothetically that the Supreme Court had a code, how would you limit or put limits on, like, internal enforcement? And the example I take since I deal a lot with the Federal Circuit with the Judge Newman issue. Because it seems like right now, the Federal Circuit’s just punishing her because she had the audacity to turn 96.

 

David Lat:  And to have different opinions on patents than some of her colleagues.

 

Timothy Campbell:  Yes. I just wondered if you could speak to, like, internal limitations or how that case would impact this issue.

 

David Lat:  So, I’ve actually written a fair amount about the Judge Newman situation on my Substack newsletter Original Jurisdiction. And I’m very deeply troubled by what is going on here. And itagain, I guess I’m what passes for the hawk here on ethics. But I like to say, look, let judges regulate judges, and it should be fine. But I think what’s going on in the Federal Circuit is judges sort of regulating judges and it’s not fine. Judge Pauly Newman is 95, 96. She’s a highly respected member of the Federal Circuit. She is still in active status, not senior status. And her colleagues are basically trying to push her out. They claim that she is sort of out of it, but by many accounts, she is not. And she goes to conferences like this one and gives very fluent speeches and she certainly seems very “with it.” But, oh, lo and behold, she happens to be called the great dissenter of that court. She has very different views on patent rights than some of her other colleagues.

 

So you have to -- I do share the concern even though I’m the liberal or the hawk or whatever, I do share the concern that even when judges are running the situation as opposed to Congress, which I do not support, even judges implementing and enforcing a code of their own design, even that can be abused. So I have concerns and the Judge Newman situation, which I was going to actually mention if you hadn’t mentioned it already, I’m very, very troubled.

 

And look, I’m also very troubled by the due process issue here. Because what happened here is her colleagues are witnesses. Her colleagues are affected by her presence on the court. And her colleagues are the ones who are investigating her. And what should have happened in this case, which is what routinely happens, is this should have been transferred to the judicial counsel of another circuit, but they refuse to. And they basically said, “Well, you see, we’re the closest to the facts. We know what’s going on.” Well, like you can’t have a judge preside over sexual harassment case involving like their recently left former firm because I know all the partners here, so I know who’s really into sexual harassment. You don’t want a judge who’s tied to the facts. You want a judge who’s impartial and who doesn’t have firsthand knowledge of the players. So, I’m very, very troubled by the Judge Newman affair.

 

Hon. David Stras:  All right. We are running -- we are out of time. In case -- no, no, you’re good. Anyone else want to comment on that, or should we leave it there? Well, all right. Well, thank you all. Thank our wonderful panelists. Great panel, and see you later.

 

[Applause]

 

 

3:30 p.m. - 5:00 p.m.
After Dobbs and Samia: The Potential Implications of Applying a Dobbs Lens to the Supreme Court’s Constitutional Criminal Jurisprudence

2023 National Lawyers Convention

Topics: Criminal Law & Procedure • Jurisprudence
East Room
The Mayflower Hotel
1127 Connecticut Avenue NW
Washington, DC 20006

Share

Event Video

Listen & Download

Description

Stare Decisis, a Latin term meaning “let it stand,” is a key element of how American law is interpreted, applied, and adjudicated. When applied, it leads courts to stand by decided cases, to uphold precedents, and/or to maintain former adjudications. How exactly that principle should be applied, however, is a topic of some debate. In Dobbs v. Jackson Women’s Health Organization, the Supreme Court held that a proper application of stare decisis required an assessment of the strength of the grounds on which the prior precedent was based. That articulation has led some to question: what are the implications of applying that conception of stare decisis to the Court’s constitutional criminal jurisprudence under the Fourth, Fifth, Sixth, and Eighth Amendments? What might be its effect on those rights and remedies?

Featuring:

  • Hon. John F. Bash, III, Partner, Quinn Emanuel
  • Mr. Michael Caruso, Federal Public Defender, Southern District of Florida
  • Prof. Meghan J. Ryan, Co-Director, Tsai Center for Law, Science and Innovation, Altshuler Distinguished Teaching Professor, and Professor of Law, Southern Methodist University Dedman School of Law
  • Prof. John Stinneford, Edward Rood Eminent Scholar Chair, Professor of Law, & Senior Fellow, Hamilton Center for Classical and Civic Education, Levin College of Law, University of Florida
  • Moderator: Hon. Amul Thapar, United States Court of Appeals, Sixth Circuit

Overflow: Chinese Room

Speakers

Event Transcript

John Richter:  I'm John Richter. I chair The Federalist Society's Criminal Law and Procedure Executive Committee, and it's my pleasure to be able to introduce Amul Thapar -- Judge Thapar. Really, number one claim to fame is that he was nominated to be a United States attorney the same day that I was. And but for his nomination, I'm pretty sure I probably never would have gotten through the Senate. But we were a package deal and the skids were greased. The other thing I'd say, obviously, about Judge Thapar, of course, is having served on the district court and on the Court of Appeals and having been an Assistant United States Attorney in two different districts, as well as, obviously, United States Attorney, he brings a wealth of background and experience, practical as well as, obviously, all of his teaching and whatnot.

 

Finally, I think my closest connection to Judge Thapar is he's reputed to have made, at least according to Wikipedia, because that's where I do my research. He's reputed to have made a reference in a decision describing fraud as, essentially, if a bar says they serve Pappy Van Winkle, but is, in fact, serving Old Crow, that is fraud. That is truly Kentuckian. And I can tell you, given that my next-door neighbor is Julian Van Winkle, that would be a travesty. So without further ado, let me introduce Judge Thapar.

 

I will say for CLE purposes, if you're pursuing that, obviously, if you want to get credit, you need to go and sign in and out each day. You can also do it -- I think there are QR codes somewhere. Make sure that if you've not checked in, you scan the QR code on the back of your convention booklet or one of the posters. I think there will be a code at the end of this that I believe Judge Thapar will read out to you. Finally, I do want to emphasize that obviously, the practice groups, including the criminal law and procedure practice groups, are open for business. We urge your participation and interest in those. And then, as I understand, I'm told that I'm supposed to also announce some kind of bus schedule, because there's really no task too small. If you've got tickets for the Scalia Memorial dinner, the location, of course, is at the Washington Hilton. And shuttle buses to the Hilton, evidently, from here, run starting at 5:15 and run until 6:30 every five minutes. The pickup, I believe, is on Desales Street on the side. So without further ado, Judge Thapar. Thank you.

 

Hon. Amul Thapar:  Thank you, John. And I think it was the other way around. I only got through because I rode your coattails. But it's an honor to be here with this amazing panel. I think you're going to really like it. Each of the panelists are going to talk for five to ten minutes. We'll keep it short so we can have some dialogue amongst the panel. And then question and answer -- I want to emphasize one thing about questions. The sentence always, there's no exceptions, ends with a question mark. And so I want to be very clear that judges are good at cutting people off. That's why they let us be moderators. So you can get up and ask a question, but if you make a speech, you will sit down or you can exit stage right. So please get up and ask questions. We encourage it, but questions only.

 

So, first, I would like to introduce John Bash. And John is the co-chair of the National Appellate Practice and co-managing partner of the Austin office of Quinn Emmanuel. At one point, he held the job that John and I both call the greatest job in the world. Not John Bash, but John Richter and I. But John Bash says it's an okay job, and working in the SG's office was much better.

 

Hon. John F. Bash III:  I would use a stronger word than okay. Good job.

 

Hon. Amul Thapar:  He was the United States Attorney for the Western District of Texas from 2017 to 2020. As I mentioned, he was also assistant to the Solicitor General. He clerked on the Circuit Court for Judge Kavanaugh and the Supreme Court for Justice Scalia.

 

Next to him going second is Michael Caruso. Michael Caruso is the federal public defender, which I can tell you, like the US attorney, is an extremely important job, probably harder in many ways, but in both jobs, you have a lot of responsibility. And one of the cool things he's done -- and their bios are available to you but I'm just emphasizing a few things -- is he was lead counsel in the criminal case against Jose Padilla in the Southern District of Florida and before his indictment, for the many of you that are too young to remember this, he was being held as an enemy combatant under an executive order signed by President Bush. Caruso -- I'm skipping now -- obviously, in his job as the federal public defender, not only manages the office, but represents many individual clients and serves on many local and national committees that advocate for criminal justice reform. He earned his law degree from the University of Florida Law School and clerked for Judge Zloch on the United States District Court for the Southern District of Florida.

 

Next to him and going third is Professor Meg Ryan. Professor Ryan is the co-director of the Tsai Center for Law, Science and Innovation, Altshuler Distinguished Teaching Professor and Professor of Law at Southern Methodist University. All those words say to me, she's just really smart. She's an award-winning teacher and scholar at the intersection of criminal law and procedure, torts, and law and science. One of the important things about her is she practiced at Dorsey and Whitney. I love professors that actually practiced law and were in the courtroom. And she focused her practice on, among other things, commercial and intellectual property litigation and white-collar defense and compliance. Before joining SMU, she was a professor at the University of Minnesota School of Law, where she taught criminal law, Crim pro, and sales.

 

Last but not least is Professor John Stinneford. He's the Edward Rood Eminent Scholar, chair, professor of Law and Senior fellow, Hamilton Center for Classical and Civic Education, Levin College of Law, University of Florida. Again, that just means smart. I wish they would shorten their titles and just say smart professor of law. His work has been cited numerous times by the United States Supreme Court, several state supreme courts, federal courts of appeal, and numerous scholars. Like his fellow professor, he also practiced in the courtroom, and he practiced both at Winston and Strawn and as an Assistant United States Attorney, which is also an amazing job. And he teaches first year courses in crim law and con law and upper level courses in many things, including criminal procedure and federal criminal law and white collar crime. So without further ado, I'll turn it over to John.

 

Hon. John F. Bash III:  Thank you, Judge, and thanks everybody, for being here. So I think our prompt is criminal law in the wake of Dobbs. So Dobbs being the abortion decision, if anyone in the room is not aware of the title, and I guess I'll just start by completely reversing the framing of that and talking briefly about Dobbs in the wake of criminal procedure, because I think the mode of analysis where precedents were questioned and overruled based on originalist understanding really started with criminal procedure. As I'm sure you all know, for many years, Justice Scalia and then eventually Justice Thomas were lone voices in favor of originalist understandings in various cases, but they actually started translating those into wins, essentially by joining with more liberal leaning members of the Court in the area of criminal procedure.

 

And I'll just give some examples of that. Justice Scalia, I think, had said that one of his two favorite majority opinions was Crawford v. Washington, which is the opinion that, in his view, at least, restored the original understanding of the Confrontation Clause, which entitles criminal defendants to confront witnesses against them. And in a case called Ohio v. Roberts in the early '90s, the Supreme Court had essentially said, "Well, you sort of have a right to confront, but if there's indicia of reliability for the out of Court statement that was not confronted, that's okay, too." And via a sort of balancing test, practical analysis had on some views watered down the confrontation right. In Crawford v. Washington in 2004, the Supreme Court overruled Ohio v. Roberts and said, "No. Under the original understanding, the right to confrontation means the right not to have unconfronted hearsay, testimonial hearsay, used against you in Court." And so unless it falls into a historical exception or is not testimonial, which was a concept explored in later cases, or you had an opportunity to confront before trial, you can't use those statements.

 

And what's telling about Crawford and will be telling about all the cases I'll mention is that it was a coalition between the more liberal members of the Court that probably did not have methodological commitments to the originalist analysis, but probably liked the outcome in that it was protective of defendants' rights. And Justice Scalia and Justice Thomas, who didn't have necessarily a predisposition to protect defendants' rights in the abstract, but understood the Confrontation Clause to mean something historically and enforced that. And Crawford itself, as I mentioned, has spawned a whole line of precedent which are kind of interesting if you're an originalist, because Justice Scalia and Justice Thomas have diverged on certain questions about what counts as testimonial and so forth. So it's an interesting line, but that whole line of relatively important criminal procedure precedents has been completely subsumed in an originalist analysis, which is not necessarily true of all other areas. I know you all will talk about the Eighth Amendment, which still is pretty non originalist in that it's about changing mores and so forth.

 

So that's one. I think that's the most prominent example. But there are others. One really watershed originalist Scalia Thomas liberal coalition is Apprendi v. New Jersey. I'm sure many of you are familiar with that. It was a 2000 case that said, essentially, any fact that increases the maximum sentence someone can receive in court must be proved to a jury. And that immediately, not in that case, but in two later cases called Blakely and Booker, essentially meant that the guideline systems that states and the federal government had established for criminal sentencing were unconstitutional. Under those systems, if your statutory range was, say, 0 to 20 years, the systems would say, "Well, if the judge doesn't find some fact like you did it with a gun, actually you can only be sentenced to 10 years. For the judge to sentence you in the upper area of the statutory range, he or she needs to find that you did it with a gun or did it with some other aggravating circumstance." And the Court said that's unconstitutional because those facts are now necessary for your upper range sentence. And if they're necessary, they must be found by a jury.

 

And there's now been a whole line of Apprendi cases feeding off that originalist analysis and saying, "Well, what about criminal forfeiture? What about penalties? What about all these other things?" And then it even extended ultimately to mandatory minimums, which Justice Scalia was not willing to extend it to but Justice Thomas was. But all of that essentially derived from the views of Justice Scalia and Thomas that under the 19th century understanding of what a crime is, every fact that increased the sentence was an element of the crime. And so when you put that into the jury trial, right, every fact that increases the maximum has to be proved to the jury. It was a very originalist analysis, vigorously objected to by the more practical, right leaning members of the Court, like Justice Kennedy, Chief Justice Rehnquist. But again, it was Justices Scalia and Thomas joining with liberals who presumably liked the outcome to enmesh an originalist mode of reasoning into an important area of criminal procedure.

 

I'll just give two others and then quickly say a couple points about the implications of this. The Fourth Amendment. A lot of you probably know a case called Kyllo, which was about whether the police officers need a warrant or whether it's a search, at least, to use a heat seeking device to obtain information about the interior of a home. And Justice Scalia wrote the opinion, joined by liberal members of the Court, and said, "You know, Katz, this 1960's standard about reasonable expectation of privacy, is sort of circular. It's very hard to apply. But in this case, it's easy, because at common law you, at minimum, had a reasonable expectation that the government could not pry into the interior of your home, at least without a warrant. And so just because you have new technology, if you're achieving the same thing that was forbidden at common law, it's forbidden here."

 

The other Fourth Amendment case that's important in this area is Jones from 2012. And in Jones, the question was, "Can the police attach something to your car without a warrant that tracks your movements on public streets?" And in a Warren Court era Katz analysis, there would be a debate about, "Well, you can see people driving on the streets, so why is it an invasion of privacy just to track you on public streets?  You're doing that in public." But what Justice Scalia and Justice Thomas and the liberals again said -- I think it was a broader coalition in Jones, if I'm remembering correctly -- what they said was that, "Forget all that. Putting the thing on the car is a trespass at common law, period. So it doesn't matter -- privacy expectations on the streets. It's a trespass at common law to put it on the car. That's it. That's a search. You need a warrant."

 

And the last area I'll mention, it's pseudo-originalist, is the emergence or reemergence in recent years of the vagueness doctrine for criminal statutes. So I had the misfortune of arguing in the Supreme Court a case called United States v. Johnson, which was about something called the Residual Clause of the Armed Career Criminal Act, which I'll oversimplify, but it enhanced criminal penalties if they could show you committed a prior criminal offense that had a high chance of violence. I can't remember the language now, but it was something super vague. And the Court had struggled with lots of cases about whether certain sorts of prior offenses qualified under this vague language.

 

And the issue in Johnson was whether mere possession of a sawed-off shotgun counted. I argued for the government that it did count. I like to think I was so persuasive, but that outcome seems so crazy that the Court decided to just strike the entire statute down as unconstitutionally vague, which Justice Scalia had been pushing for a long time. And that arises out of traditional originalist notions of due process and fair notice in criminal statutes. So the broader point I want to make is, in all these areas, essentially Justice Scalia and Justice Thomas's views about the correct way to conduct constitutional interpretation, which didn't really have a majority of the Court at the time, made their way into majority opinions because liberal justices who didn't appear to have any commitment to that style of reasoning wanted the vote. I don't want to psychoanalyze them. But they joined votes on methodological grounds they otherwise didn't endorse, presumably because they liked the rule of law coming out of those cases. That, in some sense, at least doctrinally, laid the groundwork for the current, more controversial cases like Dobbs, where the Court has used originalist arguments and reasoning to overrule long settled or 50 year settled precedents.

 

And it now doesn't look so weird that that's happening. I mean, imagine there hadn't been Crawford, there hadn't been Apprendi, there hadn't been these cases. All of a sudden, the Court's overruling precedents based on their view of the original understanding. It looks a lot more anomalous in that situation. Whereas now you can point to Crawford and Apprendi and Jones and Kyllo and all these cases and say, "We're just doing what we always do. When something's clearly wrong on the originalist understanding, we have overruled precedents, and Dobbs is not anomalous in that respect." And so the interesting question for me going forward is do the liberal justices feel like they or their predecessors made a mistake in joining some of those opinions? They could have concurred in the judgment and said, "I don't agree with looking at 19th century sources about the jury trial right or the confrontation but the rule is correct for these other reasons that appeal more to my sensibility." Because now it's defensible to say, "Hey, in Dobbs, we're just doing what we did in Crawford. We're just doing what we did in a lot of these cases." And I wonder if going forward, the liberal justices will be more reluctant to sign on to originalist analysis, even in cases they agree with, for fear of establishing more precedent of that originalism can overrule precedent. So that's my opening spiel, and I guess I'll turn it back over to the Judge.

 

Hon. Amul Thapar:  Michael?

 

Mr. Michael Caruso:  Thank you, Judge. And thank you, John, for inviting me to participate in this panel. There aren't many groups that appreciate the views of public defenders, so I do appreciate The Federalist Society for inviting me here today. I don't think it's an accident, however, that a bright light is shining in my face like my clients would be subjected to. Yes, of course. The reason why police officers shine that light in a suspect's face during interrogation was to get the truth out of them. So I'm going to tell you that's not going to work today. I'm going to try to tell the truth as much as I can.

 

Hon. John F. Bash III:  Have you ever been a member of the Communist Party?

 

Mr. Michael Caruso:  Never. Socialist Party, yes. Not the Communist Party. So I'm going to take -- as a public defender, I'm going to take a more cynical view than my friend John here. So I do agree that those cases did make strange bedfellows. And it is clearly Justices Scalia and Thomas that led those original interpretations with regard to those cases. Whether the liberal justices regret signing on to those opinions, whether they'll be hesitant to sign on in the future, I don't know. It seems like we're in a different Supreme Court world where every case generates a majority opinion, two concurrences, and numerous dissents. So I think there's room for multiple interpretations. And we actually saw that in a case I think a few of us are going to discuss today. Ramos, a case that involved the jury unanimous requirement of the Constitution overruled a case that I think was 1-4, but overruled it also in a fractured opinion, which Justice Alito pointed the irony out in his dissent. But my bottom line, cynical view is that the criminal procedure cases that John talked about and the Dobbs decision really are not related.

 

My view is that Dobbs occurred because the Court got to five. I think there was an agenda, and I don't mean that in a pejorative way. There was a conservative legal and political agenda from the day after Roe was issued to have that decision overruled. And again, that's not pejorative. That's every American's right to try to change the law the way that he or she sees fit. But we had Roe for many, many years, and then we had Casey. Again, a fractured opinion. But of course, Casey predates Crawford and Apprendi and Kyllo and Jones. And now we have Dobbs. And I think for me, sort of the confluence between the Dobbs decision and criminal procedure cases going forward is the Louisiana v. Ramos case that predated Dobbs by a couple of years. And you can -- we have Supreme Court clerks here. What the justices are very good at, I'm going to say the conservative justices more so, is playing the long game. 

 

So after Casey -- because Casey is a case about two different issues, right? Abortion rights and precedent. And in fact -- and I would be interested to hear the judge's view on this or the audience's view and my co panelists as well -- when you reread Casey, there is this very striking language. And I think that's why Roe and Casey were often referred to as super precedent by senators during confirmation hearings and other politicians because -- I don't have the language memorized. But I think the justices in Casey wrote that they were upholding Roe as a promise of constancy and that the overruling of Roe would be, I think, a breach of faith, is what they said.

 

So that's very strong language about precedent. And you could see since Casey, Casey was not widely cited on stare decisis issues. It was cited in a few cases but if you look at the cases that had overruled prior cases in the last few years, and there have been a number of them -- I think Justice Kavanaugh pointed that out in his Dobbs opinion that every sitting member of the Court had voted to overrule a prior precedent -- you do see that Casey went missing from certain opinions. And I think really where we saw the long game really come out -- and it was in Justice Gorsuch's opinion in Ramos, where it seemed to be a fairly simple case. There were only two states in this entire country that allowed non unanimous jury verdicts. I think Justice Gorsuch made it a more complicated case than it had to be. There was a portion of the opinion that argued that the prior precedent wasn't precedent at all.

 

But you could see the groundwork both in Justice Gorsuch's main opinion, where he's going through various factors that would authorize or legitimize the Supreme Court from overruling a prior case. But you also see it in Justice Kavanaugh's concurrence, which I think really laid the groundwork for Dobbs in two critical respects. One is this idea of egregious error that Dobbs uses as a factor. I think Justice Kavanaugh called it a grievous error, but I think it's roughly the same. The other issue that came out in Ramos that is very interesting in light of Dobbs, is this discussion about reliance interest. And that, from a public defender, avowed liberal and progressive, that was the hardest part of Justice Alito's opinion to digest for me.

 

One, the decision that the Court is not to look at intangible reliance interests. And again, in my humble opinion, sort of the short shrifting of the concrete reliance interests. But I do want to focus on the intangible reliance issues, because that's what I find most interesting about putting Ramos and Dobbs together, because Justice Gorsuch, in very, very strong language at the end of his opinion, chides the liberal justices, I think Justice Kagan, for not fully accounting for the interests of the American people in having criminal juries render unanimous verdicts. Now, I have to tell you, I've had about 60 federal jury trials. I've probably watched 100 more. I've seen that many voir dires. I've seen lawyers and judges in nearly every case ask potential jury members about what they think about the rule that a jury has to be unanimous. And I have to tell you, I think their eyes are glazing over, probably like your eyes are glazing over now, listening to me speak.

 

So, to me, although I love Justice Gorsuch's language, it was sort of very simple and very powerful language, it totally runs counter to my experience. But what he was saying was, in the terms of overruling a prior Supreme Court case, that intangible interests do matter, that Americans have this reliance interest in what he called the preservation of our liberties. So you fast forward a few years to Dobbs and Justice Gorsuch, of course, joins the majority opinion. And Justice Alito basically says, "No. Intangible reliance interests don't count at all." The Court -- he cites a number of reasons. And again, and I'm not saying he was being disingenuous, but because I think they are legitimate topics to discuss, I think he got it wrong.

 

One, he said that the Court is not equipped to assess whether Americans or individuals have these intangible reliant interests, even though Justice Gorsuch said only a few years earlier that they did. So that's very interesting to me to compare those opinions on that point. And then what I'm obviously very interested in is what we're looking at going forward in terms of criminal procedure. Because one of the things that does concern me as a public defender and as an American are the rights of criminal procedure that my clients currently possess, most of them given to them by the Warren Court. And there is a part of the opinion that can be read in what Justice Kavanaugh was saying -- and Justice Alito points this out in Ramos -- whether any decision that is not grounded in originalism -- I don't often use that word, as you can probably tell -- I do use outcome -- is egregiously wrong. And so to me that is very concerning, because if you look at the Warren Court's decisions, you do see the argument that some could make that they are functionalist opinions.

 

And I'll give you two examples. One that scares me for both me and my clients. One that scares me. Mapp v. Ohio. That's the case that -- where the Warren Court said that the remedy for police misconduct is the suppression of evidence. I would imagine -- how many originalists are here today? Would any say that that remedy is grounded in the text or history or tradition of the United States? A much smaller show of hands. So I think under the conception of Dobbs, that type of opinion can be viewed as egregiously wrong. So I think that is something I'm concerned about. Now, the other side to that is like the Bruton case that came out last year, Samia, the Supreme Court has essentially already overruled Mapp v. Ohio because suppression law is riddled with so many exceptions. It's not very much of an issue now.

 

But what I am most concerned about for myself, because I do have a mortgage to pay, I have kids to put through college, is what Justices Gorsuch and Thomas have written about that Gideon v. Wainwright was wrongly decided. And of course, that is a classic functionalist opinion. How many would say that the right for state and federal taxpayers to provide lawyers for people accused of crime is found in the text, tradition, or history of the Constitution? Oh, good, you should all be judges and then I'll still have a job. But no, they are on record saying that that case was wrongly decided. And the bottom line is, and I've talked for way too long, and I apologize, but we'll see where this goes. But definitely there are many, many criminal procedure opinions that help my clients that may be put at risk because of Dobbs.

 

Prof. Meghan J. Ryan:  So, like Michael, I want to start with Ramos as sort of a starting point for how and why we might be here. As Michael said, in Ramos, the Court found that under the Sixth Amendment, the criminal jury verdicts have to be unanimous. In doing so, the Court overturned the Apodoca case, where the Court, nearly 50 years earlier, had found that 10-2 and 11-1 verdicts were constitutionally sufficient. So in Apodaca, the Court had applied this cost benefit analysis, this functional approach that Michael was talking about in determining the constitutional requirements, and looked at whether the jury could effectively serve its function with non-unanimous verdicts. The fact that unanimous verdicts were used at the time of the founding was considered not to be important or it was insufficient for constitutionally requiring the unanimous verdicts. And then, in contrast, the Ramos case looked at the practice at the time of the founding, taking a historical approach or some sort of originalist approach to discerning those constitutional requirements under the Sixth Amendment.

 

So, of course, this was a really marked change, moving from that functional approach to the originalist or historical one. And it was significant, too, that the Court, in doing this, overturned again nearly 50 years of precedent in this arena. And as Michael was talking about, in concurrence, Justice Kavanaugh really digs into the requirements or ideas about when stare decisis ought to be followed and when it ought to be put aside. And so we see the Court, I think, in Dobbs, picking up somewhat on that concurrence that Kavanaugh has in the Ramos case. And the Court in Dobbs focused again on the strength of the grounds in which the prior decision was adopted. Of course, there were other factors, but that seemed to be the most significant one in Dobbs.

 

But it seems that the Court, by strength of its grounds, and Michael alluded to this, it seems more like the strength of the mode of constitutional interpretation. And as we all know, the Court has become more conservative in recent years, and many say it's become more originalist in its methodology, although I think there's quite a bit of fuzziness about what type of originalism is being applied, whether it's consistently being applied, whether it truly is originalism. Some say it's a fig leaf for political preferences, et cetera. And as the Court indicated in the Dobbs case, it's ready to, I think, right earlier decisions about constitutional interpretation that were perhaps wrongly decided during the Warren Court, especially where we have a lot of movement in criminal procedure and just in other previous cases. And the Court's really ready, I think, to have major upheaval and precedent, if it's necessary to get there, to these originalist right decisions.

 

Okay. So the Warren Court, which changed a lot of criminal procedure, a lot of those decisions -- most of those decisions were not grounded in originalism or historical or analysis, or at least not only grounded in originalism or historical analysis and took more of a patchwork of methods of constitutional interpretation in reaching those decisions. So this Court's favorable view of originalism or historical analysis of some sort, paired with its willingness that we see in Dobbs to disregard stare decisis, I think, really sets the stage for some significant upheaval in criminal procedure like we're talking about. But perhaps the biggest change, at least in terms of doctrinal change, maybe not necessarily in terms of effects on the ground, but the biggest change in terms of doctrinal change, I think, really is in the context of the Eighth Amendment.

 

Since the 1958 case of Trop v. Dulles, the Court has pretty consistently applied the evolving standards of decency approach in Eighth Amendment cases, trying to assess the evolving standards of decency that mark the progress of a maturing society. So this approach, what we see in the Eighth Amendment, is probably the most antithetical to traditional views of originalism, to a historical approach focusing on practices and morals that are changing over time, rather than on the beliefs and perhaps practices, depending upon what sort of originalism you apply at the time of the founding. So putting this evolving standards of decency approach to the side and replacing it with one focused on practices at the time of the founding, for example, really can make some major changes in Eighth Amendment doctrine.

 

So we might see the Court setting aside prohibitions, for example, on executing juveniles under the Eighth Amendment, or executing intellectually disabled persons, or limits on grossly excessive punishment. We even see Governor DeSantis has recently signed a bill providing for a death penalty in child rape cases, something that, under a 2008 case by the Court, Kennedy v. Louisiana, is unconstitutional. But we see perhaps DeSantis seeing the Court maybe setting aside that precedent. It would also suggest that, at least constitutionally, capital punishment is here to stay, even if a supermajority of jurisdictions find it morally repugnant. The Court has already pretty explicitly said that this is going to be the case for various reasons. Capital punishment is here to stay, at least as a constitutional matter. Focusing on practices at the time of the founding also would suggest that practices such as ear cropping, splitting noses, branding foreheads could potentially, at least constitutionally, be legitimate -- whether states actually put those practices -- things into practice is a different question. So I think in the Eighth Amendment, again, at least doctrinally, we might see some major changes as a result of this confluence of the focus on originalism and the willingness to set aside precedent.

 

Well, perhaps the biggest changes or the biggest implications of the Court's favoritism of originalism or historical approach and movement away from stare decisis is probably in the Eighth Amendment context. Because this evolving standards of decency approach is so antithetical to historical analysis, the effects, I think, throughout criminal procedure could potentially be enormous. So, for example, the Court's decision in Ramos suggests that perhaps in a similar context, there have to be 12 people on juries in criminal matters, something that's long been written off as just a historical accident, just as unanimous verdicts were before Ramos. Justice Gorsuch actually recently talked about this in his dissent in a denial of cert. So I think that might be coming down the pipe, potentially. The limitations that the Court has put on the interpretation of Justice Scalia's Crawford opinion right now, it's sort of been narrowed to some extent. Those could perhaps fade away, and we have a more robust analysis under Crawford, something that we might already be seeing a bit in the works.

 

In my view, some of these outcomes could be positive, some of them could be negative. I think criminal procedure is unique compared to other areas of constitutional law in that you might have, as John alluded to, you might have liberals agreeing with outcomes that are in line with originalist methodology, which I think is pretty rare compared to some other areas of constitutional law. And if we take a historical analysis to things, and if it's consistently done, perhaps an originalist approach could have the result of making criminal procedure, which is really quite fractured in many ways, making it more coherent. But again, I think that's dependent upon a certain type of originalism being applied consistently, which I think is unlikely to happen perhaps. So in that case, we might actually see more fracturing in criminal procedure. Only time will tell, of course, what version of originalism a majority of the Court is going to apply, whether it does it consistently, whether it maintains its moxie in significantly transforming the criminal procedure landscape. I really look forward to some extent with a bit of trepidation as to what the Court is going to do down the line. But I also look forward to hearing what all of your thoughts are on the matter. Thank you.

 

Prof. John Stinneford:  All right. Thanks so much. It's tough going last at the end of the afternoon, so please excuse me if I fall asleep during my own talk. So I'll try to be as brief as I can. My understanding of what we were talking about today is that we're thinking about the ways in which Dobbs, and particularly its treatment of stare decisis, may impact criminal law and criminal procedure going forward. And as I thought about the stare decisis factors in Dobbs, I thought in particular about this notion of grievous error. That if there's a grievous error, we can overturn a precedent. And in thinking about grievous error in Dobbs, Dobbs actually has been criticized as being a non-originalist opinion. I don't know if you've heard this, but if you look at what Dobbs says about Roe and Casey, it says, "Well, there's no text about a right to abortion, and a right to abortion is not deeply rooted in this country's history and tradition." And in determining whether it should be considered deeply rooted, the Court takes the Glucksberg approach, which is to say sort of a concrete approach to history and tradition, and says, "Is there any concrete right to abortion historically?" The answer is "No."

 

Now, folks on the left might say that that's a non-originalist opinion for two reasons. One is, there's no effort to establish that the deeply rooted standard itself is part of the original meaning of the Constitution. And secondly, there's no effort to show that the Glucksberg approach to deep rootedness, that is the concrete approach, is the correct originalist approach to determining unenumerated rights, because there's also the sort of the Casey, Lawrence, Obergefell approach to deeply rooted, which is the abstract approach. Is there an abstract right to liberty and equality, et cetera, in our country's history and tradition? And if there is such an abstract right, then can we identify abortion as being consistent with that abstract right? So we have these -- and in the case law -- and I think this is an extremely important issue for constitutional interpretation. We have both the Glucksberg approach and the Casey, Lawrence, Obergefell approach. None of these cases have been overturned. They're both sort of available as approaches to constitutional interpretation.

 

And what I'm going to argue today, actually, is that the Court, although it didn't attempt to do so, it actually did get the original meaning right in using the Glucksberg approach. And the reason it did so will actually have a deep effect on future precedents in the area of criminal law, criminal procedure in particular. Now, again, this is a complex issue, and I've only got a few minutes. I'll try and go through it quickly, and I can take things sort of in questions if people have them. I want to start, actually with Justice Scalia, who in many ways is a great hero to originalism, but also in some ways made some mistakes that I think that have cost us. And one, and the one that's really at issue here is his idea of what the common law is. Justice Scalia, like many folks in the post realist era, had two sort of diametrically opposed ideas of what the common law is in his head at the same time.

 

One of those ideas was that the common law is judges making policy from the bench as they go, based on their own preferences. The other is that the common law is a set of rules that were established way back in the day and that are unchangeable and that we can refer to as sort of this historical grounding. They're both there in his thought. They're both there in all of our thought, I think, on some level. But actually, I think they're incorrect. They're not a correct understanding of what the common law is. And I really lay the fault here with Oliver Wendell Holmes, who they say he's a great hero of the law. I think he's one of the great villains, truthfully, because he's the one who came up with this idea that the common law is judges making policy, and it should be judges making policy. Prior to Holmes, nobody asserted that judges had a law-making power under the common law. Critics of the common law said that's what judges are really doing.

 

But the common law was never justified on this basis. Rather, it was justified on the basis of custom and long usage. That is, the common law was a kind of customary law, and judges would identify customs that had been established through time immemorial, long-standing customs, and then apply those customs to new situations. And a custom could only count as law if it was universally received throughout the jurisdiction for a very, very long period of time. Now, why is this important? Well, it's important for a couple of reasons. Number one, most of the rights we're talking about when we talk about criminal procedure rights under the Fourth Amendment, Fifth Amendment, Sixth Amendment, Eighth Amendment, were originally common law rights. They existed at common law. They were then enumerated in the Bill of Rights.

 

And so when we think about what those rights are and what they mean and how they apply, it's important that we understand what the common law is and how those rights came to develop, because they are common law rights. Also, a second -- and this relates to unenumerated rights. Let me back up for a second. Common law thinkers. One of the questions that they often faced was, how could the common law be law when Parliament has never said thou shalt or thou shalt not, the king, the president, Congress, no one has said thou shalt or thou shalt not. It's just judges deciding cases. How can that be law?

 

And the answer to that was that the customs of a free people are more reliable in determining what's just and fair and reasonable than the judgment of any one moment in time or any one branch of government. So we look to long standing customs. If something has been universally received throughout the generations, then this is powerful evidence that it's reasonable, which is to say it comports with principles of reason or natural justice, and that it enjoys the consent of the people, because if it didn't have those two qualities, it would fall out of usage. Unlike a statute, there's nothing holding it in place except for continued usage. Why is that important? That idea, I mean, ultimately, common law thinkers came to the conclusion that the common law was better than positive law at comporting with natural principles of justice, that when you had a new statute, it was more likely to be unreasonable or unjust than the common law rule that it replaced. And this is why we have rules of interpretation, like statutes, and derogation of the common law shall be narrowly construed, because the notion was the legislature was likely to mess it up relative to the common law.

 

Now this gave rise to the idea of rights enforceable against the sovereign, because in England, and then especially in America at the time of the revolution, there was this idea that there's some rights established at common law that are so fundamental that even the king and Parliament can't change them. The right to a jury trial, the right not to be taxed without representation in Parliament, et cetera. These were not established by positive law. They were common law rights, but they enjoyed long usage. They were considered fundamental to existence as a free people. So fundamental that even these, the government can't do anything about. All right. And then ultimately, of course, we encode them in the Bill of Rights, because we want to make sure that the Congress won't do what Parliament did and try to deny that they're actually fundamental. This, I think, helps us think about unenumerated rights. If there are unenumerated rights, and I'm not sure there are, but if there are unenumerated rights, how do we identify them?

 

Well, the common law would say you identify them by looking to see whether they've been established through long usage. Have they been universally recognized throughout the jurisdiction for a very long period of time? That is to say, the Glucksberg approach. I think without even knowing it, the Glucksberg approach actually is the correct approach for identifying fundamental rights, unenumerated rights, that is, if they do exist. Also, it's the correct way of thinking through the meaning and scope of enumerated rights. We look at how the rights developed at common law, and by the way, we say developed, but in fact, the tradition's not a dead tradition. Edward Cook, the greatest common law thinker, wrote, "Custom loses its being if usage fails," right? So if something was thought to be just and reasonable, but then fell out of usage for a very long period of time, then that's powerful evidence that it's actually not just and reasonable, because it did not withstand the test of time.

 

So, for example, slitting nostrils and cutting off ears fell out of usage centuries ago. If we tried to bring them back, they're no longer part of the tradition. And by the way, the words cruel and unusual, the word unusual means, contrary to long usage, unjustly harsh in light of long-standing prior practice. So this is our method of determining whether a given practice comports with fundamental rights that came through the common law is to determine whether they meet with our historical practices. Now, in the Eighth Amendment context, this is where I've spent most of my career is writing and thinking about the Eighth Amendment.

 

I think that there are lots of things one might say about the possible consequences. I'm not going to go into them in detail. I'll just give a little list. People can answer -- ask me questions if they want. Yes, the death penalty itself is probably safe, but instances of the death penalty that fell out of usage centuries ago, like, for example, the first Congress authorized the death penalty for counterfeiting. Probably not okay, right, because it hasn't been done for two centuries. Lethal injection, I think probably not okay because the three-drug protocol involves a risk of severe suffering prior to death that's much greater than traditional methods like hanging. Long term solitary confinement, probably not okay because, again, it imposes extreme suffering in comparison to imprisonment.

 

So there's a mixed bag in terms of the outcomes if you were to do original meaning, although I would argue that overall, the Eighth Amendment becomes much more protective of criminal offenders under the original meaning than it does under the evolving standards of decency test. And I won't go into any more detail.  Just to list a few things. Obviously, the Fourth Amendment, we've seen a move in this direction, as well. There was a mention of the Kyllo case, but also, Carpenter v. U. S., Riley v. California. These are cases where the Court is struggling to think about technology in the context of searches and seizures, but also in terms of the language of the Constitution, persons, houses, papers, and effects. How do we think of technological surveillance in those terms? And I think the way the Court is doing it is potentially very productive and very protective of criminal rights. Fifth Amendment.

 

I just got to give a shout out to Miranda and Dickerson. Dickerson might be the most unjustifiable decision that's still surviving, I think, in the Court. It's hard to see how Miranda continues to survive going forward, except that, in effect, it's now kind of a pro law enforcement decision, because as long as you follow Miranda, no one's going to win on a claim that you've coerced an interrogation out of somebody. So law enforcement no longer has any interest in getting it overturned. Talked about the Eighth Amendment.

 

A couple of other things. The right to habeas corpus. I mean, one open question, and I don't know the answer to this, is the AEDPA too narrow in light of the historical meaning of the right to habeas corpus? Has it made it unavailable in ways that it would have been available at common law? And if so, is that constitutional? And one final point for criminal law, and I want to, especially for the judges in the room, think about reviving the rule of strict construction of penal statutes. This was a rule that survived in this country until the middle of the 20th century, when Justice Frankfurter replaced it with the rule of lenity. The rule of lenity is a weak, sickly cousin, barely related to the rule of strict construction of penal statutes. The basis of the rule of strict construction is that when you have a new penal statute that's significantly harsher than what the common law would permit, then we have to be very skeptical about it, and we're going to read it as narrowly as we reasonably can. That rule is no longer in effect. The rule of lenity is like a piece of shrapnel floating in the atmosphere. Sometimes it lands somewhere, but it doesn't do much. So, judges, read the first edition of Sutherland's on statutory construction. Don't read today's. It's mishmash. And you will do much to protect criminal defendants. Thanks so much.

 

Hon. Amul Thapar:  Okay.  So we don't have a ton of time because I have to have you -- everyone out of here by 5:00 sharp, and I'd ask that you immediately -- I know you want to talk to your neighbor afterwards or talk to the panelists. I ask that you do it in the hall because the FedSoc folks have to shut this down because the Scalia dinner is tonight. Reminder, there's buses, and they start at 5:15 and end at 6:30. And so now I'm going to turn it to the panelists, but because we went over, I'm going to -- yes, that's a shot at the four of you FYI -- I am going to limit your time and cut you off. You each get two minutes because I want to make sure that the audience can ask questions. So, Attorney Bash -- or Mr. Esquire do you want to say anything? You get two minutes.

 

Hon. John F. Bash III:  I'll just ask John a question so that he can use the time. The originalist, true originalist, Eighth Amendment. I guess I've been under the assumption that the original meaning of the Eighth Amendment related only to methods of punishment, not to the things that it's been expanded to. But you mentioned counterfeiting, not being able to have that death penalty for counterfeiting, which is not a method of punishment issue, but a fit between the crime and the punishment. Does your research show that at common law, that would have been understood to be encompassed by that concept?

 

Prof. John Stinneford:  Yeah. So, first of all, let me say, if you're interested in this particular topic or if you have trouble sleeping, I wrote an article called "Rethinking Proportionality Under the Cruel and Unusual Punishments Clause." It's in the Virginia Law Review, and it lays out my thesis in detail. I'll give you one quick kind of fun story to highlight this. So the phrase "cruel and unusual punishments," first showed up in the English Bill of Rights in the 17th century, and we know very well what it means because of a fellow named Titus Oates.

 

Now, Titus Oates was this disreputable Anglican clergyman who had trouble with the law. He'd fallen out of favor. He had no job, and he was sort of like a 17th century Kardashian. He really wanted fame and fortune, and he thought, what will get me fame and fortune? Well, everyone hates Catholics, and everyone's worried that the Spanish armada is going to come sailing up the Thames any day now. So if I make up a story that there's a Popish plot to kill the king, then everyone will love me, right? And so he does. He tells this story to a magistrate. He names 15 people, including the Queen's physician, as conspirators. He gives this evidence to a magistrate. The magistrate then turns up dead in the streets of London, right? So now it's panic at the disco, and they have these trials, and there's a series of trials of conspirators, and it's like trial, conviction, execution, trial, conviction, execution.

 

Finally, at, like, the 15th trial, it comes out that the whole story was made up. And there was this key meeting of the conspirators that had supposedly happened in England. And it was proven that Oates was actually in France, enjoying some wine and cheese on the day of the supposed meeting of the conspirators. And so now everyone was like, what do we do with Oates? Because we've just killed all these innocent people because of him. He's sort of like a serial killer, morally speaking. But the only crime that he committed was perjury, which was not a felony, and therefore, you couldn't take his life for perjury. And so they gave him, Chief Justice Jeffreys, the famous hanging judge, said, we have something special prepared for you. And then another justice sort of gave the punishment, which was a big fine. He was going to be whipped while being dragged from Aldgate to Newgate. So, across the City of London. Then two days later, dragged from Newgate to Tyburn, while being whipped again, imprisoned for life. He was defrocked and put in a pillory four times a year for life. So this was his punishment.

 

Five years later, new king, English Bill of Rights is now in place, and he shows up in Parliament and says, hey, what was done to me was cruel and unusual. Can you please lift the judgment? And if you read the parliamentary debates, they make it very clear that they agree that it was cruel and unusual. In fact, the House of Commons delegates say they were thinking of Oates, specifically when they wrote the cruel and unusual punishments clause. The House of Lords, though, wouldn't lift the judgment because he was such a bad guy. They say, so ill a man shouldn't get the benefit. And so --

 

Hon. Amul Thapar:  This is it. One sentence.

 

Prof. John Stinneford:  It's only cruel and unusual, because it's disproportionate to the crime of perjury.

 

Hon. Amul Thapar:  Good. You kept it to one. Okay. Mr. Caruso, you get two minutes.

 

Mr. Michael Caruso:  I'll ask John a question as well because I'm hoping you're going to try to dampen some of my pessimism about this subject. So I'm very interested in this custom and usage true originalism doctrine, because when I look at Gideon, when I look at Miranda, and when I look at Mapp, those are very old cases. So in talking about custom and usage, what counts? The last 65 years or the preceding 150 years? And now that -- I would say that all three of those cases have been accepted and embraced by the American people. So how does that fit into that doctrine?

 

Prof. John Stinneford:  Well, I would say, initially, a judge can't create a custom. And so when a judge issues an opinion, especially a justice of the Supreme Court, that incorrectly interprets the Constitution and then freezes that situation in place, the mere fact that it remains frozen in place over a period of time shouldn't count. Because the notion is, it's the customs of the people. The customs arising from the people that remain in place only because we choose to continue using them as a --

 

Hon. John F. Bash III:  How does that work in normal common law stuff? I mean, like, consequential damages are not available for breach of contract. How could the custom of the people, apart from judicial decisions, develop that principle?

 

Prof John Stinneford:  Well, yeah, right. So the thing about the way the common law thinkers think about this custom is that it is judges who are identifying the custom and applying the custom, and they're not ever trying to find some moment in time when the people, absent the judiciary, had a custom, and then the judges adopted it. So it is that judges have used this from time immemorial. We can't find a time when they haven't used it. It's continued in usage. But the key thing here is that there are many opportunities for it to stop being used. And so any given custom -- I shouldn't say any given, but many customs could stop being used because a judge refuses to apply the rule anymore, because a prosecutor ceases to apply the rule, because a jury won't convict in a certain situation or won't apply a certain penalty when that's in their power. It's not the Supreme Court with a single top-down approach that can never be displaced.

 

Mr. Michael Caruso:  Can I reclaim some of my time because John stole it?

 

Hon. Amul Thapar:  I think the professor used it when you gave it. But, yes, you can have a minute but no response.

 

Mr. Michael Caruso:  Okay. So this is all very interesting to me because this is used in customs. Because in the Ramos case that we were talking about earlier, the Sixth Amendment says an impartial jury. Many of these constitutional norms are not self-executing. They're very vague language. But yet Justice Gorsuch was able to tease out that that impartiality provision also encompassed unanimity. So I'm wondering how all that plays in. But you're not allowed to answer, so I'll just think about this for myself.

 

Hon. Amul Thapar:  No, you can answer. You get one minute, though, and I'm serious.

 

Prof. John Stinneford:  The answer is I don't know.

 

Hon. Amul Thapar:  Okay. That's good. You stayed within the minute. All right. Professor Ryan, so I'm going to ask you a question instead of you letting Professor Stinneford ask a question, which is, I saw you as he was talking, thinking, now, this sounds like an originalism I can endorse. Could you or no? And if not, why not?

 

Prof. Meghan J. Ryan:  Yes, to some extent, I'm sympathetic towards John Stinneford's view of original interpretation of the Eighth Amendment. My concern is that I don't think it's the same type of originalism that the current Supreme Court is applying. And I think, as I said, time will tell, I think, exactly what the Supreme Court is going to do in terms of their originalism, but it seems like a more draconian version to me and not as evolving as John's version.

 

Hon. Amul Thapar:  Okay. Do you want to say anything else?  Because you are well within your time.

 

Prof. Meghan J. Ryan:  That's all.

 

Hon. Amul Thapar:  All right. Questions from the audience. Go to the mics. They're behind you.
Yes, sir.

 

Kai Albert:  Kai Albert from Washington State. I saw the Miranda and Mapp cases mentioned, and I think you can probably put Escobedo in the same category. I'd like you to look into your crystal balls. Do you think the supreme -- is there any likelihood of the Supreme Court actually going there and looking at if those cases were grievously wrong and possibly overruling any of them, or will it just be left at academia saying, "Well, in theory, this case could be under attack if you follow the line of Dobbs."

 

Hon. John F. Bash III:  I do not think those cases are going to be reconsidered. I mean, as somebody said, Mapp has just been carved away through other means, so there's no point in using essentially stare decisis capital on overruling the exclusionary rule. And what's the other one you said? Miranda, for the reason said, law enforcement likes Miranda now. You say something that someone who's very stressed and has been arrested is barely listening to and just sounds like something they heard on TV, and then it immunizes a whole range of conduct. So I just don't think there's any movement to overrule those at all.

 

Hon. Amul Thapar:  Yeah. And in Dickerson, I'll say the law enforcement weighed in on the side of Miranda because they liked certainty.

 

Mr. Michael Caruso:  Right. The police have incorporated that into their practice. 99 percent of all people who are questioned waive their Miranda rights. I would just briefly say Gideon does cause me concern, because when you look at, like, a state of Georgia, which has a horrifically inefficient state public defender system that drains their state taxpayer resources, I do wonder if there will be an enterprising state solicitor general who does bring that issue before the Court.

 

Hon. John F. Bash III:  Just a gut reaction, but I just do not think Justice Kavanaugh, who's at least for now, his vote, or Chief Justice Roberts's vote, would be required for overruling anything. I don't see them overruling Gideon v. Wainwright.

 

Mr. Michael Caruso:  Thank you.

 

Hon. John F. Bash III:  I don't know. I've never talked about that but I just don't see that happening.

 

Hon. Amul Thapar:  Over here.

 

Mike Isaac:  Thank you. My name is Mike Isaac. I'm from Tampa, Florida. And like Mr. Caruso, I may be the only criminal defense attorney in the room, but I'm actually an originalist and a textualist.

 

Hon. John F. Bash III:  I defend criminals.

 

Mike Isaac:  Oh, okay.

 

Hon. John F. Bash III:  Just people who pay for it. But I --

 

Hon. Amul Thapar:  John just wants big money work.

 

Mr. Michael Caruso:  He does it the right way.

 

Hon. Amul Thapar:  Mike does it because he has his heart in it, and John does it for the money. No, I'm kidding.

 

Hon. John F. Bash III:  That's exactly right. Oh, no apologies necessary.

 

Mike Isaac:  So I'm not sure that I share your concern about the future of where the decisions are going in light of Dobbs. How do you reconcile that concern with, for example, Justice Alito's concurrence in Caniglia v. Strom? Of course, I'm talking about the community caretaking doctrine that came from Cady v. Dombrowski in 1973. So that's 50 years of precedent. And yet in the concurrence, Justice Alito makes it very clear that this was a passing statement in the case. It was never intended to be used as a freestanding exception to the Fourth Amendment. And for those criminal defense attorneys in the room, we know that prosecutors like to use community caretaking in circumstances where police don't have a warrant, they don't have reasonable suspicion. So it seems to me that the originalistic point of view that Justice Alito gave was quite helpful to the criminal defense bar.

 

Mr. Michael Caruso:  Yeah. I mean, I'm not quite sure that Justice Alito has ever on purpose been helpful to the criminal defense bar. I mean, I think he did write Flores-Figueroa. So that was one helpful case. But I don't know. But ultimately, I agree with John in that there are only, I think, two justices, maybe three, who are really looking to undo past cases. Those are Justices Alito and Thomas, and to a certain extent, Judge Gorsuch, depending on the issue. He's a self-proclaimed libertarian. So you never know what a libertarian is going to do. He wrote McGirt, which created -- as criminal defense lawyers, I have to tell you, I embrace chaos because it's really the only one advantage I have in the courtroom. And McGirt was clearly -- has wreaked chaos across --

 

Hon. John F. Bash III:  It's an Oklahoma case and a lot of Oklahoma is a reservation so many of the federal convictions or state convictions -- state convictions were out.

 

Mr. Michael Caruso:  But I don't know. I'm not going to sleep well at night thinking that Justice Alito is going to help my clients down the line.

 

Hon. John F. Bash III:  The most characteristic Justice Thomas thing ever is he had one opinion where he said, "It's high time this Court reconsider Calder v. Bull," 1798.

 

Mr. Michael Caruso:  That's going back.

 

Devin Watkins:  Hi, Devin Watkins. William Penn, in kind of colonial America, thought that bail rights were required under Magna Carta for anyone that was not a capital offense, where the proof was clear. So I'm wondering, do you think there's a possibility of a revival of more stringent requirements for bail, for preventing any kind of bail for non-capital crimes or bail that's beyond what someone can reasonably give to get pretrial release?

 

Prof. Meghan J. Ryan:  Since the constitutional law is not terribly robust in the area of bail, I do think that's an area that's ripe for some building upon and perhaps not so much limits -- I guess I wouldn't expect so much limits on bail as I would making it -- I would expect it to become a little more of an important right, I guess, under this current Court.

 

Mr. Michael Caruso:  Yeah. I would hope that to be true. Talking about custom and usage, if you look at the cases from district to district, the decisions of magistrate judges mostly, some district court judges, regarding bail, really are not tethered to the Bail Reform Act at all, which is the leading statute on the case. And it is really based on what the tradition is in your district about who gets bail or not. So I think that I agree that is sort of ripe area.

 

Hon. John F. Bash III:  I just can't remember, has the Bail Clause been incorporated?  That I don't know.

 

Prof. John Stinneford:  I think so.

 

Hon. John F. Bash III:  It has. Okay. So it could come up that way, maybe.

 

Nathaniel Lawson:  Hi, I'm Nathaniel Lawson. Work at Cato currently. This is not to any one of you in particular, but what do you think about bringing back some level of jury nullification? I know it pretty much entirely went away very early in the 19th century, but it was pretty huge and pretty important and influential in the 1700's. Some pretty key cases, including truth being defensed, libel and stuff like that, which isn't exactly criminal law. But my point -- but were very influential in America in particular, not just England. And they were jury not listening to the legal advice of the legal doctrine said by the judge of the case --

 

Hon. John F. Bash III:  What does bringing it back look like? I mean, the jury can do that now. Now the defense counsel probably would not be permitted to argue to the jury that you should nullify, is that what you mean? Because the jury right now could say, screw this. We're --

 

Nathaniel Lawson:  Yeah. I'm pretty sure that that was the exact argument in that libel case was that the law is against me, but you should nullify it because it's unjust, against natural law of reason and justice.

 

Mr. Michael Caruso:  Right. John's right. I mean, juries do nullify, but defense lawyers are prohibited from arguing that. One issue that has been litigated through the federal courts is whether defense lawyers or the judge could let the jury know what punishment the defendant is facing. I know District Court Judge Weinstein had written a very lengthy order on that that I don't think has been adopted by any other court. So I think to me, that's an interesting issue, because if you talk to jurors after trial, after they've been convicted, and let them know what the client is facing, you often see some amount of remorse.

 

Hon. Amul Thapar:  Michael, would you be in favor of lawyers being able to argue for nullification?

 

Mr. Michael Caruso:  I would. One, my resume would look a lot better if I could make that argument.

 

Hon. Amul Thapar:  Can I ask another question? Do you worry that if you argue for nullification, in some sense, you admit the guilt? And so there would be cases that are tough for a prosecutor to prove that you might lose as a result.

 

Mr. Michael Caruso:  So I think that's why public defenders and private criminal defense lawyers should be trained. We often do -- you probably see these in court opinions -- argue in the alternative. Sometimes you can't do it directly for fear of confusing the jury about the theory of your case. But I've argued in the alternative, trying to sow the seeds of what a jury may say back in the deliberation room. Because I do subscribe to the theory that in closing argument, what a lawyer should do is arm the jurors who are most likely to vote not guilty with the ammunition they need to convince other juries -- other jurors. So I think the more that's available to a criminal defense lawyer to do that, the better. Whether that's grounded in the text history and constitution of our country is another issue. But I would.

 

Hon. John F. Bash III:  In this hypothetical world, can the prosecutor say what he did is not a crime, but it should be. Maybe I'll go for that.

 

Mr. Michael Caruso:  Or the flip side of that is Rule 404(b), which is the love of prosecutors and the bane of criminal defense lawyers. Would prosecutors be like, oh, let me tell you about all this stuff that he was convicted about in other cases.

 

Hon. Amul Thapar: Over here.

 

Prof. Lawson:  Yeah. Lawson the elder, Boston University School of Law. Professor Stinneford mentioned revival of the rule of strict constructions. I wonder what the panel thinks about this. It's a constitutional rule that all facts in criminal cases have to be proved by the prosecution beyond a reasonable doubt. Why isn't it a constitutional rule that the prosecution has to prove beyond a reasonable doubt that the law means what the prosecution says it means? 

 

Hon. Amul Thapar:  And just for those of you really interested in this, the good professor has written a book on it, as well as a great law review.

 

Hon. John F. Bash III:  Well, I'm just pulling up my Sixth Amendment. Sorry. Let's see.

 

Hon. Amul Thapar:  Do you want to go ahead, Professor Stinneford, while he's looking?

 

Prof. John Stinneford:  Yeah. I mean, I don't know the answer to that, though I look forward to reading your book. I will say it does seem to relate to that earlier question about the powers of the jury. Because I think my limited understanding was that the jury had power over both law and fact. The jury could decide in some ultimate sense what the law was in a way that it can't now. And I don't know the details of that or how it changed, but I think that's something that is worth thinking about, whether there's some constitutional aspect to that.

 

Hon. Amul Thapar:  So I'm going to speak for the professor because I've read his stuff and I think it's brilliant. For those of you out there and ask this, and, professor, if I'm wrong, you can correct me. But I think what he's thinking is we often, when we interpret laws, meaning judges interpret them by kind of a preponderance of the evidence standard. If you look at a lot of cases, the carrying a firearm, all that, the use of a firearm, we're trying to figure it out. And what he's saying is, why isn't the burden on the government? It kind of gets to your strict construction point, but it's rooted in a way that judges are good of thinking of burdens. Strict construction is harder for us.

 

Justice Scalia always said reasonable construction is a better term than strict. And as you know, Justice Barrett said, the rule of lenity is a substantive canon, which we should revisit whether we apply substantive canon. So I guess my point and I think the professors is, why not use the similar rules of evidence to interpret laws, when that is more, as Professor Lawson has argued, baked into the Constitution and kind of the role of a judge.

 

Hon. John F. Bash III:  But would it be the jury or the judge under that view?

 

Hon. Amul Thapar:  The judge.

 

Hon. John F. Bash III:  The judge would still do it. Interesting. Well, I mean, the judges do use clear and convincing for legal things sometimes, and I guess you could do that invalidity of a patent and stuff like that.

 

Hon. Amul Thapar:  Right. But what he's saying is, use the same standard. It's reasonable beyond a reasonable doubt. So it would, in effect, be strict construction, because the burden is on the government to prove that the law encompasses this conduct.

 

Prof. John Stinneford:  Yeah. I think that's right. I think the key -- I mean, whatever terminology you use, the key is for judges to understand the reason behind the rule. So if you look at, again, early sort of judicial manuals, they would say things like, "Why do we do strict construction?" Because the law loves life and the law loves liberty, and the law hates punishment. And therefore, it's the duty of the judge to construe this as narrowly as the judge reasonably can. Not unnaturally reasonably, but as narrowly as they can because there's a substantive preference against punishment. So, again, whether you phrase that in terms of burden of proof or strict construction, I think the core is that the judge knows why they're doing it. And if they know why they're doing it, I think we'll get good results.

 

Hon. Amul Thapar:  So I'll talk on my own law review in the Yale Law Journal, which talks about that in relation to federal laws, when you're interpreting them against someone, you have an obligation to apply a deference to liberty. And that's the point you're making. And I trace it back to the founding and the judicial power itself. Over here.

 

Unidentified Speaker:  My name is not Lawson, and I did not write a book about my question. I did write a law review about it, though. So one of the things I say there, but more importantly, that Gorsuch and Scalia have said, is that non-retroactivity fits very uncomfortably with originalism's fixation thesis. And Justice Gorsuch in his Edwards concurrence says, that's okay. It's kind of an equilibrium adjustment. But my question is, is it an equilibrium adjustment that makes any sense in light of the supposed problem of overusing habeas to then undermine the originalist project with opinions like Batching that say, actually a rule being originalist means it's new, not means it's old.

 

Hon. John F. Bash III:  I don't think I understand the question.

 

Unidentified Speaker:  I guess what I'm getting at is, Professor Bode has written about qualified immunity, that Scalia is wrong about it because it's an equilibrium adjustment to compensate for Monroe v. Pape, but it's one that's poorly tailored. Is Teague and Edwards the same sort of poorly tailored equilibrium adjustment?

 

Hon. John F. Bash III:  I mean, was Teague an interpretation of the constitutional habeas right or some statutory habeas?

 

Unidentified Speaker:  At the time, it was neither. But in Danforth, they classified it as an interpretation of 2243.

 

Hon. John F. Bash III:  Yeah. So, yeah. I guess I don't know if it's a proper originalist interpretation of 2243.

 

Unidentified Speaker:  But it adopts an interpretation of Supreme Court opinions as creating new law, is my point.

 

Hon. John F. Bash III:  I see what you're saying.

 

Unidentified Speaker:  And what Scalia's point and Gorsuch's point.

 

Hon. John F. Bash III:  Sounds like a professor question.

 

Mr. Michael Caruso:  Yeah. I agree. This does not sound like a PD question.

 

Prof. Meghan J. Ryan:  This is not an answer to that question exactly, but I think the more you move away from the foundations of whatever your view of originalism are, the less legitimacy it has. And I think, as I suggested before, if the Supreme Court is adjusting things to account for other things and not just applying originalism and its view of what originalism actually is or how it ought to be applied, then it loses some of its credibility and you end up with more fractured criminal procedure.

 

Hon. Amul Thapar:  Sir.

 

Jacob Smith:  My name is Jacob Smith. My question is, do any of the panelists have opinions on whether harmless error and plain error are consistent with the original meaning of the Constitution? 

 

Hon. John F. Bash III:  Don't the Federal rules require --

 

Hon. Amul Thapar:  Yes.

 

Hon. John F. Bash III:  -- harmless error and plain error?  So it doesn't matter. I mean, Congress can establish rules.

 

Hon. Amul Thapar:  I guess they can't -- what he's saying is they can't establish rules inconsistent with the meaning of the Constitution, and so could they be unconstitutional?

 

Hon. John F. Bash III:  I see. That your conviction must be vacated if some error --

 

Hon. Amul Thapar:  So I'll add to his -- I'm sorry, I'm going to add to your question, is Neder wrongly decided?

 

Hon. John F. Bash III:  Is Neder harmless error if you omit an element of the offense?

 

Hon. Amul Thapar:  Yes.

 

Mr. Michael Caruso:  The jury instruction case.

 

Hon. John F. Bash III:  Well, I say yes on that because Scalia did unless I'm remembering --

 

Hon. Amul Thapar:  Yeah. Scalia's opinion is great in that, but -- okay. Any thoughts?

 

Prof. John Stinneford:  None in particular. I mean, I do think that I've never seen an issue with either rule from a constitutional point of view, but I have to admit I've not thought about it deeply either.

 

Prof. Meghan J. Ryan:  I don't know enough about the history, I guess, to know at the time of the founding what all the thoughts were about those --

 

Hon. Amul Thapar:  Well, let me rephrase it. Can a judge -- okay, so jury is not properly instructed on the elements and you have a right to a jury trial. So one of the elements is not proven to the jury. Should a judge on review be able to say, "Well, the evidence is in the record, so it's harmless beyond a reasonable doubt," because that is Neder.

 

Hon. John F. Bash III:  Yeah. I mean, it does seem like there may be a difference between constitutional errors on constitutional requirements and other sorts of error, like the admission of evidence in violation of the federal rules of evidence. And since Congress could presumably not even have the federal rules of evidence and have some totally different system, it can also kind of say, "Well, if you make an error and it turns out not to be prejudicial under the harmless error rule, it's okay." Neder is different because you have a constitutional right to have the jury decide each of these elements. So it's a little weird to say the judge can just dispense with it.

 

Mr. Michael Caruso:  Yeah. I mean, we have common ground on that. It does boggle my mind that if a person is charged with committing a crime that has four elements and the judge neglects to advise on element three, even if there was evidence in the record, how we can say that that defendant got a fair and impartial trial by jury is beyond me.

 

Hon. John F. Bash III:  Some of those doctrines, though, I think especially retroactivity doctrines on habeas -- I'm not the first person to say this, but they helped the liberal program because they weren't going to get the votes to expand rights if that meant, like, 20,000 people in prison were all going to be able to take advantage of this and get out of prison, like, the moderate justices were not going to vote for that.

 

Mr. Michael Caruso:  Like Johnson.

 

Hon. John F. Bash III:  Johnson. Yeah. Exactly. No, but obviously, if it means that it's only going forward, that's a lot more palatable to people and so forth.

 

Mr. Michael Caruso:  Right. The parade of horribles.

 

Hon. Amul Thapar:  Any final comments?

 

Prof. John Stinneford:  Well, just on the instruction on the elements issue, the interesting question for me is that, or the interesting confounding factor is that the nature of criminal elements has changed since the founding. So the whole elemental approach to criminal law really was the invention of the model penal code, by and large, in the 1950s. And so before that, I mean, crimes were all malum in se, and you would have standards like, did he wickedly and maliciously do X. And so you weren't going to have -- I would think again, my gut instinct is that at the founding era, you wouldn't have a legalistic appeal, because no one's going to forget to say, was he wicked and malicious in murdering his mother-in-law or whatever. Whereas the model penal code says, "No, you have these five elements. You got to extract each five elements." We also have a lot of malum prohibitum crimes now that we didn't back then, where maybe the elements are more important because there's no way the person's going to know that what they're doing is wrongful, whereas back at the founding era they would have known because all the crimes were also sins, essentially. So anyway, I think it's a very interesting question on that level. It would involve a lot of thinking.

 

Hon. Amul Thapar:  Any other final statements?

 

Hon. John F. Bash III:  I'll say one thing, which is that, to me, I'm a big fan of the current Court. I think it's doing a fantastic job, and it's exactly the Court I want to see. But I think that one danger when we're talking about precedent is a virtue of originalism, has been that it's objective, or at least purports to be objective. And it's not the judge's policy preferences -- debates about how much that's actually happening, but that's the supposed virtue. But if they don't have a really systemic, objective way of deciding which precedents they'll reconsider on originalist grounds and which they won't, that can easily bring in through the back door all the political bias and policy preferences that supposedly originalism gets rid of. And I don't know that the recent cases overruling precedents have given a super objective account of which precedents should be discarded and which ones, while wrong, are sufficient to keep. So I think that's a danger for the current Court.

 

Prof. John Stinneford:  I noticed that. I mean, just in going through, because I was thinking about stare decisis, looking at Dobbs and Ramos and Casey. When it comes to stare decisis, the Court is almost as lawless as it is when it comes to standing.

 

Hon. John F. Bash III:  Nothing's worse than standing. Sorry, Judge. They make it up. It's all made up.

 

Prof. John Stinneford:  Yeah. It just expands and contracts and sort of -- yeah, I completely agree with you.

 

Mr. Michael Caruso:  I agree as well. It's actually, like, because I practice in the district court and the appellate courts, I don't ask those judges to overrule cases because they don't have that power. But in reading these cases, it does also boggle my mind that 250 years later, we're still not on the same page as to why we would overrule a precedent. And this whole thing about not only should something be settled, but settled right is very malleable. So it's just very interesting in a person who just wants a stable and orderly society in which to live. Anyway --

 

Hon. Amul Thapar:  Well, I want to thank, and I hope you will, our amazing panel. I also want to thank you all for actually asking questions. I've been in too many of these where people make speeches. And I would ask just one final instruction that I mentioned before, please immediately leave the room and then you can talk to the panel amongst yourselves. Thank you.

 

     

 

 

3:30 p.m. - 5:00 p.m.
The Judiciary's Federalist Revival

2023 National Lawyers Convention

Topics: Litigation • Federal Courts • Federalism
Grand Ballroom
The Mayflower Hotel
1127 Connecticut Avenue NW
Washington, DC 20006

Share

Event Video

Listen & Download

Description

In recent years, the U.S. Supreme Court has emphasized the federalist nature of our national Constitution and the importance of preserving state sovereignty. This trend is evident in several of the Court's decisions – Dobbs most notable among them – that have recognized and reinforced the authority of individual states in matters of health, safety, and morals. As a result of this return to federalism, some of the nation’s most interesting and groundbreaking legal work is being done at the state level. In particular, state constitutional and statutory provisions that used to be subsumed by federal law or judicial precedent – restrictions on abortion, requirements for post-conviction review, grants for religious schooling, and so on – now matter in their own right. On this panel, several state supreme court justices will discuss what the ascendance of federalism means for their states and state courts, as well as how this shift will impact the teaching and practice of law across the nation.

Featuring:

  • Hon. Rebecca Bradley, Wisconsin Supreme Court
  • Hon. David N. Wecht, Pennsylvania Supreme Court
  • Hon. Evan A. Young, Supreme Court of Texas
  • Moderator: Hon. Carlos T. Bea, United States Court of Appeals, Ninth Circuit

Speakers

Event Transcript

Jesse Panuccio:  Okay. Good afternoon, everybody. If you could just find your seats, we're going to get started here in just a few seconds. All right. Well, thank you all for being here, and again, good afternoon. My name is Jesse Panuccio. I'm a member of the Litigation Practice Group Executive Committee. Pleased to welcome you to this breakout panel entitled "The Judiciary's Federalist Revival."

 

      My job in kicking off this panel is just to make a few brief, mostly logistical remarks. First, this panel is coordinated by The Federalist Society's Litigation Practice Group. The Society's Practice Groups, the executive leadership, and those that staff that within The Federalist Society are chiefly responsible for all the breakout sessions during this great conference.

 

      The Practice Groups also coordinate other excellent programming throughout the year, including The Federalist Society's teleforums, its Executive Branch Review Conference, and lunch panels throughout the year. So we would encourage you to keep track of all of that if you're interested in the Practice Groups. They cover just about every area of practice and law. And if you wanted to serve on an executive committee, we would encourage you to reach out to the Society and get involved. And, finally, we want to thank those involved in the Practice Groups for putting these panels together at the conference.

 

      Second, let me just provide a reminder that, to qualify for CLE credits, you must sign in and out once per day using the CLE QR code, which is posted in your program and throughout the lobby and the area here. You need to do that once a day to check in, once a day after the last panel to check out in order to get credit.

 

      Third, an announcement about this evening:  The banquet tonight, the dinner tonight, is not at Union Station this year; it is at the Washington Hilton. If you've gone to Union Station, you are going to be having a different dinner. So make sure if you want to get to the dinner, beginning at 5:15, there are shuttle buses to the Washington Hilton. They will leave the Mayflower lobby here every five minutes. Pickup is in the back entrance, and the last bus will leave at 6:30 near the gift shop. Pickup is near the gift shop.

 

      Finally, it is my privilege and honor to introduce our moderator for this afternoon's panel, the Honorable Carlos T. Bea. Judge Bea serves on the U.S. Court of Appeals for the Ninth Circuit, to which he was appointed in 2003 by President George W. Bush.

 

      Judge Bea is a graduate of Stanford University and Stanford Law School. He began his legal career in private practice in San Francisco, principally in the area of civil trials, both jury and non-jury. He taught courses in civil litigation advocacy at Hastings College of Law and Stanford Law School before beginning his judicial service as a judge of the San Francisco Superior Court. Judge Bea, thank you for sharing your time and your expertise with us today. The floor is yours.

Hon. Carlos Bea:  Thank you very much, Jesse, for that nice introduction, and we'll get started on this panel. Recent cases from the Supreme Court have indicated a trend to send cases back to Courts for an application of state constitutional and statutory law. It's been called, in this panel, the Federalist revival. For those of us who attended the session down in Arizona in 2020 regarding the Federalist Papers, the distribution of power to the state sounds to me more like an anti-Federalist than a Federalist idea, but anyway, that's the subject of today's presentation.

 

      I will introduce first of all, each of the panelists, and then they'll make their opening remarks in the usual form. And then we'll take a few minutes to discuss a case that I finally got back last year from the Supreme Court telling me to apply California choice of law rules that you might be interested in.

 

      And then we'll have a period of discussion among the panelists, questions regarding the practice of remanding for application of state laws. So then, the question is -- We'll finally come around to asking the question, why is the Supreme Court doing this? Why is the Supreme Court getting interested in application of state law? Besides having read Jeff Sutton's book, why are they doing this?

 

      So we'll start out with introductions. On my immediate left is Justice Evan Young, who is a Justice of the Supreme Court of Texas. He was appointed by Governor Abbott in 2021 and was elected to a full term the following year. Justice Young is a former clerk of both Harvey Wilkinson and Antonin Scalia and served as Counsel for the Attorney General in the U.S. Department of Justice and did us a stint in Iraq in 2007 and 2008 at the embassy there. He went into private practice and worked for Baker Botts and is the chair of the firm's Supreme Court and Continental Practice Group. That's Evan Young.

 

      Immediately to his left is the Honorable Rebecca Bradley, who is a Justice on the Wisconsin Supreme Court. She was elected in 2016 after being appointed by Governor Scott Walker in 2015. And before joining the Supreme Court, she served as a district court of appeals judge and a county trial judge, circuit court judge, and worked as an attorney in private practice.

 

      To her left is—and I'm not trying to indicate political positions by saying that—is the Honorable David Wecht, a Justice on the Supreme Court of Pennsylvania. Judge Wecht joined the Court after his election in November of 2015. Prior to joining the Supreme Court, he served as a Judge of the Superior Court and of the Court of Common Pleas in Pennsylvania's Fifth Judicial District.

 

      And also, he's the author of one of the cases that he probably will be discussing, which has to do with the financing of public schools based on state and local financing. Judge Wecht was twice elected to the Allegheny County Registrar of Wills and clerks in Orphans' Court. So, with that, we'll get started, and I'll ask for opening remarks from Evan Young.

 

Hon. Evan Young:  Well, I am delighted to be here. And my being here -- Any of the three of us -- not Judge Bea. Any of the three of us is statistically improbable, in fact, and I say that because there are 172 active U.S. Circuit judges. There are seven vacancies, it looks like. Of those 172, 22 of them are on panels at this year's National Lawyers Convention, 13 percent of the total. And there are at least a couple of senior judges, a couple of district judges, a couple of other federal judges of 28 federal judges.

 

      Of the 330 state Supreme Court justices in the United States. There are four, three of us and Justice Mitchell, who was on a panel a little bit earlier. And why is that relevant? The 1 percent of the Supreme Court, 13 percent of the circuit judges, why is that relevant? Well, it's because that ratio is actually an improvement for the state courts.

 

      State Supreme Courts have been something of a backwater, maybe in real life, but certainly at Federalist Society National Lawyers Conventions, as the dozens of federal judges every year really put the federal in Federalist Society. The reason for the state Supreme Courts seeming like backwaters was that, for a long, long time, most of the highest stakes litigation, especially of constitutional magnitude, was in federal court and often about federal constitutional law, too.

 

      When I went to law school, I had a professor—some of you may have had him as well—Professor Ellickson, property law scholar, and he diagnosed what he called the Yale Law School disease. And that disease was that, even if you had to -- If you have to find a principle of state law, the way you do that is by finding some federal court that has said what state law is. And it can be a district court in a different state; that's okay, but you wouldn't want the Pennsylvania or the Wisconsin or the Texas Supreme Court.

 

      That's what the Yale Law School disease was, and it was a malady that resulted from, I think, in large part, the extreme federalization, constitutionalization in so many areas of our law. And so that meant that what state law was mattered an awful lot less in an awful lot of very important cases.

 

      Now, I'm not trying to overstate that -- well, not overstate it too much. State law always mattered. Erie guesses were always important. State law was what the federal courts would and still do apply when state law questions are determinative. We'll talk about certification, I think, a little bit later, often in contractor insurance or tort law questions when there's diversity jurisdiction.

 

      But the very existence of this panel reflects that some of that is changing, at least in some areas, what state law is, even if the bread and butter of state Supreme Court still typically is superintending the common law, construing statutes, regulations, making sure state government is working.

 

      The Supreme Court of the United States is edging—in some cases, jumping perhaps—towards making state law play a much larger part of daily life of our citizens than it perhaps did in an awful lot of areas up until relatively recently. Of course, that's not just for state courts; it's states. We just saw a couple of days ago, another example of the people of a state saying, "Fine. If that's not going to be federalized, then we will decide for ourselves what that will be." It's not just state courts. It's states now that really matter in terms of saying what the constitutional principles that govern our people will actually be.

 

      That's the first point that I want to make, that even if you don't necessarily accept the premise that states were sort of backwaters when it came to the great constitutional dialogues, at least maybe you could accept that they're becoming much less so now. And the second point is that a number of state courts, including mine, have not done all that much over our histories to explore the differences between our state constitutions and the federal Constitution.

 

      In part, why bother? If the federal constitution is going to be so over-present, omnipresent, and govern everything, there's not a whole lot to be gained in many instances, or so the theory was, from exploring the nuances of our state constitutions. And there are many kinds of constitutional provisions in state law where this matters.

 

      Sometimes the state provision might be more or less coterminous with federal law. And I'll take Texas, for example, because I know it a little bit better. Our contracts clause in our constitution reads almost identically to the federal contracts clause, and there's evidence that that was purposeful. But our takings clause does not read like the federal takings clause; it reads quite differently, and there's evidence that that was very purposeful as well.

 

      And there are other kinds of clauses. In Texas, we love juries. We love juries for everything in Texas, so much so that we have multiple provisions of our constitution. In our Bill of Rights, there's a jury trial provision. Also in the judiciary Article of the Texas Constitution, there are other provisions guaranteeing the right to trial by jury, but historically, we've just said, "Well, it probably means the same thing," which can't really be right because they're written differently. They were added in different ways, but we're only now beginning to explore these questions.

 

      And then there are other kinds of provisions. We have the due course of the law of the land. We don't have a due process clause. A lot of states don't do course clause. What do all of those mean? Well, we don't know because our tradition has largely been to say, "It probably means what the federal Constitution means. Call the next case, and hopefully it's about insurance law or something."

 

      And there are two reasons at least for that. First, as I mentioned, why bother? Whatever we say the Texas constitution meant, in many instances, the U.S. Constitution is going to trump. And then a second reason is even less salutary, and that is that we historically have gotten very little help from parties and lawyers in the bar, and this is starting to change.

 

      I wrote a concurring opinion that's in the materials called City of Baytown v. Shrock about our takings clause. And Justice Busby, of course, has written another opinion raising some of these point about our takings clause, which is that you might really have a good Texas takings claim, but if you just mouth with the words Texas and federal constitutions, and then you only bring to our attention federal case law and federal doctrines, that isn't doing anything to help us figure out what the differences might actually be.

 

      And so my third point is that this is an increasingly urgent problem. It poses serious risks of us having a doctrinal deficit in this way, a gap that is there, as the Supreme Court of the United States seems to be causing federal principles to recede. And that creates risks because, when there is a gap, the temptation is to fill it, and perhaps to fill it unwisely, given—and not all states are like this, but in many—the remarkable level of undeveloped or at least underdevelopment.

 

      And you mentioned Chief Judge Sutton's great books, which are wonderful, anticipating some of these problems describing it. I think the solution is not necessarily for Supreme Courts of the states to move into fifth gear and just say, "All right. We're going to fill the gap immediately because our job instead is to soberly undertake the very serious work of determining the original public meaning of our state constitutions."

 

      And my fourth point is that that is a very hard thing to do, much harder than it is compared to the federal Constitution. Not that that's easy, but our state constitutions often are much bulkier; Texas is second only to Alabama in our length. We have entire forms in the Constitution with blanks that would be used for home financing statements.

 

      We have provisions that describe the taxation of green coffee beans imported into particular ports in Harris County or the creation of drainage districts in Ector County. We just had 13 new provisions of our constitution added on Tuesday. The only one that the voters rejected was the one that would allow judges in our state to serve past the age 75. They nixed that one, and they almost nixed the provision that would have allowed Galveston County to abolish the position of county treasurer. People really thought maybe they needed that county treasurer and Galveston County.

 

      But we have all of this complexity, it's constantly changing, and it's all so much less well sourced than the federal Constitution is. And so it's much harder to really meaningfully reliably systematically figure out what the original public meaning is, and you add to that the dearth of precedent that would perhaps have arisen at the time or near the time when these provisions were enacted.

 

      And so we need help. We need help from the bar, from the government, from the Academy to bring us good cases, to preserve state issues at all times in the litigation. We need amici to be entering the fray on both sides of these important issues. We need state government to be doing hard archival work to be gathering the information so that our state constitutions can be meaningfully interpreted.

 

      And we need to make sure that even though the chips are going to fall where they're going to fall, that we don't let them fall until we know for sure what they mean. And that's my last point that, in any given case, regardless of what kind of those four kinds of texts that I mentioned, there are at least three options that we have to keep our eyes peeled for and open for. And that is that perhaps the state constitutional provision really does and purposefully meant just what the federal analog says, or maybe it really does protect a lot more purposefully than the federal analog did, or maybe it protects a lot less. And all of those need to be options that we think hard about so that we can take this opportunity, recognizing it also as a risk to make sure that our courts are doing their job when the U.S. Supreme Court is creating space for them to do it.

 

Hon. Carlos Bea:  Thank you very much, Justice. Now can we hear what problems Wisconsin has?

 

Hon. Rebecca Bradley:  I need more than an hour and a half for that. Good afternoon, everyone. I'd like to thank The Federalist Society for the invitation to participate in this panel. And thank you, Judge Bea, for moderating it, and thank you, Justices Young and Wecht, for participating. The United States Supreme Court's renewed respect for federalism and state sovereignty is something to be celebrated, but there is good reason for caution.

 

      In Wisconsin, new federalism has a pejorative connotation. Under our state constitution, the people of Wisconsin gave the lawmaking power to the legislature. Nevertheless, nearly 20 years ago, Wisconsin suffered the dictates of an activist state Supreme Court that didn't hesitate to exceed the limits of its constitutional authority.

 

      This year, a state Supreme Court election shifted the balance of power from a majority philosophically committed to textualism, originalism, and respect for our structural constitution to a new majority with a philosophy grounded in politics and policy, unrestrained by universally respected boundaries surrounding the exercise of judicial power.

 

      For Wisconsin, I predict the recent ascendance of federalism will embolden the wrong branch to resolve all the important policy questions reserved to the states or to the people. In 1948, Winston Churchill observed those that fail to learn from history are doomed to repeat it. So I will briefly recount some relatively recent Wisconsin Supreme Court history.

 

      In 2004, then-Justice Diane Sykes left the Wisconsin Supreme Court for the Seventh Circuit Court of Appeals. The governor appointed Justice Butler to the open seat, creating a liberal majority. As Judge Sykes described it during her Hollows Lecture at Marquette University in 2006, the court's term following her departure was a watershed that marked a dramatic shift in the court's jurisprudence, departing from long accepted principles that normally operate as constraints on the Court's use of its power.

 

      I recommend reading Judge Sykes' remarks in full for an in-depth study of how an activist court can intrude on the prerogatives of the political branches for the purpose of imposing judicial policy preferences on people who previously rejected them through the democratic process. I'll give just a few examples of the Court's willingness to manipulate the Wisconsin constitution to justify its policymaking.

 

      In State v. Knapp, the defendant was suspected of killing a woman with a baseball bat. A police officer went to Knapp's apartment to arrest him and asked for the clothes he wore on the night of the murder. Knapp pointed to a bloody sweatshirt which the officer seized after intentionally withholding Miranda warnings. He was charged with first-degree intentional homicide, and his attorney filed a suppression motion, which the trial court denied.

 

      The Wisconsin Supreme Court reversed, and the state appealed to the United States Supreme Court, which vacated the judgment and remanded the case back to the Wisconsin Supreme Court because its earlier decision was inconsistent with the newly decided U.S. v. Patane case. In that case, the Court held that the failure to give Miranda warnings does not require suppression of the physical fruits of the suspect's unwarned but voluntary statements.

 

      On remand, the Wisconsin Supreme Court decided to, in its words, utilize the Wisconsin constitution's analogue to the Fifth Amendment to reach the same conclusion as its initial review had produced, specifically the Knapp Two Court held that the Wisconsin constitution requires suppression of the physical evidence obtained as the direct result of the Miranda violation. The majority expressly embraced the new federalism movement in doing so.

 

      Now, I agree that state courts should not reflexively interpret state constitutional provisions in lockstep with their federal counterparts. And, of course, state constitutions can afford greater protections to its citizens than the federal Constitution provides, but the constitution itself must actually provide them. State courts do not have the authority to invent protections that are nowhere to be found in the constitution as originally understood.

 

      The Knapp Two court did mention a case decided shortly after statehood, in which our court declared no person is compelled to give evidence against himself or to testify in any manner tending to incriminate himself, but the Knapp Two court did not even attempt any historical analysis to support its theory that, somehow, the violation of those rights means suppression is the remedy for the violation.

 

      Instead, that court relied heavily on its view that the officer's conduct was repugnant and required deterrence and the court's professed desire to preserve judicial integrity. However well-intentioned, judicial policy goals cannot alter the fixed meaning of the constitution. Neither repugnant facts nor intolerable actions by law enforcement have anything to say about the meaning of the privilege against self-incrimination or the remedies for its violation. These were nothing more than justifications for the exercise of judicial will.

 

      Although a majority of my court may, at times, prefer certain constitutional protections for criminal suspects, it remains the prerogative of the people of the state of Wisconsin to bestow them. As a sidenote, even though the court in Knapp Two acted beyond its constitutional authority, its holding was never overturned, despite a 15-year period during which judicial conservatives held the majority and had the opportunity to overturn it.

 

      For state courts, the laboratory of experimentation tends to ratchet the law in one direction toward results generally favored by progressives. Why? Because judicial conservatives often apply the doctrine of stare decisis even in cases in which an earlier decision was objectively wrong. Judicial conservatives are also more likely to read provisions of state constitutions in lockstep with federal Courts' interpretations of federal counterparts.

 

      Last year, my court decided a case in which a transgender defendant challenged the constitutionality of a statute prohibiting sex offenders from legally changing their names. She argued that the law violated the Eighth Amendment's prohibition on cruel and unusual punishment and the free speech clause of the First Amendment.

 

      After examining the original meaning of those constitutional provisions, we concluded that the statute did not offend them. Three members of my court disagreed. They said, "But times change. Societies evolve. Instead of looking backward to esoteric sources to define the contours of modern existence, we should instead look as we do in other contexts, to 'evolving standards of decency that mark the progress of a maturing society.'"

 

      Had that case been postured differently, a majority of the members of my court, as currently constituted, could very well utilize our state constitutions free speech clause to impose their personal notions of evolving standards of decency and reach the result that the First Amendment denied them, but they would have to disregard the text in order to do so.

 

      Now, if the people elect judges who all but promised to decide cases in accordance with their personal values, why should we be concerned? As one reporter asked me, isn't that democracy? Whatever one wishes to call it, having a handful of lawyers refashion the constitution in accordance with their own personal values without the participation or the input of the people is an affront to democracy.

 

      Although it may be tempting for people to elect state court judges who will achieve policy outcomes they desire but are unobtainable from the democratic process, it is a dangerous electoral choice to relinquish the power that the people constitutionally retained for themselves.

 

      In his dissent in Obergefell, Justice Scalia said the practice of constitutional revision by an unelected committee of nine robs the people of the most important liberty they asserted in the Declaration of Independence, and one in the revolution of 1776: the freedom to govern themselves. Justice Scalia also wrote, "A system of government that makes the people subordinate to a committee of nine unelected lawyers does not deserve to be called a democracy."

 

      Even though Wisconsin elects its justices, it is not democracy to subordinate the people to a committee of four lawyers, regardless of how they are chosen. Justices are, after all, elected to exercise judicial power, not legislative, and judicial elections can never override the constitution.

 

      Even if evolving societal mores could change the meaning of the Constitution, why should the personal policy preferences of a handful of judges prevail over everyone else's? Any student of jurisprudential history knows that judges are not reliable protectors of individual rights or liberty when they seek to replace the original meaning of the Constitution with their own notions of the way things ought to be.

 

      Only the Constitution, given a fixed meaning that changes only through amendment, can serve as a reliable bulwark of the rights and the liberty of the people. As we proceed in this new era of renewed federalism, we would do well to keep in mind Hamilton's warning in Federalist Number 78: Liberty can have nothing to fear from the judiciary alone but would have everything to fear from its union with either of the other departments.

 

      Should the court on which I serve resume its encroachment on the legislature under the banner of new federalism, the people can choose to reverse course in future elections, but Wisconsin history shows us the damage is not easily correctable and often stands uncorrected. Wisconsin history illustrates the dangers of a movement that may be misused to transform a court into what Judge Jeffrey Sutton has called a court of outcomes. Thank you.

 

Hon. Carlos Bea:  Thank you very much. Justice Wecht.

 

Hon. David Wecht:  Thank you, Judge Bea. It's a pleasure to be here. I was mentioning to my fellow panelists before the session started that I recall, 30 or 35 years ago, attending a few of these National Lawyers Conventions when I was a lawyer at a firm down the street. I lived up the street and worked at a firm down the street, and I'd stop here and attend some of the sessions. And the crowd was a lot smaller than, but the discussion was just as delightful then as it is now, and I'm very pleased to be here with all of you.

 

      I'm also pleased to hear from Justice Young that the Yale Law School was very similar when he attended that it was when I attended, and the state courts were kind of an afterthought. Here we are. So as you all probably know, one of the sparks for the new judicial federalism was a speech that Justice William Brennan gave at the Harvard Law School in 1977, and it became a very influential law review article. And my colleagues have mentioned Judge Jeffrey Sutton's books, which have really developed this area of law quite thoroughly and quite well.

 

      And I guess one way to approach this subject is to note -- And, of course, this is consistent with the Preamble to the Constitution with the Ninth and Tenth Amendments that the states and the people themselves, of course, preceded the federal union. And in Pennsylvania's case, our constitution is significantly older than the U.S. Constitution; our first constitution was adopted in 1776, the same year of our independence as a nation and in the same building, Independence Hall in Philadelphia, which some of you have toured, no doubt.

 

      One of the authors of Pennsylvania's constitution was Benjamin Franklin. And we on the Pennsylvania Supreme Court have had occasion to note that our constitution is the ancestor, not the descendant, of the United States Constitution. Indeed, along with Massachusetts and Virginia's constitutions, the Pennsylvania constitution played an important role in the thinking of Madison and others as they approached the drafting and debates around the Constitution of the United States of America and its ratification. Now, we can go back to 1932, and I'm sure you all remember Brandeis' words from the New State Ice Co. v. Liebmann case that it is one of the happy incidents of the federal system that a single courageous state may.  If its citizens choose, serve as a laboratory.

 

      And, of course, this is the beauty of our federalism and the idea that the various states in our union experiment, and we all learn from these experiences and, hopefully, gain in wisdom as time goes on; at least, that's the idea. The Pennsylvania experience is one that evolved not long after the Burger Court signaled that there would be some retrenchment from the Warren Court.

 

      And there grew, correspondingly, an interest in many of the states in exploring whether certain protections would be found under their state constitutions. And, of course, we rely on lawyers -- I understand the litigation section of The Federalist Society is involved in this. They're sponsoring this session. And I'd be remiss if I didn't mention now—because I might forget at the conclusion of my remarks—to urge you litigators to raise these claims.

 

      Because I'm sure my colleagues could agree, and I can certainly tell you, that there are many, many, many instances in which -- And this is very consistent with that Yale Law School mentality. We're beating up on our alma mater here. Professor Amar is here. He's going to rise to the defense of our alma mater. Litigants forego and just miss raising, even invoking, state constitutional provisions, which might, if developed properly, be found to afford greater protections.

 

      But if the claims aren't made, of course, we can't develop those claims for the litigants, and we don't. But there have been innumerable cases in my time on the court when a colorable state constitutional claim was not made, and I think that's simply a frequent default of people to think only of the U.S. Constitution, notwithstanding the efforts of Brennan and Sutton and so many others to flag this principle of state constitutionalism, of course, which is very much in line with the philosophy of this society based on federalism.

 

      Now, to give you just a very brief tour of illustrative cases, I just want to mention four in Pennsylvania. We could talk about them in greater detail if you like, or not. The in 1991, during that burger retrenchment, a case reached the Pennsylvania Supreme Court, Commonwealth vs. Edmunds. We're one of the Commonwealths.

 

      In the Edmunds case, long story short, the Supreme Court of Pennsylvania interpreted the cognate or correlate provision, the similar provision on warrantless searches, Article I, Section 8 of our Constitution, which corresponds, in large measure, to the Fourth Amendment to our United States Constitution. And the court declined to adopt Leon's good faith exception to the exclusionary rule.

 

      And there were several other states that had then or have since followed Pennsylvania's opting out from the good faith exception to the exclusionary rule, and that was premised in part on the court's judgment that, based on the text and history of Pennsylvania's provision, that it's based on a privacy rationale rather than a police misconduct prevention rationale. So Edmunds provides the framework for analyzing or comparing, when the claim is raised, whether the Pennsylvania Supreme Court should find some divergence or greater rights under its charter than the than the federal charter.

 

      Three illustrative cases during my tenure on the Pennsylvania Supreme Court, which I'll touch on briefly -- And they involve different provisions of Pennsylvania's constitution. In this case, unlike the Edmunds case, none of which have a cognate or correlate in the U.S. Constitution. I emphasize that.

 

      First, then, the Pennsylvanian -- And these are in your materials. I believe these are all in your materials if you want to read them in detail. The Pennsylvania Environmental Defense Foundation case, 2017, interpreting a provision of the Pennsylvania constitution which reads as follows. This is in Pennsylvania's Declaration of Rights. Obviously, this was added long after 1776 but adopted in 1971 by the people of Pennsylvania.

 

      Listen to this language because it will strike you as being unlike anything in the U.S. Constitution. "The people have a right to clean air, pure water, and to the preservation of the natural, scenic, historic, and aesthetic values of the environment. Pennsylvania's public natural resources are the common property of all the people, including generations yet to come. As trustee of these resources, the Commonwealth shall conserve and maintain them for the benefit of all the people."

 

      Time doesn't permit me to go into all the aspects of this, but obviously, there's a public trust created there, and the Commonwealth, the state government is the trustee protecting those environmental rights. Hawaii has a similar provision. And since Pennsylvania's was adopted, some other states have adopted similar provision.

 

      We held in the case I mentioned, Environmental Defense Foundation, that it does not require legislation to be enforceable. Prior cases had held that there was no right of action to enforce it, that it was not self-actualizing, that the legislature had to, in effect, provide an enforcement mechanism. We held that that was incorrect and reversed that precedent.

 

      The second one, William Penn School District, I was the author of that majority, 2017, interpreting our thorough and efficient public education. That was my reminder to shut up. I'll be quick. I did that to try to respect the limits, which I'll now disrespect a little bit, just real quickly.

 

      William Penn School District. Going back to 1682, William Penn's framework of government for Pennsylvania set out that the people should spare no cost and providing for education, and in fact, that was codified as a thorough and efficient public education responsibility in our general assembly.

 

      We held in the William Penn School District case that that was justiciable, reversing a case called Moraira, which has said it's not justiciable but it's a political question. And we sent that back for trial, and that trial did happen and resulted in an order for the General Assembly to provide adequate funding for public education.

 

      Finally, in the League of Women Voters case, which some of you have read about, we took a petition challenging the legislative districting alleging the congressional districts were politically gerrymandered, and under Pennsylvania's free and equal elections clause, which has no cognate in the U.S. Constitution, that claims for political gerrymandering, packing, cracking, dilution of votes are justiciable.

 

      A year later, in Rucho v. Common Cause, SCOTUS said, there is no tool, there is no yardstick, by a 5-4 margin, for claims under the U.S. Constitution, but specifically cited our decision and said that relief may be available under the state constitutions. And in fact, as I said, we had held in in 2018 in the League of Women Voters case that such claims are recognizable.

 

      So again, that's just some highlights from Pennsylvania, and I would urge you as lawyers, when you're representing your clients zealously, whether in a civil or criminal case, to think about and consult your own state constitution, and you may be a pioneer of developing some case law interpreting your own state's organic charter. Thank you.

 

Hon. Carlos Bea:  Thank you very much. I'm going to take advantage of my position as a moderator to supplement some of what you've heard from the states by telling you about the case that I mentioned earlier that will illustrate to you what the Court is doing as far as remanding cases for state adjudication.

 

      The case involves a very famous painting by a 19th century French impressionist, Camille Pissarro, that was owned by a Jewish family in Berlin in 1939 and was stolen from them by the Nazi government. The painting disappeared for years and was finally sold by a count in Austria, Count Thyssen-Bornemisza, to the Spanish government and went into a museum in Spain.

 

      When it happened to go to the museum, the family that had owned the painting learned about the painting's existence. They thought it was lost, and they brought claims against the Spanish museum to have the painting returned to them in the Central District Court in California. The case proceeded through several appeals, and finally, the decision of the Ninth Circuit was that the law of Spain, which allowed, in effect, adverse possession, if the painting were held openly, notoriously, and as ownership by the museum for a period of years, the title would, by adverse possession, be in the Spanish Museum, rather than in the Jewish family that had owned the painting.

 

      That decision was appealed to the Supreme Court of the United States. Supreme Court Justice Kagan writing said that the jurisdiction for the case was under the Foreign Sovereign Immunities Act. And since the museum was holding a painting which had been expropriated, immunity didn't apply.

 

      So, therefore, the action in the District Court in Los Angeles was similar to a diversity action. And therefore, the question of which law applied, the choice of law, whether California law, which would vest the painting in the family, or Spanish law, which would vest  painting in the museum applied, that should be determined according to California law; not federal law, not the restatement of conflict of laws, but California law, which is quite unique.

 

      So the case came back to us. The split panel decided to certify the question to the California Supreme Court. What is the California choice of law rule as to this situation? And one of the reasons given by the advocate for the family for asking for certification of that question was that, quite frankly, he said, "We'll be better off in the California Supreme Court than you are here in the Ninth Circuit."

 

       So the case was certified to the California Supreme Court. And in August of this year, much to the surprise of a lot of us, the California Supreme Court denied certification 6-1. So the case has come back to us now and is under submission. But this is a case -- This opens up the whole question of certification.

 

      What has been your experience, Justices Young and Bradley and Wecht, with certification of questions by federal Courts to your courts?

 

Hon. Evan Young:  We get them all the time, and our court has not refused a certified question for 30 years or more. And in part, that's because, the last time it happened, I think that it was regarded as an example of the Fifth Circuit saying, "Well, look, if we're going to have these cases involving Texas law, we think it's respectful to the Supreme Court of Texas to give you the opportunity to resolve a recurring issue that seems often to come up."

 

      There are questions like that. There are questions of state law. The Uniform Fraudulent Transfer Act often will have these questions that seem to only arise in cases that have -- the federal Courts have jurisdiction over them. Some of them are always removed, for example. And so to not have to constantly guess, to get an answer is a way of maximizing cooperative federalism.

 

      And so when the court apparently—this is way before my time—refused, it seemed like that was an affront to the Fifth Circuit. "Well, fine. If you don't want to, let's do our own, and maybe we'll never certify anything again." And so, for whatever reason, that custom in our state has taken hold, but it's not just California.

 

      I get the emails every day from the Fifth Circuit, and they, within the past year, I think, certified something to Louisiana Supreme Court which also said, "Pound sand." That's not the way we do it. In fact, in our state, when we get a certified question, we not only will answer it; we set it for oral argument. We all go out onto the bench. So that takes up some precious space because we're only going to have 65 or 70 oral arguments a year.

 

      And if a circuit gives us something, we take it, and that does lead to a little bit of a conceptual problem sometimes. If the party that really wants the certification was the party that removed the case maybe from state court into federal court, then loses, "Wait, wait, wait. Let's get the Supreme Court to answer the question."

 

      It might not have been something we would have granted the petition for review. We grant very few of them, we have 1300, 1400 cases that come. And so it can be a bit of an in-run. We haven't really thought too much about whether we should modify our practice or not, but by and large, it's a lawful advisory opinion that our people had to change our constitution to authorize because it is just advice to the circuit. They are the ones that are going to decide the case, but it's a way of ensuring that the law is uniform in both court systems within our state. So we tend to think that we should do it.

 

Hon. Carlos Bea:  How about you, Justice Bradley?

 

Hon. Rebecca Bradley:  Since I exceeded my time limit in my opening remarks, I'll be rather brief on this one. We regularly will accept certification from a federal court as a matter of comedy. And also, it makes a lot of sense, of course, for the state's highest court to resolve an issue of state law. The only situation that I can envision where our court might decline certification is if we're sitting six, and after our preliminary discussion, it appears the court could split.

Hon. Carlos Bea:  Justice Wecht.

 

Hon. David Wecht:  Yes. Similarly, in the time that I've been on the court, we have not ever declined a petition for certification. I thought I turned that off. Sorry.

 

Hon. Evan Young:  You didn't give yourself very much time.

 

Hon. David Wecht:  Yeah. Boy, I think The Federalist Society cut me off there. So, interestingly, I'm told that in the years -- I was elected in 2015 to this court, and I'm told that, in the years prior, the court had from time to time said no, which is really striking to me. I don't know about to you.

 

      As a matter of comedy, it seems elementary that the Supreme Court of a state would grant certification, there being little to no chance that a U.S. Court of Appeals is going to certify something that's absurd or something it's given no thought to. In fact, when we get a certified question, from one of the U.S. courts of appeals, invariably, there's a writing that accompanies it developing for us, even prior to the briefs of the parties, obviously, what it is they're looking to have answered, rather than just a sentence. You know, there's a lengthier writing, at least a couple of pages, it seems to me, always.

 

      The other thing is, even apart from comedy, it seems completely counterproductive and self-defeating to say no, because why would any state Supreme Court want the U.S. district courts and the U.S. Courts of Appeals to be making mistakes about what the state law means, for lack of a better phrasing?

 

      Perhaps during the era when the Pennsylvania Supreme Court would say no from time to time to certification, there were many—or there were at least several—district court decisions in Pennsylvania U.S. District Court, and I think maybe Third Circuit, too, that had made a prediction about whether Pennsylvania would follow the second or third restatement of torts, and the predictions were that, yeah, we'd follow the third restatement.

 

      And when the Pennsylvania Supreme Court, before I was on it, finally got around to deciding that issue, it said, No, it's the second restatement. And so, had the court granted certification, probably a lot of wasted time and resources by federal judges and all the litigants and lawyers in those courts would have been avoided.

 

      So I don't see any reason -- In fact, we have an argument session the week after Thanksgiving, and we have a certified case from the Third Circuit that we'll be hearing that week. And we've heard certified questions from other circuits, too, although, most commonly, obviously, is the Third Circuit.

 

Hon. Carlos Bea:  Have any of you, on the question of certification, considered that the loser in the federal court who asked for certification to the state court might be engaging in forum shopping?

 

Hon. Evan Young:  It occurred to me as an advocate. When it happened to me when I went to Fifth Circuit, and then they said, “Oh, I'll go to the Texas Supreme Court." So I had to argue in that court and won it there, too. But, yes, it is something that is a risk. And so, by and large, I think that our thought is, well, the circuit is the one that's going to have to figure out and protect its own integrity. And if it decides, based on all of the factors, that it needs the answer from the state Supreme Court, there's at least a strong presumption that we'll do that. We only will take it from appellate courts. There are a lot of states that will take certification even from district courts, I don't think we could possibly do that, just given the size.

 

Hon. Carlos Bea:  How about you two?

 

Hon. David Wecht:  We only take it from the circuit. Yeah. And that's what they want to do. I'm not aware of other -- I'm not aware of any -- Well, let me say this: The Third Circuit takes those themselves. They don't let the district courts, as far as I know, certify. I'm not sure about other circuits, but I've never seen a certification request from a U.S. District Court to our court.

 

Hon. Carlos Bea:  All right. Well, we've heard about a lot about original public meaning here. That's the basis of this whole convention. Tell me, how is the Supreme Courts of these three states dealing with the issue of original public meaning versus original intent versus a living Constitution? Is that a subject matter discussion which is going on these days?

 

Hon. Evan Young:  Well, it probably varies from state to state, court to court. In Texas, it is not a formal doctrine, but I think that most of my colleagues will say, "If we can get what the original public meaning was, that's the gold standard." The problem is, how do you do that in a lot of things? And as I mentioned earlier, it's really hard with a lot of the various things that have happened and changed and modified a little bit that way.

 

      We had our -- You're the 1776 constitution; we're the 1876 constitution -- amended about 1000 times since then., but when the bulk of the work was being done, a vote was taken about whether they should spend a couple of dollars to have a court reporter take down the notes of the convention.

 

      And we Texans, we're pretty careful with our money. Well, why would we waste that a couple of dollars for that? That's a terrible use of the people's money. So we lost access to all of that. So it's hard. In theory, yes, we want to do the original public meaning, but finding out what it is, is sometimes much more challenging than you would think. And so we're turning to lots of sources to try to get as much data as we can before we mistakenly say, "Here's what the constitution means," only to then be proven wrong and then have to have a stare decisis fight on our hands.

 

Hon. Carlos Bea:  What are you doing in Wisconsin, Judge Bradley?

 

Hon. Rebecca Bradley:  We were doing originalism, but I think that is at its end with the new composition of the court, and there has been a lot of writings, concurrences, dissents, and sometimes in the majority opinions where the debate between living constitutionalism and originalism has manifested.

 

      And during my tenure on the court, which has been eight years, originalism has usually won out, although as the members of this audience will appreciate, there are debates among the originalists about original public meaning, depending on the provisions that we're looking at. Of course, we have much more richly developed originalist sources.

 

      And I think the state Supreme Courts are happy when the federal judges will write concurrences if it isn't in a majority opinion on particular issues because, at least in Wisconsin, we are much more resource constrained than our federal friends on the judiciary. I, for example, have two clerks. We often do look to what the federal courts have, have done and have written at least as a starting point if we're looking at issues of federal law.

 

      With respect to state constitutional originalism, of course that is a much more difficult endeavor because of limited sources. I have one that's an analysis and exposition of the constitution of the state of Wisconsin. It's a slim volume. This is the original constitution written shortly thereafter. And our constitution has not been amended thousands of times, but at least about 150 times, so the more modern amendments or additions to the constitution, there might be more resources available.

 

      But it's a heavy lift sometimes to get attorneys, particularly those serving in the public sector from our state attorney general's office or public defender's offices. They're resource-constrained as well, and it's a very time-intensive endeavor to do it correctly. But we have, at times, again, in separate writings, urged attorneys to present the state constitutional argument to us if they have arguments to be made under the federal and the state constitution.

 

      But like my friends in other states, we have some very unique constitutional provisions in Wisconsin that do not parrot the federal counterparts, and that is certainly an avenue for litigants to have a way of prevailing in their cases, but, of course, that has to be presented correctly. And the research has to be done thoroughly in order to ensure that the justices get it right.

 

Hon. Carlos Bea:  David?

 

Hon. David Wecht:  I just heard a podcast -- Of course, the best one is Professor Amars, Amarica's Constitution. That's the best podcast. I heard a podcast just recently by the National Constitution Center, which has great podcasts. It was a discussion between Professor Sunstein and, I think, Professor McConnell on this very issue.

 

      And one of them—I'm sure Professor Amar has read it—has a recent article addressing all the various -- trying to do a taxonomy, actually, of all the various species of originalism, textualism, hybrid theories, living constitutionalism, etc. And it's, of course, as you can all appreciate, far more than a dichotomy.

 

      There are many, many -- Depending on how you define the various idiosyncrasies of different jurists' approaches, even on our current Supreme Court of United States, there are different species of originalists and textualists and what have you. I guess it was Justice Kagan who wrote not too long ago, "We're all textualists no." So the text, obviously, is the beginning. Often, it's not the end, and that's where a lot of the debate arises, of course.

 

      I'll just add one more thing. In Pennsylvania, under our constitution, we never abandon the people of Pennsylvania, never abandon the Jacksonian impulse. So we still elect all of our judges at all levels. And we just concluded -- We, the people, just elected a justice on Tuesday. And very much, from what I read in the news, the two candidates were debating this issue, among others, how they approach interpreting the constitution statutes.

 

      And this debate about originalism, textualism, and living constitutionalism was, of course, at the forefront, though probably not discussed at the same level of eloquence and academic sophistication as Professor Sunstein and McConnell or Professor Amar. It's funny you ask the question because we were just seeing the candidates speaking about this debate in Pennsylvania.

 

Hon. Carlos Bea:  Okay. The next section of this presentation is opening up to the participants any questions that they may want to ask other members of the panel or to talk about generally, and then we'll go to questions from the public.

 

Hon. Evan Young:  Well, Justice Bradley just mentioned something. There are provisions of the Wisconsin constitution that don't pair with the federal constitution. And I mentioned that we have some that seem to and some that don't, but let's assume for a second that that is one that does. It's word for word the same as the U.S. Constitution.

 

      Well, that sounds like now we know the answer, but I'm not sure that that's quite right because if, 150 years ago, the people of Pennsylvania, Wisconsin, or Texas enacted a provision that's word for word what the U.S. Constitution was at that time, does that mean that all we have to do is to look and see what the U.S. Supreme Court, 150 years later, says that it means, or is that a command by the people of our state, for their judges in their state, to accurately say what they think the U.S. Constitution meant, regardless of what the U.S. Supreme Court says?

 

      It's a very tricky little dilemma and opens up a whole new universe, even when it seems like it's the easiest question. "Oh, thank goodness, this is just the same contracts clause as the federal constitution has. We can go home." Well, not so fast, and that's a real problem that we have not really begun deeply to grapple with, but I'm afraid we're going to have to.

 

Hon. David Wecht:  I think, Justice, you've identified a very interesting issue because, in that Edmunds case I mentioned in 1991, unlike the three cases I mentioned that that we've decided since I've been on the court, in that case, there was, not identical, but a provision that was very similar. But the 1991 Supreme Court of Pennsylvania nonetheless arrived at a different -- by looking not only at the text, but at the history of the Pennsylvania provision -- because we have records going back in Pennsylvania.

 

      The related case law from other states and policy considerations unique in Pennsylvania's experience, including unique issues of state and local concern and applicability within modern Pennsylvania jurisprudence, a four-part test. So when there are, unlike these three cases, cognate or correlate provisions, the Pennsylvania Supreme Court applies this Edmunds rubric to determine whether we depart or not. And in our case, many of our provisions precede the U.S. Constitution provisions.

 

      But I think you've identified an interesting issue because, at least from what I understand from our precedent, we have an independent duty to interpret our own state constitution. And if we are persuaded by SCOTUS's rationale, we can adopt it, but we don't rubber stamp it in any sense, even if, in theory, it's identical.

 

Hon. Rebecca Bradley:  And in Wisconsin, the court has, I think, very reflexively interpreted counterpart provisions of the Wisconsin constitution consistent with how the federal courts have interpreted the federal constitution counterpart, particularly when the language is nearly identical. And I don't believe that that is the proper course, but there has to be the historical evidence to support a contrary interpretation.

 

      I think the lockstepping has happened over a long course of time because, for one, it's easier. Again, in the state court system, we tend to be more resource-constrained than the federal judges are. And, secondly, if there aren't resources available—and until the advent of computers, and even then, it's still difficult to do the research—it's very difficult, very time-intensive to uncover the historical evidence that would support an interpretation that departs from how the federal counterpart is interpreted.

 

      Wisconsin's constitution, unlike Pennsylvania's, at least originally, is from the mid-1800s. And so I think there is just a natural tendency to go back and look at, well, the language isn't any different, so we're going to follow what the federal courts have said, but I don't think that should be done reflexively.

 

      But again, the evidence has to support a different interpretation. And we do not in Wisconsin, at least, for now, introduce the policy considerations that I think are part of Pennsylvania's test, as I've read the Edmunds case that Justice Wecht has talked about.

 

Hon. Carlos Bea:  If there are no other questions that the panelists want to kick around among themselves, we'll turn to the public and ask your first question. Please identify yourself and then ask a question.

 

Nicholas DeBenedetto:  Good afternoon. My name is Nick DeBenedetto with the Pacific Legal Foundation. Question I have for the justices is, thinking about a situation where you're trying to do two tracks of originalism at the same time and how you might think about a situation that you could call a constitutional leapfrog -- And specifically, what I mean by that is, famously, many state high courts have rejected the Supreme Court's Kelo decision, and they've said that the state takings clause is more protective and more robust.

 

      How would you think about a situation where the Supreme Court subsequently changes its interpretation of the takings clause to something that is perhaps more originalist and more faithful to the original public meaning? Is it the case that you're unnecessarily left with a dead provision of your state constitution, or is there something still there to grapple with maybe with respect to background principles in the common law that might give additional life to the relevant provision of the state constitution?

 

Hon. Carlos Bea:  Who wants to handle that one? Kelo under state law different from Kelo federal law.

 

Hon. Evan Young:  I would say that it's maybe a manifestation of the very thing we were just talking about a little bit, and that is, if we were to start off with two choices: One, we're just going to reject that based upon our own constitution if we have text and history that justifies that, I don't know that that would make much of a difference what the U.S. Supreme Court were to say.

 

      Maybe the U.S. Supreme Court comes to the same conclusion; eventually, they match up. It shouldn't necessarily matter if the clause is different. They're just different sources of the law. They can be more or less protective of each other, and you let the chips fall where they're going to fall, but if it's a situation in which the text is the same, the understanding is, "Well, we're in lockstep with it."

 

      It's a little strange for the Supreme Court of Texas to say, "Well, our takings clause means the same thing as the federal one. We didn't know until the Supreme Court just said, "Admit this Kelo," whatever you might want to say, then fast forward 15 years. "Well, now the Supreme Court says that the federal one doesn't mean that anymore, so the Texas one doesn't mean that either. That's more piggybacking than leapfrogging or anything else or whatever in a melee and metaphor we want to take. And that's the conceptual problem that we've been talking about, and I think we just have to do our best to use our own text history.

 

      While I think, Justice Bradley, you're quite right to say -- I don't want to put words in your mouth here, but I thought I heard something about the idea that maybe if you already have something that's similar language and you have something in the Supreme Court, that's maybe not a bad default starting point until you have something else that's really solid to go by.

 

      And I'm not super excited about just saying, without any strong reason to say it, that similar language in our constitution means something completely different. I need some reason for it, especially if the federal Constitution has already been given a binding construction. It makes me a little nervous to jump out ahead unless I have a good reason to. I don't want to jump and not know what's beneath me.

 

Hon. Carlos Bea:  Okay.

 

Hon. Rebecca Bradley:  If I understand the question correctly, I'd like to think I wouldn't find myself in this conundrum because I would not reflexively, again, follow the United States Supreme Court's interpretation of the federal takings clause when Wisconsin has its own, which is a little bit different textually.

 

      So being presented with the issue, I would undertake the originalist analysis. Now, I think Judge Bea, I don't know that I actually answered your question. Wisconsin, it would not be original intent originalism; it would be original public meaning. I think that has prevailed in Wisconsin, as it has in most jurisdiction.

 

      Because the question shows the absurdity of saying that state constitutional provision must mean what its counterpart means under the federal constitution because a federal court, or many federal courts, have said so because that fixed meaning cannot change based on changes in what judges say in cases. That's nonsensical.

 

Hon. Carlos Bea:  David?

 

Hon. David Wecht:  Yeah, I agree with my colleagues. And I think your question underscores the need to drill down and do a state constitution analysis because, if SCOTUS reverses itself and all that the state has done is parrot SCOTUS, then query whether, without further analysis, the court in the next case simply says what they said. So it just points out the need to do an independent analysis, but again, time and time again, lawyers just blow it off or just phone it in or don't actually raise the state constitutional claim, and it's a foregone opportunity.

 

Hon. Carlos Bea:  Let's go over here.

 

David Ziemer:  Yes. David Ziemer from Wyoming, but originally from Wisconsin. And, Justice Bradley, there is one time that the Wisconsin Supreme Court didn't do that. This was before you were on the court, and this was after Butler was long gone. But if the U.S. Supreme Court had held that a jury does not need to have 12 people, but the Wisconsin Supreme Court said that, under the Wisconsin constitution, there must be 12 people.

 

      And what their reasoning was, was that by the time our constitution was adopted in 1840-whatever, a jury meant 12 people. That was just common understanding. And I guess that that's the only time I've ever known the Wisconsin Supreme Court to do anything like that. But I was wondering if any of you guys -- And I don't remember how well it was reasoned or anything or what they all looked at, but I was just wondering if that's something that either you dealt with that in a different context.

 

Hon. Carlos Bea:  Any comment on it?

 

Hon. Evan Young:  I can't think of anything else in my head that would be helpful.

 

Hon. Rebecca Bradley:  I can't comment on the reasoning. I'd have to go back and look at it.

 

David Ziemer:  I don't remember the name of it.

 

Hon. Carlos Bea:  All right. Back over here.

 

Akhil Amar:  Akhil Amar, Yale Law School. I want to ask a question about originalism, precedent, reliance, and criminal procedure. So it's going to be more probably for Justices Wecht and Bradley, given the Justice Young sits on a court that mainly has --

 

Hon. Carlos Bea:  Could you speak up a little bit? I can't hear you.

 

Akhil Amar:  -- civil jurisdiction. Question about the relationship between criminal procedure, precedent, reliance, and originalism. Justice Bradley, I've heard you say -- We heard about two cases, one about excluding fruits of a Miranda violation, contra Patane. And Justice Wecht talked about the Edmunds case, which is about the good faith exception to the exclusionary rule more generally.

 

      Has any prosecutor ever made the -- Because it's not just private litigants. There shouldn't be a ratchet at all here because, as a matter of originalism, for the first 100 years after the founding, no court ever excluded evidence just because it was improperly obtained, state or federal. And so Edmunds is wrong, actually, as a matter of the original meaning of the Pennsylvania constitution, which some of us have studied.

 

      And that Wisconsin case was wrong to reject Patane. And you can say -- Has any prosecutor said, "Yeah, there's precedent, but there's no reliance here"? Because people actually don't legitimately rely, "Oh, if I had known that there wouldn't be this exception to the exclusion rule, I would have never committed that murder, that rape, that robbery. Oh, I would have been much more careful about hiding the blood on the clothing."

 

      Because it seems to me the precedent is rooted in rule of law values, which are connected to reliance and the rest, has any prosecutor actually said, "No, this shouldn't be the ratchet at all in criminal procedure"? Because I heard justice Bradley say that's actually what some of the conservatives worried about, and so you never overruled that Patane case. And same question about the Edmunds case.

 

Hon. David Wecht:  Well, I would just say that I am looking forward to reading your amicus brief, Professor Amar, arguing for the reversal of Edmunds, and I will read it closely and consider it. Of course, I remember -- Was it Chief Justice Roberts at his confirmation hearing, when he talked about a super duper precedent, or was it somebody else? I guess Edmunds would be as close to that in the Pennsylvania setting as most precedents, as probably any other precedent, but I take your point.

 

      And certainly, the court should always be willing to entertain arguments that its precedent is wrong. And I often rail against precedent that I think is awful. I'm reminded of that time—maybe some of you were there; maybe it was a Federalist Society event—where Justice Scalia and Justice Thomas were sitting on a panel, and there was a question asked about precedent. And Justice Scalia pointed at Justice Thomas and says, "That's easy. He doesn't believe in it." So, for my part, I'm very willing to -- I suppose I'm more willing than many to say to overrule precedent, notwithstanding asserted reliance interest, although I don't minimize them.

 

Hon. Carlos Bea:  Anybody else want to comment on it?

 

Hon. Rebecca Bradley:  Well, I can respond by saying, to my knowledge, no prosecutor has made that argument because I don't think there were ever four votes on the Wisconsin Supreme Court to go back to original meaning in the manner that you suggest. So it would be a losing argument. And I think a lot of conservative jurists who might otherwise either subscribe to originalism or be open to it would say, "Well, that ship has sailed, and so we're not going to go there." But no prosecutor to my knowledge has made that argument in Wisconsin,

 

Hon. David Wecht:  I would just say that a prosecutor in Pennsylvania who wanted to revisit Edmunds and say Pennsylvania should have the good faith exception to the exclusionary rule should definitely cite your work and should get you on an amicus brief. I would look forward to reading it.

 

Akhil Amar:  Thank you, Your Honors.

 

Hon. Carlos Bea:  Do you want to weigh in on it?

 

Hon. Evan Young:  He mostly directed it to my two colleagues because he knows the people of Texas have given me one of the greatest gifts imaginable, which is to say that I have no jurisdiction over adult criminal cases. We do have juvenile criminal cases, and we occasionally have some collateral things from it, but we've got the luxury that gives a judge on the Supreme Court of a big stat -- the amount of time that some of my colleagues have to spend, can't get to a lot of important civil cases. That's pretty much what we do with the civil stuff.

 

      But I would say that I'm not sure that the analytical points you made are all that different.  , I wrote a stare decisis case in my first year on the bench, and tomorrow will just be the anniversary of my second year, so I'm still the newest one on my court. And it was about a procedural issue involving when there's a severance of cases and you accidentally file something and the old one -- then the jurisdiction of the court expires, and that's the end.

 

      Well, nobody acts in reliance on that, just like they don't act in reliance on the exclusionary rule when they decide to commit some heinous crime. And so when you're thinking about whether stare decisis applies, I think that mean mode of operation is really important in any legal context.

 

Akhil Amar:  Thank you.

 

Hon. Carlos Bea:  All right. Next question over here.

 

Anthony Sanders:  Anthony Sanders, Institute for Justice. I would question about the flip side, the lockstep problem you were discussing. Many state constitutions have these provisions at the beginning of their Declarations of Rights that Steve Calabresi calls Lockean natural rights guarantees that have these broad language protecting property and liberty and the pursuit of happiness even. Two of those states are Wisconsin and Pennsylvania.

 

      And many state Supreme Courts, including Wisconsin and Pennsylvania, have interpreted these provisions to basically be due process clauses, even though they do not contain the words "due process." And then they couple that even with the U.S. Supreme Court, what is said about the due process clause in the Fourteenth Amendment. So is that a problem, and what can we do about it?

 

Hon. David Wecht:  Well, I would just say that I've written several concurrences and dissents inciting Professor Amar, by the way, on the oxymoronic nature of substantive due process and calling for SCOTUS, and failing SCOTUS, then other state and federal courts to develop a jurisprudence under the Ninth Amendment, which is still anemic. It hasn't developed since my constitutional law professor Charles Black wrote on -- What was that book called, that thin book, Professor Amar, on reading the Ninth Amendment?

 

      Anyway, it's died on the vine. And of course, since the slaughterhouse cases in 1873, privileges or immunities have never been developed. And in the federal context, the Ninth Amendment and the privileges or immunities clause, I think, ought to be doing a lot of the work that has been crammed into this substantive due process construct that has become increasingly problematic as it gets examined over time.

 

      I would say that you're exactly right that Pennsylvania has entrenched in its first article of its constitution, and in the preamble, a Declaration of Rights. So there's a substantive component right in Pennsylvania's constitution that is quite lacking under the U.S. Constitution, again, unless you're finding it in the Ninth Amendment or the privileges or immunities clause or substantive due process. But we've got the substance in our Declaration of Rights. At least we've got substance that you don't find in the U.S. Constitution, Lockean.

 

Hon. Rebecca Bradley:  I've actually written on this. Unfortunately, I was in dissent. It was coauthored with Justice Daniel Kelly, who was then on the court. I think he might be in the audience, but the glare from the lights precludes me from identifying him in the audience. But the case is called Porter v. Wisconsin, and the individual challenging was challenging the constitutionality of an anti-combination statute. He owned a cemetery and wanted to operate a funeral home, and there's a piece of rather protectionist legislation in Wisconsin that precludes that sort of dual ownership.

 

      And one of the arguments that we were presented with is whether there's a right to economic liberty under the inherent rights, Declaration of Rights, which is Article I Section 1 of the Wisconsin constitution, which as you note, as is the case in many other jurisdictions, has been interpreted to mean something procedural and not a source of substantive rights.

 

      So we looked back at cases shortly after ratification of the Constitution to find out what was meant by the Liberty clause, particularly within the context of economic liberty in some very early cases, and I mean early; a decade or two decades after, and in some cases, several decades after statehood.

 

      The Wisconsin Supreme Court did recognize a right to earn a living as one of the great bulwarks of individual freedom guarded by fundamental law. The court also said that laws interfering with the right of the citizen to pursue his calling which invade the right of the citizen to pursue a lawful business cannot be upheld.

 

      And in these early cases, the court declared unconstitutional. laws that prohibited, in one case, plumbers from engaging in the plumbing business as a solo plumber that had to be in partnership with other plumbers. So the early cases said that the general right of every person to pursue any calling and to do so in his own way, provided he doesn't encroach on the rights of others, cannot be taken away by legislative enactment.

 

      So again, unfortunately, these are separate writings. It has not prevailed as the majority view because, again, the majority of my court has tended to adhere to stare decisis, even when the lookback into original meaning shows that their early decisions are and were incorrect.

 

Hon. Carlos Bea:  Thank you. Evan?

 

Hon. Evan Young:  I don't have anything further to add.

 

Hon. Carlos Bea:  Okay. Next question over here.

 

Arif Panju:  Arif Panju with the Institute for Justice. And I assure you, we are not engaging in federal lockstepping with my colleague Anthony Sanders. But my question is about federal lockstepping and, in looking at original public meaning of state constitutions, the importance of the structure of a state constitution.

 

      We all know that enumerated powers are how the U.S. Constitution opens up, but usually, a state constitution opens up with very robust restrictions on power, the very opposite. And I wonder, when looking at the original public meaning, is the very structure of a state constitution the fact that it frontloads protections for liberty and constrains power right out of the gate enough to reject federal lockstepping and the watered-down tests and deference that comes along with that, and instead have a more pro-liberty, more engaged, from a judiciary standpoint, jurisprudence because the ratifiers ratified something very different than the U.S. Constitution structurally? So the question is about structure.

 

Hon. David Wecht:  I would just say, I think you're right. You folks file really good briefs, by the way. I haven't always agreed with you. You haven't always agreed with me, but I think your briefs are always interesting. You know, Pennsylvania's constitution begins -- well, Article I Section 1 is titled The Inherent Rights of Mankind, and it says, "All men are born equally free and independent and have certain inherent and indefeasible rights, among which are those of enjoying and defending life and liberty; of acquiring, possessing, and protecting property and reputation; and of pursuing their own happiness."

 

      So structurally, obviously, you see from that, that sounds a lot more like the Declaration of Independence, or at least the way it starts, than it does the U.S. Constitution, which is not a happenstance or coincidence because I told you it was drafted in the same building and the same year as the Declaration of Independence, and Franklin was perhaps the principal draftsperson. So, yes, structurally, I think there's a big difference, and textually, there certainly are differences.

 

Hon. Carlos Bea:  Okay. 

 

Hon. Rebecca Bradley:  I agree with that as well. In Wisconsin, as I mentioned, Article I Section 1, this is not a preamble. This is the very first provision of our state constitution, says, "All people are born equally free and independent and have certain inherent rights. Among these are life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness." And this part is very important: "To secure these rights, governments are instituted."

 

      And so that's something that I think our branches of government, our elected officials sometimes lose sight of the fact that elected officials, their primary purpose is to secure the rights of the people. And everything else that flows in our constitution, particularly when we're looking at the powers that the people have given to each branch of government, we have to remember that we exist as government officials to secure the rights of the people.

 

      And it ends by saying, "To secure these rights, governments are instituted, driving their just powers from the consent of the governed."  And so when any branch of government exceeds its constitutional authority, as laid out in this sacred document, they are acting without the consent of the governed.

 

      And I think the structural constitution is sometimes missed by litigants, by attorneys, who are giving short shrift to the structure of the constitution, what it means to put a provision like that as the very first provision of a state constitution. I have to say, I don't blame them because of the way that my court and, I think, other state courts have given this only procedural significance rather than substantive significance.

 

      And as a final point, I'll say, again, in giving substantive meaning to a provision like that, it can't just be, Well, liberty means everything. It meant something when this provision was ratified by the people, so the evidence has to be there historically.

 

Hon. Carlos Bea:  I'm sorry. We've run out of time. I can't take your last question. I want to thank the panel because I think they've done a great job of stretching our minds as to the importance of state constitutions in litigation. And you'll all be probably guilty of malpractice now if, having heard this panel, you don't read your state constitution before you start drafting.

 

Hon. Evan Young:  It'll take a while to read the Texas constitution, though, so big cup of coffee.

 

Hon. David Wecht:  So everything's big in Texas.

 

Hon. Evan Young:  That's right.

 

Hon. Carlos Bea:   Let's show our thanks to the panelists. I'm required to read to you the following:  If pursuing CLE, make sure to sign out using your CLE QR code. Beginning at 5:15, shuttle buses to the Washington Hilton will leave the Mayflower Hotel every five minutes. The pickup is on Desales Street. The last bus leaves the Mayflower at 6:30. Okay? Thank you very much, and see you at dinner, not at the Union Station.

 

 

     

 

 

3:30 p.m. - 5:00 p.m.
Religious Liberty in the Work-and-Market-place

2023 National Lawyers Convention

Topics: Religious Liberties • First Amendment • Labor & Employment Law
State Room
The Mayflower Hotel
1127 Connecticut Avenue NW
Washington, DC 20006

Share

Event Video

Listen & Download

Description

The Supreme Court’s decisions in 303 Creative LLC v. Elenis and in Groff v. DeJoy posed issues about religious freedom in the workplace and religiously motivated speech in the marketplace. This panel will consider the cases and their implications for religious freedom, especially how future cases might apply the tests articulated by the Court for “substantial costs” to a business for making an accommodation in Groff, and for what counts as expressive messages protected against the application of state anti-discrimination laws under 303 Creative. The panel will also consider the broader question of if there is value in accommodating religion in the workplace despite conflicts with employer preferences, and likewise, if there is a value in accommodating businesses (especially small businesses, where this typically arises) in light of broader societal preferences (such as non-discrimination law). Observers indicate that Title VII represents statutory values and 303 Creative raises Free Exercise constitutional values, but both cases pose questions about making room for faith in public life.

Featuring:

  • Prof. William Eskridge, Alexander M. Bickel Professor of Public Law, Yale Law School
  • Ms. Erin M. Hawley, Senior Counsel, Alliance Defending Freedom
  • Mr. Aaron Streett, Chairman, Supreme Court and Constitutional Law Practice, Baker Botts LLP
  • Mr. Adam Unikowsky, Partner, Jenner & Block LLP
  • Moderator: Hon. S. Kyle Duncan, United States Court of Appeals, Fifth Circuit

Overflow: Cabinet & Senate Rooms

Speakers

Event Transcript

Prof. William L. Saunders:  Okay. Welcome, everybody. Welcome. We’re getting ready to get going. I’m going to give you an announcement that I’m sure that you have not heard before, so listen closely. On CLE, for those of you who are pursuing CLE, we remind you that to get credit, you need to sign in and out each day, once per day. Signing in and signing out can be done via the scanning the CLE QR codes. Thus, if you’re pursuing CLE and you have not checked in, please do so -- to scan the QR code on the back of your convention booklet or on the CLE poster. If you have already checked in via the QR code, however, there is no need to recheck-in.

 

Now, a second new announcement, which really may be new to you today, that’s on the getting to the dinner tonight. So listen up. If you have tickets for the Antonin Scalia Memorial Dinner, this is a brief reminder that we are at a new location. I think some of you heard Dean say we’re at the Washington Hilton. We’re not at the train station. Shuttle buses to the Hilton will be available, starting at 5:15 and running to 6:30 every five minutes. Pick up will be Desales Street on the side of the hotel. Further details concerning transportation are in your convention booklet or in the app.

 

So third announcement is welcome to this panel. I’m Bill Saunders, and I’m the Chairman of our Religious Liberties Practice Group. I hope many, many old friends here, but anybody who’s new and not involved in the Practice Group, we welcome you to get involved. You can speak to me. You can speak to Nate, or you can speak to this gentleman over here, Michael Moreland — hold up your hand, Michael — who is the Vice Chairman of the Practice Group and is the incoming Chair of the Practice Group. So next year, he’ll be up here speaking to you. But if you’re interested, we welcome you, and we have plenty of work to do, as Michael can tell you. So okay. So now, I turn the -- I’m going to turn the whole event over to our good friend and distinguished judge of the Fifth Circuit, Kyle Duncan.

 

Hon. S. Kyle Duncan:  Thank you. Thank you, Bill. I am honored and delighted to moderate this wonderful panel. We will be discussing two decisions from the 2022 Supreme Court term that address religious liberty and speech in the marketplace and in the workplace. Just a few brief remarks and I will introduce our all-star panel. The first case we’ll be discussing is 303 Creative v. Elenis, which sustained a free speech challenge of a Christian marriage website designer to a Colorado public accommodation law that she claimed would have forced her to speak about same-sex marriage in ways that violated her conscience. The six-justice majority by Justice Gorsuch situates the Court’s decision within the line of famous cases like Barnette and Dale and Hurley that vindicated claims by plaintiffs who were forced to speak or associate in ways that violated their consciences. By contrast, the three-justice dissent by Justice Sotomayor took a diametrically opposed view, accusing the majority of allowing a spurious speech claim to validate discrimination against a protected class.

 

The second decision, Groff v. DeJoy, is much less controversial but, nonetheless, significant. It was a unanimous decision that was effectively a clean-up operation to clean up a long-standing problem in the Court’s Title VII jurisprudence. The case involves a Christian mailman who sought from the Postal Service a Title VII accommodation, allowing him not to work on Sundays. The issue was what showing an employer had to make to deny such an accommodation under the statute. Was it “an undue hardship,” as the statute itself provided, or mere “de minimis cost,” as lower courts had held for years, based on one sentence in a 1977 Supreme Court decision called Hardison? The Court unanimously clarified that the proper test is what the statute says, an undue hardship. But applying that clarified test in future cases, of course, is another matter and one the Supreme Court has left to the lower courts to develop, which we always appreciate.

 

To discuss these two important decisions, we have assembled, as I said, an all-star panel, an extravagantly well-qualified panel that I will briefly introduce here; although, I could say much more about them. First, to my left, Ms. Erin Hawley, who is senior -- serves as senior counsel to the appellate team at Alliance Defending Freedom. Before joining ADF, Erin practiced appellate law at some of the best law firms in the land, and she has litigated extensively before the U.S. Supreme Court. She has worked in the Department of Justice as counsel to Attorney General Mukasey. She has also been an associate professor of law at the University of Missouri Law School where she taught many classes. She is a frequent commentator on legal issues in all the best publications in the land. And she formerly was a law clerk to the chief justice of the United States, Chief Justice Roberts, and Judge Wilkinson of the Fourth Circuit. She made sure -- she asked me to make sure to mention that she went to Texas A&M --

 

Ms. Erin M. Hawley:  Woop.

 

Hon. S. Kyle Duncan:  -- so she could make that sound. [Laughter] And she got a law degree from Yale School --

 

Prof. William Eskridge:  Woo. [Laughter]

 

Hon. S. Kyle Duncan:  -- reportedly one of the finest law schools in the nation. Okay. Speaking of Yale Law School, to her left, Professor William Eskridge, Jr., the Alexander M. Bickel Professor of Public Law at the Yale Law School. I probably shouldn’t say, “the Yale Law School.” It’s just Yale Law School. I have a very -- extremely restrained and humble description here. I’m sure I could go on forever about your publication, Professor. Your most recent book, written with Christopher Riano, is Marriage Equality: From Outlaws to In-Laws, which was awarded the ABA Silver Gavel Award for best nonfiction book in 2020. We’re delighted to have you here.

 

I should mention that -- [Applause] -- I should mention that Erin is a late addition to this panel, and we are very grateful for you coming on board at the last minute.

 

Aaron Streett is the Chairman of Baker Botts’ Supreme Court and Constitutional Law Practice. He has argued in front of many of the best courts in the land, including the U.S. Supreme Court and my court, I think. I think you’ve argued in that court. His practice is varied and covers virtually every substantive area of law. He has argued merits cases seven times in the U.S. Supreme Court since 2010 and has garnered numerous awards. He graduated from Hillsdale College, where my son also goes, so I appreciate that. And --

 

Mr. Aaron Streett:  I don’t have sound that goes with that. I’m sorry.

 

Hon. S. Kyle Duncan:  There is no -- well, it’s the sound of serious deliberation. [Laugher]

 

Mr. Aaron Streett:  Touché.

 

Hon. S. Kyle Duncan:  And free speech, I might add, which Hillsdale ranks number one in and the University of Texas Law School, which is burnt orange and a good law school. You clerked for the Honorable David Sentelle of the U.S. Court of Appeals for the D.C. Circuit and the Chief Justice of the United States, William Rehnquist. We’re delighted to have you here.

 

Last, but not least — and also a relatively late addition to this panel, and we’re grateful for you to be on here — Mr. Adam Unikowsky, who is a partner in Jenner & Block LLP’s Appellate & Supreme Court Practice Group, where he was worked since 2011. He served as a law clerk to the late and much beloved Associate Justice Antonin Scalia and the -- also the much beloved Judge Doug Ginsberg for the U.S. Court of Appeals for the D.C. Circuit. He graduated from Harvard University Law School and MIT. And you run a very -- aside from your marvelous law practice, you also run a very interesting blog that, whenever I feel that I want to find out what exactly the Fifth Circuit is doing wrong, I can always go to your blog.

 

Mr. Adam Unikowsky:  It’s a pleasure, Judge. Thank you.

 

Hon. S. Kyle Duncan:  All right. So we’re -- I’m grateful to preside over this panel and -- or moderate this panel, whatever I’m supposed to be doing. And so, I will turn it over with no further ado to Erin. Take it away.

 

Ms. Erin M. Hawley:  Thank you so much, Judge Duncan. Thank you, panelists, and to FedSoc for having all of us. So today, I have the privilege of talking with you about 303 Creative. And in typical Federalist Society fashion, I have three propositions for you, some of them controversial and some of them more controversial. So first, 303 Creative is a straightforward application of the First Amendment that provides crucial free speech protections for everyone. Second, 303 Creative, while a broad ruling on free speech, is a limited ruling when we’re thinking about the marketplace. It is not, as some critics have said, a license to discriminate. Third, and perhaps most controversially, standing in 303 Creative was not a stretch but is recognized by Colorado in failing to challenge standing before the Supreme Court and by Justice Sotomayor in failing to even mention standing in her heated dissent. I think there was absolutely a credible threat of enforcement there.

 

So to begin with, Proposition One, straightforward application of the Free Speech Clause. At the outset, this is not a case about LGBT rights. It’s not a case about marriage. It’s not even a case about religion. What this case is about is about free speech and about whether the government has the power to force someone to speak contrary to their most deeply held beliefs.

 

So a bit about Lorie Smith. Lorie Smith is a website designer outside of Denver, Colorado. Lorie Smith designs all sorts of wedding -- or excuse me -- all sorts of websites and wanted to expand into the wedding business. Colorado stipulated that Lorie serves everyone, including her gay clients, and she’s always been consistent that she won’t create certain messages with which she disagrees. She won’t denigrate the military. She won’t facilitate cruelty to animals, and she won’t celebrate certain marriages, such as open or same-sex marriages. The record is also clear that Lorie would not design these sorts of websites for anyone, regardless of their personal characteristics.

 

So despite the sort of overheated reaction to 303 Creative, I would submit that Justice Gorsuch’s decision -- opinion -- for the 6-3 Court comfortably fits within the Supreme Court’s precedence. To begin, Justice Gorsuch held that the First Amendment protects an individual’s right to speak his mind, regardless of whether the government thinks his speech appropriate, whether it thinks it well-intentioned or instead deeply misguided. Second, for over 80 years, it has been a fundamental principle of First Amendment law that the First Amendment protects not only the right to speak but also the right not to speak.

 

The quintessential case representing this principle, of course, is West Virginia v. Barnette. Something that’s often glossed over in this discussion of West Virginia v. Barnette, however, is that it overruled a case. Just a few years earlier, the Supreme Court, in one of its worst decisions, had held that a state could force a school child to recite and salute the Pledge, regardless of that child’s religious beliefs. There’s a great, great quote in Judge Sutton’s book that talks about one of the children in this case, saying that “I refuse to do this. I would face the hell fires of damnation if I salute the flag.” And yet, the Supreme Court said, “You have to do that,” in Gobitis.

 

Thankfully, the Court reversed course in West Virginia v. Barnette. And in a quote-worthy quote that we see in many opinions, I’m sure including some from the Fifth Circuit, Justice Jackson wrote that “there’s no principle greater than that that no official, however high or petty, can prescribe what shall be orthodox in politics, nationalism, religion, or other matters of opinion.” In other words, you have the right both what to say and what not to say.

 

Nor was 303 Creative the first time that the Supreme Court has addressed the intersection between the Free Speech Clause and public accommodation law. In a case called Hurley, the Court addressed just this dynamic. And in a unanimous opinion, written by none other than Justice David Souter, he wrote that an “important manifestation of the principle of free speech is,” again, the “one who chooses to speak may also decide ‘what not to say.’” So a unanimous Court in that instance said that a state public accommodation law cannot compel a parade to allow a message that would be contrary to its own.

 

Finally, the Supreme Court, in 303 Creative, rightly acknowledged the public accommodation laws have a long and noble history and much to do today as well. However, under that decision, the -- under the 303 decision, the Supreme Court was crystal clear that its decision applies to speech. A lot of the detractors, including the dissent, posited that the 303 Creative decision endorses a right to discriminate based on someone’s characteristics. With all respect to the dissent, the majority opinion says nothing of the stuff. In four or five different places, including in the first few lines of that decision, the Court goes out of its way to say ordinary commercial transactions are not affected. What is at issue is speech. We’re talking about the Free Speech Clause, and the government has no right to tell someone what to say, regardless of what they think about the content of her speech.

 

So first proposition, straightforward application of First Amendment law. Second proposition, the decision is a limited one when it comes to the commercial marketplace. And you don’t have to take my word for this or, more appropriately, the word of Justice Gorsuch, speaking for himself and five other justices. The New Jersey Attorney General’s Office recently released guidance. So has the Attorney General’s Office in Nevada and other places. And what that guidance says is to, again, quoting the opinion, that state civil rights law still apply to a vast array of businesses selling innumerable goods and services. So where 303 Creative applies -- where the rubber meets the road, again, is the question whether speech is involved, whether something is, a, expressive; second, whether that something that is being created is original and customized; and third, whether the declination to provide the creative service is based on the message it conveys and not on the status of the protected characteristic.

 

So to talk just a bit about each of things. There’s a lot of debate about what is expressive and what’s not expressive. And as Justice Kagan wrote in a law review article published in the University of Chicago, it can be a hard line to draw, but as she also pointed out, that line is worth drawing because if it’s not drawn, that means that the government can regulate most everything simply by calling it conduct.

 

In this case, it’s not a hard line. Lorie uses words and graphics, graphics she draws with her own hands. And as the Tenth Circuit appropriately found, we’re talking about pure speech here. There will be hard cases. There may be wedding florists. There may be wedding cake makers that ask the Court to decide what counts as expression. But this case was not hard.

 

Second, it needs to be customized. As Professor Dale Carpenter says, when we’re talking about dairy or deaths or dry cleaning, we’re not talking about customized services. Those things aren’t expressive either. But we’re not talking about the ordinary goods that we run into on a daily basis. And then, third, the refusal or declination needs to be based on the message rather than on the person requesting it.

 

And I wanted to mention here just a bit about what -- something the dissent says. So the dissent calls this status message distinction both amusing and embarrassing. But I actually think there’s a lot to this distinction between status and messages. First of all, and most importantly, as the majority points out, that distinction is actually part of the Free Speech Clause. And why that is true is because the Free Speech Clause does not protect declination based on something other than a message. The Speech Clause applies to a message and only then.

 

Second, Colorado has, in other context, namely, the context of Jack Phillips of Masterpiece Cakeshop fame, said that context -- or excuse me -- that message and status are, in fact, different. In that case, as many of you will recall, there had been three other bakers who had declined to create cakes for Christian bakers, having messages suggesting that same-sex marriage was not biblical. In each of those cases, the Colorado Commission said that those declinations were okay because they were based on the fact that those messages were demeaning to the baker, in other words, because they were based on the message and not the status. And finally, in -- just a few years, in 2018, the Supreme Court for the U.K. drew the same distinction, finding that a baker could not be required to bake a wedding cake, and in the words of the Court, “this less favorable treatment, the declination, was afforded to the message and not the man.” So again, status message distinction has roots both in the First Amendment as well as Colorado’s treatment and some international law.

 

I wanted to consider real quickly — I know I’m running out of time here — just want a contrary ruling might look like. Under Colorado’s logic, the government would be able to force anyone who speaks for pay on a given topic to accept all commissions on the same topic. As Chief Judge Tymkovich pointed out at the Tenth Circuit, this means that governments could force an unwilling Muslim movie director to make a film with a Zionist message, something, I think, most of us would find unjust. In addition, Justice Sotomayor asserted in her 303 Creative dissent that because the market is “established and maintained by the state,” it is a social contract and part of that could be a legal norm of nondiscrimination on “any business that holds itself out ready to serve the public.” That is a startling statement. In other words, as part of the social contract of having roads, of having clean air, of having those sorts of things, Americans can be compelled to say something with which they devoutly disagree.

 

Finally, standing, I think, in this case was quite straightforward under the credible threat of enforcement. The Supreme Court looked at three factors quite briefly: one, the similar case of Jack Phillips and Colorado’s aggressive treatment of him -- aggressive pursuit of him; second, the fact that any person can file suit under CADA; and third, the fact that -- I’m forgetting the third here, guys. There’s another one as well. Third credible threat of enforcement -- anyhow, there’s a third one as well that they looked at -- oh, yes. It’s an important one, the fact that Colorado had for seven years declined to disavow enforcement. So all of these things, the Court said, lent itself to standing.

 

And to address just briefly the elephant in the room, this is not a made-up case. The facts of the case are that Lorie Smith wanted to expand her wedding business, so she talked to her pastor. Her pastor said, “Hey, look at this poor guy, Jack Phillips. Are you sure you want to do this? If you want to do this, you might want to talk to Alliance Defending Freedom.” So Lorie contacted Alliance Defending Freedom, and that began this case.

 

And again, if you look at the history of pre-enforcement lawsuits, they have been a staple of civil rights litigation for generations. And I’m running out of time, but I would just submit one of the most interesting things about this case, as pointed out per Professor Richard Re, is that it may suggest that the doctrinal lines on standing are shifting. Maybe the left is getting more hawkish on standing and the right, maybe not as hawkish. Maybe this has something to do with the current composition of the Court. Something to consider.

 

Hon. S. Kyle Duncan:  Thank you, Erin. I will, then, turn it over to Professor Eskridge.

 

Prof. William Eskridge:  Okay. You want to be startled. I’ve going to startle you right now, and then, as you can get your two Yale graduates, and we’re both going to talk about doctrine. [Laughter] I kid you not. So I agree on standing.

 

Ms. Erin M. Hawley:  Yeah.

 

Prof. William Eskridge:  I’m a traditionalist on standing, and I think it had standing. But I do think this was a very curious case. I would characterize it somewhat differently and contrast it with both Barnette and Hurley. This is kind of a landmark Supreme Court case. I think it’s the first time the U.S. Supreme Court has ever held that a sale — in other words, an advertisement for sale of a service — is expressive activity that cannot be regulated by the state. Okay?

 

Barnette was not a regulation of sale. This was state compulsion. I’m from West Virginia. I’m totally with you on that. It was egregious what they did before. Okay. And Hurley -- also, Hurley was unanimous. There was a dissent, of course, in Barnette. Should have been unanimous.

 

In Hurley, this was a private parade. And I quite agree with the Professor, that, yeah, it’s an expressive parade, but this could also apply to speech as well, which the Court treated it as. But those are very different cases. There are some cases where the Court did evaluate this precise argument, and two of them are Piggie Park, in 1968, I believe, and Heart of Atlanta Hotel, in about 1964.

 

In Piggie Park, we had the public accommodations law of the ’64 Act being applied to a diner, and the owner of the diner -- these were literally his arguments. The owner of the diner said, “I cannot integrate this diner because the status of allowing black people to intermingle with white people would violate the word of the Lord” — as he understood it as a Baptist, a fundamentalist, and many fundamentalists still believe this — “and therefore, this would not only violate my right to run my business, but it would violate the message I’m trying send in the way that I run my diner.” You can see that, in Piggie Park, status and message are intrinsically intermingled, and the Supreme Court unanimously rejected all of the arguments made by the diner. Heart of Atlanta was a less dramatic case. There were more issues involved, but the Commerce Clause was the main issue. But there was a similar argument made and a similar rejection on the part of the Court.

 

So this is actually a very big deal, and it’s kind of an odd case. I do think there’s standing, but it’s an odd case because this is a pre-enforcement challenge, exactly. But it’s a pre-enforcement challenge that doesn’t appear to be a facial challenge to the Colorado statute. As I understand, the opinion, after the opinion is issued, the Colorado statute still stands, so it’s not facially invalid. So it must be kind of an as-applied challenge, but it’s kind of an as-applied challenge to a hypothetical wedding ad and an undetermined complainant and lack of an administrative proceeding. Again, I don’t begrudge that there can be standing.

 

So we, for example, don’t really know exactly what the wedding site is going to look like. There was some exhibits in the complaint. And according to the stipulations that the Court relies on, according to the stipulations, Lorie Smith, whom I have nothing but admiration for, said, “We’re ready to go with this wedding site, and the only reason we’re not doing it in 2016, 2017,” many years ago, “is because we’re afraid of prosecution. Immediately, once we get relief, we’ll put it up.” Well, I looked at it this morning, and there is no wedding services offered on her website. It says, “Wedding services coming soon,” and this is November 9th. So that’s kind of an oddity.

 

Now, Erin, in y’all’s brief, this -- there was mention, like, “Why do we want to bring a case when there’s no complainant?” Remember, the Colorado Commission generally waits for a complainant to object. There was no complainant in this case, though the brief darkly adverts to a man named Stewart as somebody who had made some inquiry about a same-sex wedding. Well, The New Republic, Stewart’s identifying information is in the joint appendix, which was part of your petition for cert. And The New Republic’s Melissa Grant actually called Stewart, and Stewart says, “I’m married to a woman. I’m not a gay rights person. I’m not gay. I don’t want to marry a man. I don’t know what’s going on here.” So there is a little bit of a mystery.

 

And I will tell you I am a gay person. Gay people do not want to discriminate against religious fundamentalists. And by the way, I think overwhelming majority of religious people do not want to discriminate against LGBT people. And we don’t want to impose ourselves, for the most part, even if we have a right to, on religious people. So I’m just not sure of the stakes there.

 

And then, here’s the real -- where the rubber hits the road, just in terms of not Article III but just in terms of do we really want this kind of record by stipulation — many of the stipulations were omitted by the Court, I might add — to be the basis for this landmark opinion. So it would be better if we had an actual website and an actual complaining couple who actually asked for something, maybe not exactly the same website as she designs for religious different-sex couples, but something maybe more bare bones, and they could go to the Commission — the Commission’s main duty and most of its cases are subject to conciliation — “Is there any way that you can figure out a path for” -- and maybe not. If the Commission does rule, if the Commission is persuaded by Justice Gorsuch, who writes a very brainy opinion, the Commission would have concluded, “This doesn’t violate our statute. Our statue does not say, on its face or as applied or anything -- it doesn’t say it’s discriminatory if it discriminates against a message that has a disparate impact.” You’d have to do a lot of gymnastics to figure that out maybe.

 

So the Colorado Commission might have actually said, after listening          to all the arguments, that it didn’t violate the statute. And then, if they did think that it violated the statute, what kind of remedy would it issue. And it has a lot of potential remedies. And one point I would make is that I do think one of the upshots of all of these cases should be that the Civil Rights Commissions and the statutes should be amended to seek more common ground, not just through conciliation, which I think is a very useful exercise, but through limitation of remedies that can be used against people who, based upon principle, rejected the application. So that’s the first point that this is a very curious case.

 

Here's a second point is that there’s a paradox at the center of the case. Exactly as Professor [inaudible 00:31:53] said, “The majority says the hypothetical violation is because of message, and you cite Barnette and Hurley. The dissent says the hypothetical violation is discrimination based on either conduct or based upon status. It’s a sale, and they would cite Piggie Park and Heart of Atlanta and maybe some other cases.” Well, here’s the paradox. It’s like the certs debate. I don’t know how many of you are old enough to remember that one. It’s not certiorari, but -- or certs. It can’t be --

 

Hon. S. Kyle Duncan:  Mint.

 

Prof. William Eskridge:  Huh?

 

Hon. S. Kyle Duncan:  The mints.

 

Prof. William Eskridge:  Yeah, yeah. Is it a candy mint or a breath mint? The Judge knows the answer to this.

 

Hon. S. Kyle Duncan:  It’s both.

 

Prof. William Eskridge:  It’s both. Yeah, he knows. Okay. This is what’s interesting about the case. It’s both. All expression is conduct, and a lot of expression does go to status. Most conduct and a lot of status is expressive. So a devout Catholic taking communion is status, conduct, and message, both in what they are aiming to express and what an outsider would intuit. Okay?

 

So this is at the heart of the case’s dilemma. So for example, getting married — same-sex marriage, different-sex marriage, interracial marriage, interfaith marriage, etc. — getting married is conduct. It is status. It is expressive. And you can discriminate for or not based upon how you want to characterize that. A refusal to recognize or to deal with marriage, likewise, involves the interaction of all three of these things.

 

So for example, in Piggie Park, the gentleman’s refusal to serve blacks was, from his point of view, based on religion, expressive. It was also conduct, and it was also based on status of the people that he refused to serve. If you refused to cater to an interfaith marriage or interracial marriage, that is conduct. It is based upon status — Protestant, Catholic, whatever your race, same-sex, same-sex, etc., but it also can be religious expression, and it can be status.

 

Now, the paradox of the case actually originates in the stipulations, 2016, seven years ago, the stipulations. And the stipulations do say that Loris Smith does not normally discriminate based on sexual orientation. She would serve a gay client who wanted to do a business website, maybe, maybe. We don’t know. But she doesn’t want to express anything that is contrary to her religion, and another stipulation says her religion is based on the Bible. And stipulation number 75, for the record, is that she believes the Bible requires marriage be a lifelong commitment between one man and one woman. Majority consistently gets this wrong in terms of what she actually believes in. It’s a lifetime commitment, yes, one man and one woman.

 

So it’s not exactly clear how far she goes, and the Court’s decision or maybe even just the Court’s debate, the conduct/status/message debate within the Court, is kind of destabilizing because it relies ultimately on a characterization game. And it asks Lorie Smith, as the owner, what she wants to make of it. She can go in any number of different directions, and let me just give you a few of them. So say Lorie Smith is asked to do -- “Can we do an anniversary website?” A lot of people do that. Gay people, probably not. What about birthdays? Maybe but maybe not. What about funerals? What if you have a funeral, and you have a bereaved spouse, or you have children raised in the relationship?

 

Maybe not. You don’t know. It’s kind of a law-free zone, and if she’s read Romans 1:26-27 recently, she probably is going to discriminate against any gay and lesbian people on a wide array of things, not just marriages. But you don’t know. The opinion sort of gives her carte blanche. What if she -- in y’all’s brief, Erin, you -- she relies on Matthew.

 

Matthew is a great book of the Bible. It has many words of Jesus Christ, our Lord and Savior. But if you actually read Matthew -- read it. Read Matthew 19:9. Jesus Christ never condemns same-sex marriages, never condemns lesbian couples. This was not an idea that he would have been familiar with. He does condemn adultery, and he defines it — he with a capital H — he defines adultery as any situation where a man divorces a wife, not for her infidelity, and remarries.

 

On 5:32, an adulteress is a woman who, while her husband is still alive, leaves him and marries another man. You see where I’m going with this? If you actually believe in the Bible and the literal words of Jesus Christ, after whom the religion is named, then it seems to me that you ought to also discriminate against a lot of remarriages. Twenty-one percent of remarriages, both spouses had been married before and obviously a higher percent, one spouse. I don’t know. Remember she says lifelong. Lifelong means no divorce. And what about interracial marriages? There are still many Americans, hundreds of thousands of them, maybe even millions, but probably hundreds of thousands of Americans which believe still that interracial marriages violate Noah’s curse or even the Tower of Babel for some bizarre reason.

 

And then, what about this? The Court says that we’re only going to spring from anti-discrimination laws what they call creative professionals and that they can exclude almost anyone, which I don’t believe, but that’s what they say. Well, okay. Say you get a family values home builder. We believe in building houses that are like the house of the Lord. We have a particular view of the Bible, and we’re not going to build houses for lesbian and gay families or any kind of families that we consider nontraditional.

 

What about the nonbinary clothing store? The nonbinary clothing store might say, “We don’t believe in gender stereotypes, and the Southern Baptist Convention has repeatedly endorsed gender stereotypes. We’re not going to serve Baptists in our store, only progressives.” What about a progressive hair salon, also discriminating against people who adhere to faith traditions that have marriage or other views that are antinomy to the LGBTQ community? Funeral homes, etc.? You might say, “Funeral homes? How’s that expressive?”

 

Well, Justice Sotomayor cites a case where a funeral home refused to do a headstone that had a message on it that was of a bereaved spouse. A lot of these things can be expressive. And remember -- do not forget. I use the word, “sale.” What is selling? It’s expressive. What is a website? It’s expressive. And a website can sort of lay out, “Here is our philosophy.” Okay. That’s second point.

 

Now, here’s a third point, and that is there’s a danger of vulcanization, and remember, the victims of free speech can be religious minorities as well as sexual or gender minorities or racial minorities, etc. There is a danger of vulcanization, and that is a stratified market with minority religions, minority races, minority sexualities consigned to second-class market situations or just self-segregating into their own markets. We’ve seen that before. That’s quite possible.

 

Now, personally, I don’t think that’s realistic because the expression/status/conduct trichotomy can always be flipped. It’s completely malleable, I think. So take a case that was not mentioned yet, the FAIR case. That was the case where the federal government went after universities, including Yale, and said, “Look, you people are not giving Cadillac treatment to military recruiters — which means advertisements, which means housing, which means linking them with students, etc., etc. — because you think that they discriminate against LGBTQ people.” And the universities said, “This violates our free expression.” The Supreme Court — I think it was unanimous, one justice not participating — said, “Well, but no. They’re regulating conduct, and the speech stuff is just incidental.”

 

Now, by the way, the record in that case — the justices need to read the record more carefully — the record in that case established that the motive for the Solomon Amendment was anti-LGBT. The Solomon Amendment was not viewpoint neutral. It says, “This does not apply to religious universities.” And Yale had a letter -- because Yale said, “Look, we’ll accommodate your folks but just not in the same way.” The Department of Defense — this was in the record — the Department of Defense wrote to Yale University, saying, “That’s not acceptable because that would send a message to your students that we are not as good an employer as the rest of them.” Supreme Court upheld that.

 

So here’s the danger. For the time being, the anti-discrimination sort of has an elastic allowance only basically for anti-gay discrimination. Are they going to overrule Piggie Park? Well, they didn’t in this case. I don’t think they would dare. So private clubs, anti-gay, Dale. Sure. Private marches, private speech, Hurley. Sure. Private businesses. If you can sort of launder yourself into an expressive business, sure. But if it’s a public entity, the Supreme Court has now held twice that public entities can be -- can -- in Fulton, the Philadelphia charitable charities case, which was a state program — it was not private; it was a private group in a state program — says the Free Exercise Clause, First Amendment requires you to discriminate, requires you to discriminate. And in FAIR, it upheld a blatant discrimination by the federal government.

 

So my concern is -- at Yale, we’re actually interested in the rule of law, and we’re interested in the way in which law can be malleable and destabilized, which I think this decision does do. But we also are very concerned that the Supreme Court is sending its own expression, which they’re entitled to do, in terms of speeches. Their own expression is that we now have a constitutional caste system, particularly since 2017, where the ordinary rules are not going to apply in cases where LGBTQ people are complaining, but we’re not going to overrule our sex discrimination cases like Roberts. That was Jaycees. Piggie Park, that was race. Religious discrimination, they’re not going to overrule those cases as well, as we see in the next panel. So that’s my concern.

 

Hon. S. Kyle Duncan:  Thank you, Professor. [Applause] We will shift gears now over to Aaron to talk about Groff.

 

Mr. Aaron Streett:  Thank you, Judge Duncan, and to my fellow panelists and The Federalist Society. It’s great to be here. I had the privilege of arguing Groff and representing Gerald Groff along with the great team at First Liberty Institute and two other firms. And I’m not going to go through all of the facts and all of the precise holdings and subholdings of Groff. Most of you are pretty familiar with it. Judge Duncan gave an overview of it.

 

I also wasn’t going to quote the Bible, but I can’t let Professor Eskridge out-quote me on scriptures, so I looked up the relevant verse. “Remember the Sabbath day, to keep it holy. Six days you shall labor and do all your work, but the seventh day is a Sabbath to the Lord your God.” That’s Exodus 20:8-10. That was at issue in our case, as Judge Duncan said. Mr. Groff believed very firmly that he should not work on the Sabbath day, which he celebrated on Sunday.

 

And what you need to know about the holding, I can tell you in two sentences because I’m going to shift gears a little bit after that, but the key language there is in Title VII, which requires an employer to accommodate reasonably the religious belief or practice of an employee so long as that can be done without an undue hardship on the conduct of the business. And the Supreme Court in a case called Hardison had interpreted that to mean anything more than a de minimis cost, a very low standard for allowing employers to deny undue hardships -- to deny religious accommodations. So the question in Groff was, “Should that standard be overruled, revised, clarified,” and the Court said, “Yes, it should. And in fact, the standard should be interpreted consistent with the plain language of undue hardship on the conduct of the employer’s business,” which the Court said means employers must accommodate, unless there would be a substantial cost to the overall business. Substantial disruption was another formulation that they used.

 

So why the shift? The Court didn’t technically overrule the Hardison case. Why the shift from a very nontextual interpretation to a faithfully textual interpretation? And I think that the key has to do with the Lemon test. We all know about the Lemon test from a 1971 case where the Court set out a three-part test for when a statute violates or a government action violates the Establishment Clause. Does it further religion? Does it have the purpose of furthering religion? And does it cause the government to become entangled with religion? And then, later, we get the Justice O’Connor gloss. Would a reasonable observer think that the government action is endorsing religion?

 

Well, that was very much in the background in the Hardison case, but in a case we all know called Kennedy v. Bremerton School District, also known as the Coach Kennedy case, the Court said, “We’ve abandoned Lemon.” The Court hadn’t really abandoned it up until that point, but once they said they had abandoned it, they’d abandoned it. And they said, “Now, we are looking to text, history, and tradition,” which the Court doesn’t tell us exactly what that means in that case, but the arguments that have typically been made for text, history, and tradition under the Establishment Clause would require a showing of something like government coercion or government taxation to benefit religion. So ideas of burdens and furthering religion and psychological discomfort and that sort of thing are no longer in play under the Establishment Clause.

 

So that’s where we came -- where we found ourselves between Hardison and Groff. Now, we’ve had plenty of discussions on panels like this at The Federalist Society and elsewhere about what Lemon now allows under the Establishment Clause. Are we now allowing school prayer? What other types of religious displays are we allowing now that Lemon is gone and something more like a coercion test is in place?

 

But I’m going to focus today on how abandoning the Lemon test frees up the Court to interpret statutes according to their terms and with using last term’s decision in Groff as Exhibit 1. And I’ll perhaps touch on some other examples that may be coming down the pipe in future comments on this panel. The idea of burdens on third parties has long been a central concept of the Establishment Clause inquiry under Lemon and its progeny. Think about the RFRA case of Hobby Lobby. Much of the debate in that case was not so much centered along the RFRA test itself, which is, of course, a very demanding strict scrutiny test. The idea or the objection to Hobby Lobby’s policy of not providing contraception coverage to its employees was that this would place a burden on third parties and, therefore, would run afoul of constitutional values.

 

There are interesting classes between Hardison and Groff, like a Connecticut statute that actually required all employees to be able to have the ability to take off on Sunday, not any other day, not any other religious accommodation, just Sunday. The Court said that’s violates Lemon. That burdens employees who don’t celebrate that religion and will have to pick up extra work, and that burdens employers who will now have to deal with that extra day from work.

 

So in Hardison itself, there was a lot of briefing on the Establishment Clause. In fact, that was one of the questions on which cert was granted, in Hardison. And it was sort of the ghost in the machine behind the opinion in Hardison. Everybody always wonders, “Well, how did the Court get it so wrong? Undue hardship obviously does not mean more than de minimis.”  And other than being a 1970s decision where the Court really didn’t look at text very much, the real reason was this Establishment Clause backdrop to the case. And the arguments and the concerns that were raised is if we really interpret Title VII according to its terms, undue hardship’s a pretty high standard. An employer is going to have to take on a fair amount of burdens onto itself in order to accommodate religion, and that’s a burden on a third party.

 

That’s always been seen as an Establishment Clause issue under Lemon. And who’s going to pick up the slack for extra -- the extra day of work or the hour of work. Now, usually, it’s not actually picking up the slack. It’s just shifting around time, but who’s going to take the less desirable shift. Well, it may be somebody who doesn’t have that religious belief, so that’s a burden on a third party. So I think the Court, during that time, was quite reluctant to interpret Title VII according to its terms because it was laboring under this misconception of the Establishment Clause that was put forward in Lemon.

 

In fact, if you listen to the oral argument in Hardison, it’s fascinating. It’s just a peek into another era of the -- when Lemon was just fresh off the lemon tree, and Justice White is just, “What if I want to go watch my kid play football on Saturday, and that’s my -- that’s not a religion, but that’s almost a religion to me.” Remember, he was a great football player. “Isn’t that discriminating against me to let somebody else take Saturday or Sunday off because of their faith?” And that’s how it was looked at. And so, that’s where the Court, I think, reached the result that it did in Hardison.

 

After Hardison, naturally, there was a lot of legislative debate about fixing the unduly low standard in Hardison and, perhaps, getting it up to something more consistent with the plain text. But there was testimony in the Congressional hearings that said, “Well, if you increase the level of burden that employers have to bear, then you will be running afoul of Lemon, and Congress never passed a statute like that.” We don’t know if it was because of Lemon. We don’t know, but there are a lot of reasons legislatures do or don’t do things. But that was very much in the debate.

 

Interestingly, we come to Groff. And the Court finally grants cert on a case after 50 years that requires it to address the question of what undue hardship means and whether it should adhere to its formulation in Hardison. And lo and behold, the solicitor general doesn’t even defend the de minimis test. It does not cite Lemon. Of course, Lemon’s been now abrogated or abandoned in Kennedy, and there’s not hardly any discussion of burdens on third parties as a reason to not interpret Title VII according to its terms. There’s discussion of burdens, but it’s in the context of what the words of the statute means, not in terms of what the Establishment Clause means.

 

So what changed, of course, to allow Groff now to interpret Title VII according to its terms? Well, Groff tells us. It’s got a great discussion of Lemon being -- now, it’s called abrogated. Lemon has moved from being abandoned in Kennedy v. Bremerton to abrogated, so I think that’s finally, maybe, the nail in the coffin. And Justice Alito, in his unanimous opinion, says, “We might have misinterpreted” -- or -- “We might have used this loose language in Hardison about de minimis because we were worried about the Establishment Clause, but now, we’re not worried about that anymore. We can interpret this according to its plain meaning. And the Court pulled out the 1970s dictionaries and looked at what undue hardship means and says it means ‘a substantial cost on the conduct of the business.’”

 

So the Court says, “We don’t need to overrule Hardison. We’re just going to clarify it.” If you want to know more, read the opinion. It’s interesting from the perspective of one who litigated it, but the Court says, “The test was not found in our holding, which we stated at the end of our opinion, where we said, ‘We hold de minimis.’ It was found in footnote 14, where we said ‘substantial cost.’” So we’ll take a win how ever we can get it. But it was an interesting way the Court got to a unanimous decision and did not have to use the word “overrule” in a statutory context. But there’s nothing in the opinion about concerns about the Establishment Clause bearing on the interpretation now, and there’s nothing about burdens as a constitutional matter.

 

So of course, with Lemon being now reinterpreted to basically deal only with coercion, we don’t have any government coercion involved here. We don’t have any taxation being involved here. And so, the Establishment Clause doesn’t come into play. What else happened? I think something else very important happened that I sort of dug into as I was preparing to argue this case.

 

When Groff -- when Hardison was decided back into -- back in the 1970s, there was only one statute that required employers to provide accommodations for some protected characteristic. And so, in that sense, you can understand why the Court got it wrong. It looked like there was this targeted favoring of religion. In the time between Hardison and Groff, Congress enacted many accommodation statutes: probably the most famous and relevant one was the Americans with Disabilities Act — which used the exact same language, “reasonable accommodation, absent an undue hardship on the conduct of the employer’s business;” the Pregnant Workers Fairness Act, passed in 2022, just in time for Groff; the USERRA Act, involving accommodating veterans; and probably the most burdensome accommodation statute — and I don’t use that pejoratively — but the one that probably has the most effect on employers is the Family and Medical Leave Act. Anyone can take 12 weeks of family and medical leave. It’s not even based on a protective characteristic. And the employer just has to find a way to deal with it.

 

So it’s become engrained in our culture that, within the workplace, employers and employers are going to work together to accommodate one another’s protected characteristics because we think it’s important for everybody to be able to work in the workplace. So now, with that backdrop, it does not seem anomalous. Nothing seems unconstitutional about requiring employers and employees to bear one another’s burdens so that religious workers can fully participate in the workplace. So where does that leave us? Under Groff, the test is now that the employer must show substantial cost to the business or a substantial disruption.

 

The second holding of the Court is also important. And that’s where the Court does turn to the issue of burdens in context of the statute. And the Court says that burdens on coworkers are not enough, and the Court says, “We got to look at the text of the statute. The statute says, ‘Undue hardship on the conduct of the employer’s business.’” So if an employee has to pick up the shift or shift around the time that he or she works to accommodate a religious worker, then that’s not going to be, in and of itself, an undue hardship on the business.

 

The employer will have to come forward and adduce evidence of the effect on the business as a whole. Is the job not getting done? Is it hurting the bottom line? Is it disrupting the morale in some material way? And again, that was based on an interpretation of the statute, not a single word about “We’re interpreting it this way to comply with the Establishment Clause” or anything like that. So the implication is, of course, some coworkers are going to have to bear some burdens, and yet, nobody says anything that that has any concern for the Establishment Clause.

 

Another interesting issue that’s open after Groff — partially open, at least — is what about unionized workplaces. So in a unionized workplace, you have a collective bargaining agreement. Mr. Groff’s workplace was a good example, the Postal Service. It simply said, in his union agreement, that Sunday shifts will be assigned on a rotating basis. And the Postal Service said, “Oh, we can’t give you a religious accommodation. It’s a pure rotating basis, and if you get an accommodation, we’ll have to breach our collective bargaining agreement. Well, Hardison was open to the reading that any accommodation that required an employer to alter a collective bargaining agreement would be, per se, an undue hardship. That’s what the district court held in our case, which, of course, would mean that employers and unions could just bargain away accommodation rights by not including them in a CBA.

 

Justice Alito’s unanimous opinion, I think, hopefully, if perhaps implicitly, solves that problem. It interprets Hardison very narrowly to only be about seniority rights. It says only if the employer would have to violate a seniority right in a collective bargaining agreement will that be an undue hardship. And the reason that makes sense is because Title VII has a special carve-out protection for seniority rights in collective bargaining agreements. So we now read Groff to say any alteration or accommodation that would be required that would “violate” other provisions of a collective bargaining agreement that don’t have to do with seniority, that’s not a per se undue hardship. Instead, it’s going to have to be judged under the substantial cost or substantial disruption test going forward.

 

And again, that, I think, shows how the shift has made its way from being very worried about accommodating -- from, I guess, being worried about imposing costs on coworkers and more in favor of accommodating the religious practice of individual employees. Incidentally, that issue’s going to probably be resolved on the Groff remand because, as I mentioned, the district court misinterpreted Hardison to say that it would be a per se rule, that any time a CBA needs to be altered, it would be an undue hardship. We think we’ll win on that now, under Groff. I think I will stop there. I think there’s some future issues we can discuss on the next round about other statutes that the Court is now free to interpret, according to their terms, without being worried about violating the Establishment Clause now that the Establishment Clause is properly understood. But I’ll reserve my comments on those.

 

Hon. S. Kyle Duncan:  Thank you, Aaron. [Applause] Last, but not least, Adam.

 

Mr. Adam Unikowsky:  Thank you, Your Honor. First want to start by expressing my thanks to The Federalist Society to -- for inviting me to this incredibly distinguished panel. It’s really an honor, and I truly appreciate The Federalist Society’s commitment to the free exchange of ideas.

 

So I’d like to talk a little bit about a couple of questions that I interpret Groff to have left open. Groff was a unanimous decision, and that’s certainly a testament to the outstanding lawyering of my colleague on the panel today. But as one might expect from a Supreme Court that’s sharply divided on issues of religious liberty, in a unanimous opinion, there’s a number of issues that weren’t decided. So I’d like to focus on two in my remarks today. One is the issue of coworker burdens, that Aaron mentioned, and the other is to what extent an employer would have to pay cash out-of-pocket to hire new employees to ensure that they’re fully staffed. The opinion does use a substantial costs standard, but the question is, “What are substantial costs in this context?”

 

So let me start off with the first question about coworkers. So the decision in Groff makes crystal clear that the fact that a coworker is merely offended by an accommodation is not a reason to deny it. So if an employee seeks an accommodation that might allow him to, for example, wear a beard, the employer cannot deny it because some coworker doesn’t like looking at beards or thinks it’s unfair that the other employee wears a beard and he doesn’t or is just an atheist who hates religion. Those are not reasons to deny an accommodation, and Groff makes that clear and properly so. I actually am surprised that any courts ever went the other way on this, but apparently, there were some horrible decisions of that nature in the past.

 

But what I construe Groff to leave open is the question of tangible harms on coworkers. So just concretely, suppose you’ve got two coworkers, and they’re equally senior, and the employer would like them to split Sundays. But one employee says, “Well, I’m religious, and I can’t work on Sunday.” Does the employer have an obligation, under Title VII, to say, “Well, I’m just going to force the other employee to work every single Sunday, even if it’s against his will.” The other employee may have very good reasons not to want to work every Sunday. Maybe he wants to spend time with his family. Maybe he wants to go to soccer games. I don’t construe the Groff opinion as having resolved that question.

 

At the end of the decision, the Groff opinion puts various options on the table for accommodations in that situation, like voluntary shift swapping, incentive pay, but I don’t construe it as deciding, one way or another, the question of whether the employer is required under Title VII to coerce the reluctant employee, if he’s -- doesn’t -- is not willing to shift -- to swap shifts voluntarily, to work when the employee doesn’t want to. In my opinion, the answer is no. I don’t think that Title VII should be interpreted to require the employer to force the unwilling employee to work every Sunday to accommodate the religious employee’s religious practice. And I guess that’s for a few reasons.

 

First of all, the statute talks about the undue burden to the conduct of the employer’s business. And I think that if the employee’s recalcitrant and files grievances or quits, which are some of the facts that actually occurred in the Groff case itself, I do think that puts an undue burden on the conduct of the employer’s business. I think that respect towards employees, treating them equitably, ensuring that they don’t feel like they’re discriminated against is part of the conduct of an employer’s business. I think most employers would say that. But more fundamentally, Title VII is an anti-discrimination statute.

 

The way it’s set up is that the employer is not permitted to discriminate on the basis of religious practices. You can’t fire someone or not hire them because of their religious belief or practice. And then, as an exception to that principle is the undue hardship exception. So I accept that, if an employer has a facially neutral no-beards rule and is so Procrustean about it that they just fire any employee who wants to wear a beard for religious reason, I accept that’s a form of discrimination against the religious employee. Again, even if it’s a facially neutral rule, that policy reflects such hostility and such unwillingness to tolerate religious diversity in the workplace that I think it’s sensible to consider that a species of anti-religious discrimination.

 

But I think it’s a little different when we’re talking about an employer saying, “Hey, employee, you have to work every single Sunday, even if you don’t want to.” That does sound like discrimination going the other way, in ordinary English. Think of it from the employee’s perspective. “I don’t want to work every Sunday. I have to do it because I’m not religious, and someone else is.” In ordinary English, that is discrimination on the basis of religious belief. And from my perspective, to paraphrase the Chief Justice, the way to stop discrimination on the basis of religious belief is to stop discriminating on the basis of religious belief.

 

And one final point on this, I think that we have to interpret Title VII consistent with traditional conceptions of religious liberty. I think, historically, it’s been a -- religious freedom has been a negative liberty. The government stays away from someone if they want to practice their religion. That’s certainly compatible with a case like 303 Creative, where the website designer simply wanted to be left alone and create websites according to her faith. It’s also consistent with the Hobby Lobby case, where, again, the employer said, “Look, we’re a religious employer. We just don’t want to offer contraception in our insurance policy. Leave us alone, government. Let us hire who we want.”

 

But it’s a little bit different when you’re talking about the government requiring a reluctant employer to require a reluctant employee to work days the employee doesn’t want. That strikes me more as the -- using government as a sword to impose religious beliefs on a reluctant person rather than using religious freedom principles as a shield to ensure that someone can practice according to their faith without government interference.

 

So I’d like to talk about one other issue, which is the question of much money the employer really has to spend to comply with Title VII. So for example, just concretely, in the hypothetical, where there’s the two employees who want to split Sundays, one accommodation is to say the employer can just hire another employee and pay the cash out-of-pocket. And the question is whether, under the Hardison case, the employer has to do that. Well, the opinion says, “substantial cost,” and I don’t really know what that means. And then, it says that, in applying that factor, you have to consider the size and operation cost of the employer. Okay.

 

So the employer in Groff is the federal government, the wealthiest employer in the country. Looking at its balance sheet last year, it earned $-1.7 trillion last year, so surely, the government can afford -- Lord knows, it wastes money on a lot worse. Surely, you could have afforded to hire one more mailman. Right? But there’s a question of whether -- is that substantial? What about Walmart? The opinion calls out Walmart. It says Walmart earned $11 billion in profits. There, it criticized Walmart for not allowing voluntarily shift swapping, but suppose the remedy in one case, the accommodation is just hiring one more greeter for 7.25 an hour. Walmart would never notice that new hire, but the question is whether Walmart should be required, under Title VII, to just hire a new employee to ensure there’s full coverage on Sundays, even if that requires paying out-of-pocket. And I don’t really think it does.

 

But first, let me just register my dissatisfaction with the substantial cost standard because I have no idea what that means in these hypotheticals. So that may seem like a little bit of a low blow. Right? The law tolerates substantiality standards all the time, right, substantial costs in other contexts, substantial compliance, substantial risk, and it’s the easiest thing in the world to say, “Well, where do you draw the line.” Right? The law tolerates a certain amount of ambiguity, and that’s okay. But it just feels a little different in the context of Title VII because the problem is you’re measuring this cost standard against the value of someone living according to their faith.

 

When you’re asking whether there’s a substantial cost, what you’re really asking is is -- you’re asking to measure the cost on the employer with the employee’s ability to practice their religion and work at a particular job. So you’re basically saying is how much is it worth in the abstract, how important it is, how money are we willing to spend to allow this employee to work and still live his life according to his faith. And how do you measure that? And it’s almost a little bit even worse than that because -- in the Groff case, the employer was the government. In most Title VII cases, it’s a private employer. Right? And so, what Groff is essentially commanding private employers to do is to do this measurement.

 

It’s telling, “Hey, private employers, you’ve got to measure the value of the religious practice of your employees and decide is that value substantial.” And then, if you get it wrong, there’s a lawsuit that’s filed because, of course, there’s a private right of action in Title VII, and then, a court is going to make the same determination. And I just don’t even -- it’s just incommensurate, the value of someone living according to their faith with how much money you’re spending, and that’s why I sort of dislike this new standard.

 

But I would also like to just say a few words about the Establishment Clause. Now, I know that when people hear “Establishment Clause,” it causes a lot of people’s eyes to roll. Right? There’s those neurotic atheists getting traumatized about seeing a Christmas tree again. [Laughter] And there’s no doubt that, even as someone who is somewhat sympathetic to Establishment Clause claims, there have been some excesses over the years. And in fact, the claim in Hardison that my colleague alluded to was one of those. The argument was made that any statute that required religious accommodations had the effect of advancing religious, which is one of the three prongs of Lemon and, therefore, was unconstitutional.

 

So I do not mourn the death of Lemon. Almost no one does. But that doesn’t mean that Establishment Clause claims always lose. It’s still there in the Constitution. It still does mean something. We all know the boy who calls -- cries wolf parable. When I was a kid, at the end of parable, the wolf actually ate the boy. I’m told by my son that now in school they actually just see the wolf and then go home, which, I think, this is the point of the parable -- but anyway, it’s a gentler era today.

 

But anyway, sometimes, eventually, after a lot of reclaims, you get a stronger one, and I think that under an interpretation of Title VII that requires public employers to essentially hire a new person and spend money out-of-pocket to accommodate religious belief, I think that’s presents an Establishment Clause problem, not under Lemon, not under the living Constitution, but under the dead Constitution, the 1787 Constitution. And just thinking this through, so Justice Thomas, for instance, has offered a persuasive case that the Establishment Clause shouldn’t be incorporated against the states. But this is a federal statute, so that’s not an issue at all here.

 

Number two, there’s many arguments that have been made that the Establishment Clause applies a coercion standard. Having hurt feelings about seeing someone praying is not an Establishment Clause violation. I accept that. But there’s definitely coercion in Title VII as applied to private employers. The government is saying, “If you don’t pay money out-of-pocket to hire this new person, you are punished. You pay fines. The EOC is going after you.” That’s coercive.

 

I bet some people in this room probably don’t like Bostock. Bostock is definitely coercive. It’s forcing employers to do certain things. Well, so is Title VII as applied to religious employees as well. Then, there’s a question of spending. Right? There’s many Supreme Court cases that say that you can tax people as long as the money’s spent neutrally, if it’s spent on both religious and nonreligious institutions in neutral terms. But Title VII definitely doesn’t do that under an interpretation in which employers must earmark funds specifically for purposes of religious believers.

 

And finally, one more word about history and tradition, let’s face it. All of us in this room determine history and tradition on Wikipedia. If you look on Wikipedia and you research this for a few minutes --

 

Hon. S. Kyle Duncan:  Not me.

 

Mr. Adam Unikowsky:  -- you are not going to find examples of old statutes from the early republic imposing -- sort of requiring employers to spend money to advance religious practice in this way. You’ll definitely find examples of things like legislative prayer and displays of religious symbols and things like that that were struck down during the period Lemon was alive, but laws like -- under interpretation of Title VII, a law that would impose this sort of coercive spending requirement on employers, I don’t think you would have seen that. And that’s why I’m skeptical of a very broad understanding of substantial costs. Thank you.

 

Hon. S. Kyle Duncan:  Thank you, Adam. [Applause] Well, I’ve been a bad moderator, and I’ve let the panelists run on, but -- and I take the same approach to oral argument time, by the way, on the Fifth Circuit, if you’re ever there. But I was just so entranced with what everyone was saying. It was so good. And so, I will risk letting people respond because I know there’s lots to say. And so, take it away, Erin.

 

Ms. Erin M. Hawley:  I will be brief. So just two -- a couple of counterpoints. First, as to Stewart, there’s no dispute --

 

Hon. S. Kyle Duncan:  This is “Stewart.”

 

Ms. Erin M. Hawley:  Yes, “Stewart.” I actually think “Stewart” is “Stewart.” The question is whether “Mike” is “Mike.”

 

Hon. S. Kyle Duncan:  I see.

 

Ms. Erin M. Hawley:  But as to Stewart and Mike, there’s no question that Lorie received that email from an outside source. There’s also no question that she would have put herself in peril had she investigated that claim. Again, just look at Jack Phillips down the road, and Jack Phillips is relevant to my second response as well.

 

Professor Eskridge recommended, I think, something good here that maybe the Commission take a look at its own statute. We would be delighted if the Commission and the Colorado courts would look closely at CADA because Professor Eskridge is correct. CADA says the discrimination has to be because of a protected characteristic, but in the third iteration of Masterpiece Cakeshop, after the state has yet, once again, gone after Jack Phillips and then, when that case got kicked, been sued in civil court under the same statute, the trial court found two critical things as finding of fact. The trial court found that a gender transition cake was inherently expressive. It was celebrating a gender transition. The trial court also found that it was message-based and that Mr. Phillips would not make that cake for anyone. Despite finding both of those things, the trial court found that this violated CADA. So I love Professor Eskridge’s recommendation, but the Colorado courts so far have closed that door.

 

The last thing I’ll say, to take a shot at our alma mater, law might be malleable at Yale, but to quote a Harvard law professor, who’re we’re all familiar with, Justice Kagan, there is value in drawing lines, especially when you’re talking about the First Amendment. Line drawing is a part of every free speech case. The question is whether something is speech or not. That’s something that is not unique to this context. And she makes the really good point that if you don’t evaluate that, if you don’t draw lines and determine whether something is speech and protected or whether something is conduct and not protected, then you are going to allow the government to do precisely what Colorado sought to do here, and that is to silence someone based upon their viewpoint or to compel them to speak contrary to their conscience. [Applause]

 

Hon. S. Kyle Duncan:  Please and then you go ahead. Say whatever you like, and I have a follow up.

 

Prof. William Eskridge:  Oh, whatever I like, okay. Stewart -- I appreciate Ms. Smith’s position, but if you put it in a Supreme Court brief, I think the lawyers need to figure out whether Stewart was really someone who was going to complain. And the fact of the matter is that he was not. I think we’re actually in agreement. I would go further than you, though, Professor. I do think that Colorado needs to pay careful attention to its statute. But I also think two further things, and that is that civil rights commissions need to take very seriously their conciliation duties and their duties not to go hog wild on remedies.

 

It does seem to me this relates to the discussion you all are having, that you should not impose substantial costs on small businesses that are doing it on principle, even if you think the principle does violate the statute and is not protected by the First Amendment. I think it’s egregious the remedies that are sometimes issued against small business people. And I also do think that legislatures, unfortunately -- I think the Colorado legislature, the Congress, etc. ought to revisit some of these statutes. The Gorsuch opinion has an implicit criticism that maybe public accommodations ought not to be so broadly defined. Well, okay. I think that’s worthy of legislative consideration, particularly in light of some these cases. I think remedies need to be maybe more tailored, and the legislature can certainly send signals through revisiting the statute.

 

And frankly, let me cite a church, the Church of Jesus Christ of Latter-day Saints. I don’t know if we have a lot of Latter-day Saints in the audience. One of the great statutes passed in the last ten years is the Fairness for All statute that Utah passed in 2015, expanding their anti-discrimination laws, not in public accommodations but for employment and housing, and creating religious allowances by statute, such as we see in Title VII already.

 

Now, finally, I do believe that the Yale people are in one mind about drawing lines. Yes. I’m with the Professor on drawing lines. I would draw lines the way precedent draws lines, and that is there’s no Supreme Court case where the Supreme Court has held that sales, advertisements, sales talk, etc. is protected by the First Amendment against anti-discrimination laws in a blanket or broad way. That’s the holding -- that is the holding of Piggie Park. It’s the holding, I think, of Runyon v. McCrary as well, which I didn’t mention, and probably of Heart of Atlanta, too, and maybe McClung. So it’s a holding of a whole variety of cases, and it’s different from these other cases.

 

And I might add that we go back to Barnette, and I -- 1943 or thereabouts, 1940s, sometime -- when Barnette was decided, the First Amendment gave no protection to commercial speech. You want to talk about a living Constitution. That’s the living Constitution. And y’all, y’all, many originalists out there, can you raise your hand, originalists? Huh? Why don’t you read the Gorsuch opinion and see how much original public meaning evidence he adduces for his ultimate holding? I’ll tell you what. The short answer is pretty much none; although, I think he does wave at the original meaning of the First Amendment and certainly the text of the First Amendment.

 

But remember, speech is contradisposed toward conduct and status, and the First Amendment original public meaning — it cites Madison, if I remember correctly, but don’t quite on point. The main on point stuff that he relies on are Supreme Court precedents, mainly precedents in the last, say, 60 or 70 years, so this is truly a living Constitution. But it’s a living Constitution that, I think, draws the lines in a really odd way.

 

Hon. S. Kyle Duncan:  Thank you, Professor. If I may, I was going to follow up on the Piggie Park point. I thought the edgiest thing that Professor Eskridge said, and that Justice Sotomayor says in her dissent, is that this opens the door to overruling a case like that. Do you have a view on that? Do you want to say anything to that, or -- well, actually, well, you said something already, and that’s good.

 

Prof. William Eskridge: Oh, okay. But both of us?

 

Hon. S. Kyle Duncan:  But did Erin have a -- I didn’t think you responded to that, or did you?

 

Ms. Erin M. Hawley:  So no. Absolutely not. I think that the majority goes out of its way in four or five places to talk about how this is about speech. It is about -- it’s not about a sale. And I think if we’re going to talk about original meaning, I think that there’s no case throughout the history, certainly none that were offered by Colorado, that allows a government to compel someone to speak contrary to their belief. That’s just something that has not happened until recent times. And for that reason, I think Piggie Park, Runyon, all of these cases, Heart of Atlanta are absolutely distinguishable.

 

Prof. William Eskridge:  I would disagree on the line drawing there. There are many cases where the Supreme Court has upheld government compelling you to speak against your belief. Many of them are liable cases. You might really believe something that is untrue and libelous, but you are going to be held accountable for that. Fraud, this is sales. A lot of people, the best fraudsters — we see this in politics, don’t we — the best fraudsters are the ones who actually believe their own fraudulent claims. That can be held liable, based upon the First Amendment.

 

And moreover, until the 1970s and really much more the ‘90s and the new millennium, you could say all sorts of things you believed in in commercial speech, and the state could prohibit it and still can prohibit a lot of that stuff, like if you try to sell a drug that actually harmful, but you believe it’s not. You can be held liable for that. Now, in Piggie Park — I think we’re at one — of course, they’re not going to overrule Piggie Park. Is it because of principle? No. Piggie Park was a speech case. It was a case just as sincere as Lorie Smith, morally, not as admirable but just as sincere.

 

I wrote a whole article on this — I’ll give you a copy — called “Noah’s Curse,” which does document religious -- either one of you can have it -- [laughter] religious -- no, the faith tradition.

 

Hon. S. Kyle Duncan:  This is a real article?

 

Prof. William Eskridge:  That’s a real article.

 

Hon. S. Kyle Duncan:  Kind of like Stewart.

 

Prof. William Eskridge:  No, it’s a real article that -- I’m a Presbyterian. My own denomination, Southern Presbyterians, in the 19th century, believed that the word of the Lord required racial segregation and required barring interracial marriages. And many religions continued to believe that through much of the 20th century, though that’s been muted, I think, since the civil rights laws of the ‘60s.

 

Hon. S. Kyle Duncan:  You’re a Southern Presbyterian, and you are from the South, I would guess, by your accent.

 

Prof. William Eskridge:  Yes and yes.

 

Hon. S. Kyle Duncan:  Where are you from?

 

Prof. William Eskridge:  Well, West Virginia --

 

Hon. S. Kyle Duncan:  We’ll see --

 

Prof. William Eskridge:  -- which many of you all would not consider true South, but we were South.

 

Hon. S. Kyle Duncan:  Well, I’m from South Louisiana, so I consider -- I would consider you a Yankee, but --

 

Prof. William Eskridge:  Well, if you want to call me names. If you call me names, I will -- Jesus Christ taught us; I will turn the other cheek.

 

Hon. S. Kyle Duncan:  I will -- and with that, it is refreshing that Yale would hire someone who points his finger at people and says, “Y’all.” So I’m grateful for that.

 

Prof. William Eskridge:  Y’all, y’all, [inaudible 01:25:14. But they’re not going to overrule Piggie Park because it’s a race case, and remember my point is that it is completely flippable. If you want to emphasize the status and conduct, then you uphold Piggie Park. If you want to emphasize the message, then you don’t. And the racism, or however you want to term it, message in Piggie Park is unacceptable — and you can legally launder that in a lot of different ways — but it’s unacceptable today. But it’s not unacceptable to harbor anti-gay things. Right?

 

Hon. S. Kyle Duncan:  If Professor Eskridge were in my court, I would have given him a lot of extra argument time, and you used your time well. Let me let Aaron, if you have any -- and Adam, if you have any final comments. I must say I was intrigued by Adam’s suggestion of -- about the Establishment Clause from the -- from a, I guess, a certain interpretation of the undue hardship. I don’t know if you want to speak to that or anything else.

 

Mr. Aaron Streett:  Yeah. Yeah. I appreciated Adam’s thoughtful comments on that, too, and I think one way to look at this is -- I think Adam raises good questions about whether hiring an additional employee or assigning someone to work a shift he doesn’t want to work would violate the -- would be an undue hardship on the statute. I don’t think there would be a bright-line rule either way on that, but I think one thing has to be clear is that it doesn’t violate the Establishment Clause because we already have the Family and Medical Leave Act. We already have the Americans with Disabilities Act. We already have the Pregnant Workers Fairness Act, which results in -- just think. If somebody takes off 12 weeks of work, the employer has to hire somebody to cover those 12 weeks. The employer has to hire someone to do the work that the -- if a pregnant woman is doing heavy labor, then somebody has to cover that undesirable shift. So it cannot be a violation of the Establishment Clause to treat religion on par with other protected characteristics under the statute.

 

The only other point I would very briefly make is on whether these are going to lead to sort to unreasonable demands and a lot of lawsuits. I think so many of this -- these questions will be resolved on the question of what is a reasonable accommodation, the other prong. And the courts have said a reasonable accommodation is not the employee’s preferred accommodation. It doesn’t mean that the religious person gets to give all the undesirable shifts to the nonreligious people. Mr. Groff said, “I’ll work every single Saturday. I’ll work double shifts during the week. I’ll work every single holiday that’s not on a Sunday.” And that was a reasonable accommodation.

 

You might end up working the graveyard shift you don’t like. You’re not going to get to dump all the unfavorable shifts. What it's going to lead to, I believe -- having the proper standard in the statute, is not going to lead to a lot more lawsuits. Hopefully, it will lead to more employers and employees sitting down and working something out, which is the process that already happens under the ADA and other statutes but has been absent because of Hardison’s misinterpretation of the statute.

 

Hon. S. Kyle Duncan:  Adam, you’ve reserved 30 seconds for rebuttal.

 

Mr. Adam Unikowsky:  I think I’ll yield my time. [Laughter] Thank you.

 

Hon. S. Kyle Duncan:  Well, I would -- first of all, I want everyone to join in thanking this wonderful panel. [Applause]

 

Prof. William Eskridge:  Well, and everybody, thank the Judge for his most genial -- he was a moderator. He was a genial moderator, even though he did call one of the panelists names.

 

Hon. S. Kyle Duncan:  A Yankee. Oh, yes. I’m sorry about that.

 

Prof. William Eskridge:  It was a good fight.

 

 

Hon. S. Kyle Duncan:  That’s all right. Well, so, I have some announcements. First, the CLE thing that was announced at the beginning, same announcement as at the beginning. Second, this is more important. If you have tickets for the Antonin Scalia Memorial Dinner, this a brief reminder that we are at a new location this year, the Washington Hilton. Shuttle buses to the Hilton will be available starting at 5:15, which is in 15 minutes, and running to 6:30 p.m., running every 5 minutes. Pick-up will be on Desales Street on the side of the hotel. Further details concerning transportation are in your convention booklet or on the app. And with that, thank you for your attention. Bye, bye. 

6:00 p.m. - 7:00 p.m.
Madison Club Reception

2023 National Lawyers Convention

Washington Hilton
1919 Connecticut Avenue NW
Washington, DC 20009

Share

Description

(Ticketed event) Black Tie Optional

 
6:00 p.m. - 7:00 p.m.
Lawyers Convention Reception

2023 National Lawyers Convention

The Washington Hilton
1919 Connecticut Avenue NW
Washington, DC 20001

Share

Description

(Ticketed event) Black Tie Optional

 
7:00 p.m. - 10:00 p.m.
2023 Antonin Scalia Memorial Dinner

2023 National Lawyers Convention

The Washington Hilton
1919 Connecticut Ave NW
Washington, DC 20009

Share

Description

(Ticketed event) Black Tie Optional

10:00 p.m. - 11:00 p.m.
Closing Reception

2023 National Lawyers Convention

The Washington Hilton
1919 Connecticut Ave NW
Washington, DC 20009

Share

Description

Back to top
9:00 a.m. - 11:00 a.m.
Showcase Panel II: Whither Precedent?

2023 National Lawyers Convention

Topics: Constitution • Supreme Court
Grand Ballroom
The Mayflower Hotel
1127 Connecticut Avenue NW
Washington, DC 20006

Share

Event Video

Listen & Download

Description

No one maintains that the Court has always and forever been originalist in its orientation. By any definition of "originalism," there is a vast body of case law that does not conform to it.

How do and should modern originalists - and here one might specifically include lower-court judges who consider themselves originalist - handle this case law? Do non-originalist precedents count for nothing, no matter the expectations built upon them? If they count, how much do they count? Given the interconnectedness of the Constitution's provisions and structure, does it make sense to be "originalist" in some respects and some contexts but not others? Does originalism itself provide means to answer, or even address, these questions or does one necessarily have to step outside originalism to establish its relationship to precedent?

Featuring:

  • Prof. Tara Leigh Grove, Vinson & Elkins Chair in Law, University of Texas at Austin School of Law
  • Prof. Randy Kozel, Fritz Duda Family Professor of Law, University of Notre Dame Law School
  • Prof. Gary Lawson, William Fairfield Warren Distinguished Professor, Boston University School of Law
  • Prof. John O. McGinnis, George C. Dix Professor in Constitutional Law, Northwestern University Pritzker School of Law
  • Moderator: Hon. William H. Pryor Jr., United States Court of Appeals, Eleventh Circuit

Overflow: Chinese Room

Speakers

Event Transcript

Dean Reuter:  Good morning, everyone. I’m Dean Reuter, Senior Vice President and General Counsel of The Federalist Society, for those of you who don’t me. Thank you all for being here. You are the stalwarts that show up at 9:00 a.m. in the morning after the annual dinner. So thank you for being here.

I thought we had a great day yesterday, kept by a great night last night. And I’m so happy that it seems that very few of you went to Union Station last night. [Laughter] So I count that as an additional success. I have been asked about last night’s event, so I will tell you all at once the official count.

We had four justices of the Supreme Court in attendance last night—Justice Barrett, of course, but also Justices Gorsuch, Kavanaugh, and Alito. So the four justices were unable to issue any decisions, but they could have made a cert grant. So keep an eye out for the orders list.

Now, again, on logistics, if you’re using -- if you’re getting CLE, use the QR code to sign in this morning. Make sure you do that. Also, don’t miss the Rare Documents exhibit. I mentioned it yesterday on the second floor and enter the drawing. I’m not sure I was clear that there’s a drawing. The item I held up yesterday is the door prize.

It is a very handsomely framed page from a first edition Federalist Papers. So it’s quite something to have. And you need to go to the South Carolina room to see the documents and to enter for that. And just to reassure you, they didn’t destroy a first edition copy of the Federalist Papers. [Laughter] This was an edition that was beat up. It was compromised in a lot of ways. So what they did was salvage some pages and made these. There’s only four of them, so you can get up there and see those documents and enter yourself to win.

We have another great day planned today beginning with our panel discussion on precedent and originalism. But before we get to that, I want to mention the day’s events. We have five book signings that might not be clear in the program later this morning—I think just after this panel—on the Mezzanine level. If you haven’t been to the Mezzanine level, it’s a nice, less-crowded place you can go to. There’s coffee up there. There’s electricity up there. You can charge your phones and your laptops.

And then after a flurry of breakout panels all day long and another fireside chat and a special session on natural law, we’re going to finish the day with Bari Weiss as she delivers the Olsen lecture.

Now, I’m honored to introduce the moderator of our Showcase Panel on Precedent. Judge Pryor has served on the Eleventh Circuit Court of Appeals for some 20 years now. In clerk years, that’s 80 years, meaning he has mentored -- I’ve just coined that notion. But he has mentored and credentialed and brought along a clerk family of 80 men and women—quite a legacy in and of itself.

But before taking the bench, he served as Alabama’s attorney general, where, among other things, he founded and led RAGA, which has become a check on federal power and an enforcer of the rule of law. I could say much, much more about Bill Pryor, but I’ll close with one note.

Internally at The Federalist Society, when I’m trying to find a special speaker or a special guest or someone special to fill a slot, I think in terms of somebody who is of The Federalist Society—the inner, inner circle—a face or a name you think of or I think of when you think of The Federalist Society. Judge Pryor is surely of The Federalist Society. He founded nearly every Alabama chapter of The Federalist Society—student or lawyer chapter—and he is so ingrained and integral to the organization. He’s a part of the organization’s DNA. So I’m very proud to welcome him today, Judge Pryor.

[Applause]

Hon. William H. Pryor Jr.:  Good morning. Thank you, Dean, for that kind introduction. I thought that you had perhaps scheduled me to be the moderator this morning, the morning after the dinner, because you wanted something a little rambunctious from me this year than in contrast with last year. [Laughter] Our topic this morning is “Wither Precedent?”

No one maintains that the Supreme Court has always and forever been originalist in its orientation. By any definition of “originalism,” there is a vast body of case law that does not conform to it.

How do and should modern originalists—including inferior court judges who consider themselves originalists—handle this case law? Do non-originalist precedents count for nothing, no matter the expectation built upon them? If they count, how much do they count? In the light of the structure of the Constitution, does it make sense to be originalist in some respects and some contexts but not others? Does originalism itself provide means to answer or even address these questions, or does one necessarily have to step outside originalism to establish its relationship to precedent?

To discuss these questions, The Federalist Society, as usual, has assembled a distinguished panel of scholars. I will introduce each of them in the order in which they will speak. Each of them will speak, give or less, around 10 minutes, maybe a little more. We have ample time before we open it up.

Our first speaker, Randy Kozel, is an Associate Dean and Professor of Law at the University of Notre Dame. There’s been a Notre Dame takeover this week. It’s so quaint. They think they still play football there.

[Laughter]

Hon. William H. Pryor Jr.:  He also directs the Notre Dame program on constitutional structure. His book, Settled Versus Right: A Theory of Precedent, makes the case for using precedent to bridge interpretive disagreements. Professor Kozel received his JD magna cum laude, from Harvard Law School, where he was the Article Committee Chair of the Harvard Law Review. He served as a law clerk to Justice Anthony Kennedy on the Supreme Court and as a clerk to Judge Kozinski on the United States Court of Appeals for the Ninth Circuit.

Gary Lawson is the Philip S. Beck Professor of Law at Boston University School of Law and, importantly, the Secretary of the Board of Directors of The Federalist Society—one of its founders. He previously taught at Northwestern University Pritzker School of Law. Professor Lawson is a graduate of Claremont McKenna College, and he received his JD from Yale Law School. He served as a law clerk to Justice Antonin Scalia—then Judge Antonin Scalia on the United States Court of Appeals for the District of Columbia—and then later as a law clerk for Justice Scalia on the Supreme Court.

John McGinnis is a Professor at Northwestern University Pritzker School of Law, where Professor Lawson previously taught. Professor McGinnis is a graduate of Harvard College and earned his JD from Harvard Law School, where he was an editor of the Harvard Law Review. He also has a Master of Arts degree from Balliol College, Oxford, in philosophy and theology.

Professor McGinnis served as a law clerk to Judge Ken Starr on the United States Court of Appeals for the District of Columbia Circuit. And from 1987 to 1991, he served as the Deputy Assistant Attorney General in the Office of Legal Counsel at the Department of Justice. He is the author of Accelerating Democracy: Transforming Government Through Technology and Originalism and the Good Constitution with Mike Rappaport. He is a past winner of the Paul Bator Award given by The Federalist Society to an outstanding academic under the age of 40.

Last but not least is Professor Tara Grove, the Vinson & Elkins Chair in Law at the University of Texas School of Law. I have to pay my respects. They do play football again.

[Laughter]

Hon. William H. Pryor Jr.:  She graduated summa cum laude from Duke University, and she earned her JD magna cum laude from Harvard Law School, where she served as the Supreme Court Chair of the Harvard Law Review. Professor Grove clerked for Judge Emilio Garza on the United States Court of Appeals for the Fifth Circuit, where I started my career, and then spent four years as an attorney for the Department of Justice Civil Division Appellate Staff. She is a coauthor of Low and Jeffries’s Federal Courts and the Law of Federal State Relations, and she’s served as the Chair of the Federal Court Section of the Association of American Law Schools. She, too, previously received the Paul Bator Award. Dean Kozel.

[Applause]

Prof. Randy Kozel:  Thank you, Judge. Let the record show I made it almost to 9:15 a.m. before I suffered the first insult of Notre Dame football today. [Laughter] But there is no doctrine of precedent in college football, so next year is a brand new year. I thank you all for being here. Home in South Bend, I always teach on Friday mornings in part because the people who opt in on Friday mornings are a special breed and such a dedicated lot. So thanks for being here today.

This morning, I’ll be arguing that originalism goes hand-in-hand with deference to precedent and the doctrine of stare decisis. Even more than that, I’ll argue that stare decisis strengthens the case for originalism by promoting ideals of stability and personality and constraint within an originalist framework. And I’m also going to argue that we ought to be skeptical of any account of originalism that squeezes out stare decisis, not only because of the potential for disruption, but also due to the long line of justices and constitutional thinkers who have described precedent as a legitimate and valuable part of the judicial process.

Since I’ll be talking about the virtues of precedent, I suppose it’s only fitting that I’m going to start by looking backward to October 24, 1989. On that day, Case Western Reserve University hosted a distinguished lecture, and the speaker was Justice Scalia. He took aim at a variety of legal clichés. “Too often,” the justice explained, “the wisdom of legal aphorisms can’t keep pace with their prominence.”

Most relevant to the topic of today’s panel, Justice Scalia challenged Ralph Waldo Emerson’s famous line of, “Foolish consistency is the hobgoblin of little minds.” Justice Scalia didn’t criticize Emerson per se. As the justice put it, “I think it generally sound policy to leave poets alone if they leave you alone.”

[Laughter]

Prof. Randy Kozel:  But his objection was to Emerson’s attack on consistency because, as Justice Scalia noted, consistency is an ideal that resides at the core of both law and logic. In the legal world, consistency is made manifest through the doctrine of stare decisis. Stare decisis is equal parts legal rule and judicial mindset. At the most basic level, it urges judges to let things remain settled instead of constantly rewriting the rules and rehashing the past.

We’re here today to talk about originalism and particularly the weekend’s broader theme of “originalism on the ground.” So the big question is whether originalism has room for stare decisis. And I think the answer is yes. The two are compatible—more than compatible, actually, because stare decisis dramatically improves the case for originalism on the ground. That’s the point Justice Scalia made when he laid out his originalist philosophy in a matter of interpretation. He described stare decisis as crucial to prevent originalism from being so disruptive of the established state of things that it loses much of its utility.

To my mind, the justice had it right about the role of precedent. And it’s not just about making originalism palatable. It’s about making originalism functional. So I start from the premise that in a democratic system that protects basic liberties and promotes human flourishing—in other words, in a country like the U.S.—any legal theory that would lead to massive upheaval has a big problem on its hands. But that’s just my inclination. That doesn’t have analytical bite.

The legal case for stare decisis begins with history and the fact that precedent-based decision making was a familiar part of the case deciding function as the Founding generation knew it. Consider Madison’s recognition that the good of society requires that the rules of conduct should be certain and known. “That wouldn’t be the case,” Madison observed, “if any judge disregarding the decision of his predecessors should vary the rule of law according to his individual interpretations of it.”

Or consider Federalist 78, where Hamilton emphasized that judges should be bound down by strict rules and precedents in order to fend off what he called an arbitrary discretion. Federalist 78 was among the sources Justice Kavanaugh cited three years ago to support his claim that the Framers understood the doctrine of stare decisis as part of the judicial power rooted in Article III, giving it a firm constitutional basis.

Even apart from that sort of textual argument, it strikes me as a solid inference that federal judges, including Supreme Court justices, may lawfully defer to precedent as a way of bringing stability, continuity, and coherence to the interpretation of a charter that’s specific and exact in some ways but open to debate in many others. Of course, there’s no fully defined doctrine of stare decisis hiding in the Constitution any more than there’s a treasure map in the back of the Declaration of Independence. Instead, the Constitution permits federal judges to create and apply and debate about the law of precedent, which is what they’ve been doing for years and what they continue to do today.

Now, there’s a notable counterpoint to this understanding. It comes from Justice Thomas’s 2019 concurrence in a case called Gamble v. United States. Drawing on scholarly work, including a brilliant and way ahead of its Time article by my co-panelist Gary Lawson, Justice Thomas described stare decisis as intention with the superiority of the Constitution over other sources of law.

He argued that the judicial power doesn’t authorize a Supreme Court justice to elevate mistaken precedents over the Constitution itself. Rather, the Supreme Court is constitutionally forbidden from deferring to precedents that are, as Justice Thomas put it, demonstrably erroneous. For him, stare decisis is lawful only in one set of circumstances: when the traditional tools of legal interpretation reveal that precedent, while incorrect, nevertheless adopted a textually permissible interpretation.

The sweep of this position depends on how we define its key terms. The most salient question is what it means for a precedent to be demonstrably erroneous as opposed to textually permissible but still wrong. We need to know what confidence level equates to demonstrable error, and we need to know why, when that confidence level isn’t met, it’s okay for the judge to defer to precedent instead of offering his best interpretation of the law, irrespective of what prior courts have said. So we’ve got some work to do before we can put it all into practice.

There’s another step, too, because the concept of demonstrable error doesn’t exist in a vacuum. According to Justice Thomas, courts need to assess whether an error is demonstrable using the “traditional tools of legal interpretation.” That, I submit, is the whole ballgame because if traditional tools of legal interpretation is another way of saying “originalism”—which certainly seems to be the case based on the concurrence in Gamble v. United States—then every non-originalist precedent that reaches a non-originalist result is guilty of demonstrable error, which means every non-originalist precedent that reaches a non-originalist result not only may be overruled but must be overruled no matter how deeply it’s entrenched and no matter how much reliance it’s commanded.

It might well be that an unbroken pattern of originalist interpretation going back to the Founding would have been the best of all possible worlds. But in our actual constitutional system where non-originalist precedents play leading roles in shaping the freedom of speech, the rules of criminal procedure, the extent of federal power, and beyond, we need to worry about disruption and instability if all those precedents are up for grabs. Plus, as I’ve suggested, I think Justice Thomas’ structural argument for the unlawfulness of stare decisis ultimately has too much going against it. Here’s why.

When we put together the history of precedent-based decision making, the familiarity of the Founding generation with that practice, prominent Founders depictions of precedent as part of the judicial process, the fact that from the moment of its ratification, the Constitution contained a host of uncertainties that would need to be worked out and solidified through processes including judicial interpretation and the absence of any language indicating that the Constitution takes the unusual step of excluding stare decisis from the judicial power or the case-deciding function, I can’t help but to conclude that stare decisis has a role to play.

I take heart in the fact that the Supreme Court sees it that way, too. Over the years, justices who tend to interpret the Constitution very differently from one another have found common ground in the legitimacy of stare decisis. That remains true up to the present. Even in a landmark case like Dobbs, the majority describes stare decisis not just as constitutionally legitimate but as promoting the consistency and integrity of what judges do. The idea that, over the years, so many justices have been wrong about the lawfulness of stare decisis is an aggressive claim. The bar for proving that case ought to be awfully high, and I just don’t think the text and structure of the Constitution get us there.

Now, accepting stare decisis doesn’t mean freezing every constitutional mistake for eternity. That’s where the doctrine does its essential work and separating the mistakes we can live with from the mistakes we can’t. Just as generations of judges have recognized the lawfulness of stare decisis, those same judges have acknowledged the validity of departing from precedent under certain circumstances. The essential step is making sure judges don’t flex their overruling muscles every time they come upon a dubious opinion, particularly if “dubious” refers to all opinions that reflect methodological commitments different from one’s own.

So what should judges—including originalist judges—look at when deciding whether to revisit precedent? For starters, they should ask whether the external world has changed in a way that undermines the precedent’s factual predicates. Likewise, they should ask whether the precedent’s rule of decision has been procedurally unworkable and reliance interests are significant as well.

Apart from those sorts of considerations, the best reason to revisit a precedent isn’t its interpretive methodology but its substantive impact—its impact on the ground, we might say. There’s a corollary. If a precedent’s real world effects aren’t too bad, there’s much less need to reconsider it, even if you think it’s likely wrong, and even if its reasoning is decidedly non-originalist.

The point here is that originalist judges—like all judges—need to be careful about how many errors they characterize as so grave as to demand overruling, which means it can’t be the case that every non-originalist precedent is exceptionally harmful. And the same goes for a non-originalist court in its handling of originalist precedents.

If I may, I’d like to return to Justice Scalia one last time before I close. “One should assuredly not,” Justice Scalia observed, “shrink from changing his views when persuaded that they are wrong. The problem,” he pointed out, “is with the judge who finds himself repeatedly in that situation.” In my view, what is true of judges as individuals is equally true of courts as institutions.

There’s nothing at all objectionable about a court that reconsiders its prior decisions from time to time. But those departures should occur within a stable legal framework and one that recognizes the court as an enduring institution committed to durable principles that transcend the current moment. Thank you.

[Applause]

Prof. Gary Lawson:  As Randy just said, about 30 years ago, I had a really crazy thought. What if we take the argument for judicial review and we substitute judicial decisions for statutes in the form of the argument? Does that mean courts always have to prefer the Constitution to prior decisions the way they have to prefer it to statutes? Does that mean precedent is therefore categorically unconstitutional? That’s just nuts, I thought. The problem is, I couldn’t figure out why it was nuts.

So this was a time when I was pretty heavily involved in designing Federalist Society conference programs. So I put myself on a program. I structured a panel around me. [Laughter] This is true. And I picked out the three people in the country who I thought would have the best chance of explaining to me while I was wrong. One of them actually is with us this weekend—might even be in the audience. Oh, here he is. And to my amazement, all of them said yes. And it was a phenomenal panel. It was everything I could have hoped for, except that at the end of it, I still couldn’t figure out why it was nuts.

So three decades later—still crazy after all these years, oh, still crazy after all these years—how did I end up in this state? Well, let’s go back to the case for judicial review. Both houses of Congress pass a bill. It goes to the president. The president signs it. It’s now a law. Article I, Section 7, Clause 2 specifically defines it as a law—can’t get any more law than that. And let’s just suppose that that statute—that constitutionally defined law—pretty conclusively resolves a dispute between parties, and one of the parties who’s going to win takes it into court. What is the court supposed to do?

The court’s job is to decide cases according to governing law. The party says, “Here’s the governing law. The Constitution defines it as a law. Give me my verdict.” And the other side says, “Well, wait, wait. Not so fast. That Article I, Section 7, Clause 2 statute is unconstitutional.”

Well, now what? I mean, the statute is law. The Constitution has specifically defined it as law. More than that, the statute is a precedent. Actually, it’s multiple precedents because prior constitutional interpreters—at least three: the House, the Senate, and the president—have all independently determined that that is, in fact, constitutional. They are charged by oath and by implication from their grants of powers with making constitutional judgments. So we have not one precedent, but three.

Does that combination of law plus precedent mean you have to give effect to the statute? Well, as we all know, the answer to this come down to us is, no, not necessarily. And while Marbury v. Madison is wrong about a lot of things, it’s not wrong about this. And here is why. Because not only is that statute defined as law, the Constitution also defines itself as law—along with statutes and treaties—even defines itself as supreme law over other competing sources, like state constitutions and statutes.

And then there’s the inferential move of Marbury, which I think is correct, that even within that group of supreme law sources, there’s something special about the Constitution. It is hierarchically superior to other claimed sources of law, statutes, treaties, the law of nations—also mentioned in the Constitution—common law, state constitution’s statutes. The Constitution just is the trump card, the ace of trumps, right?

Well, wait a minute. Maybe what we can say is that the Article I, Section 7, Clause 2 status of that statute at least creates a presumption in favor of its constitutionality, some kind of legal force—not necessarily conclusive, but still non-zero. And there’s a very venerable tradition of this expressed perhaps most clearly by James Bradley Thayer in his rule of clear mistake. Today, we know it as several other names: the presumption of constitutionality or, to older generations, judicial restraint.

But here’s the thing. I don’t think you can get that rule out of the Constitution itself. And, in fact, when Thayer a century ago came up with this, he came up with it not out of interpreting the Constitution, but out of anti-constitutional reasoning. His problem was that courts were behaving too much like lawyers and deciding things. And yeah, if you actually behave like a lawyer, you’re going to reach these conclusions that these things are unconstitutional.

Now, courts are supposed to be statesmen. I don’t think that’s true. I don’t think Article III is a statesman article. I think it’s a law article. So I’m not sure you can get that presumption of constitutionality out of Article III. Wouldn’t it make the job of judges easier if they could defer to some extent to the prior decisions of Congresses and presidents? Well, of course it would. This is why deference doctrines get created by courts all the time. The problem, again, is courts swear an oath to uphold the Constitution, not an oath to make their jobs easier. So I don’t think you can get that out of there either.

And finally, fourth, might not those prior decisions be good evidence of the right answer, something that a court should at least take account of because, well, maybe somebody else knows more than you do. And finally, here, we have that, of course, absolutely 100 percent. I don’t know that that is something that deserves the label of precedent because what that means is courts are supposed to figure out the right answer, and sometimes, good evidence of the right answer is what somebody else has come up with as the answer.

Now, is there any good systematic reason to think that congresses and presidents are, over the large course of things, likely to get the Constitution right? Suppose one could try to make an argument for that but seems like a hard case to make. All right.

So all of that’s just about judicial review. What does any of that have to do with this panel? Well, now, let’s go back to my problem from three decades ago. Take exactly the same argument—literally, the full structure—and just everywhere where I had Article I, Section 7, Clause 2 statute, take that out and put in judicial decision or, if you prefer, press release by a 26-year-old Ivy League law clerk. [Laughter]

Okay. What changes if we do this? Well, I think two things change. One is unlike Article I, Section 7, Clause 2 statutes, the Constitution doesn’t specifically define judicial decisions as law. Nonetheless, I do think they qualify. After all, Article III is not the judicial rambling clause. It’s the judicial power clause. And for judges to have power, there has to be some kind of legal effect to the things that they do. So I think that is sufficient to establish that judicial decisions, properly issued, do have a status of law. Presidents can execute them using the executive power. They certainly couldn’t do that if they weren’t law of sorts. So I do think we can get rid of that distinction.

The other distinction—and Randy mentioned this—is that Article III does speak of this thing called the judicial power. Could it be that part of the judicial Power just is the ability to prefer prior decisions of courts to the Constitution? I mean, there isn’t anything conceptually impossible about that. The Constitution is certainly capable of saying, “Oh, by the way, ignore me in these circumstances.” It’s not impossible.

The question is whether it does so. And that’s the problem I’ve had for three decades. I just can’t read those words “judicial power” in Article III as authorizing courts to treat their own decisions better than they treat state constitutions, state statutes, Article I, Section 7, Clause 2 statutes, the law of nations, and every other source of law that there is.

And I want to be very clear. I’m not saying judicial decisions are not law. They’re absolutely law of sorts. The question is whether they are law that is hierarchically superior to the law of the Constitution. And that’s a tough sell, right?

So does that mean all prior judicial decisions are of the same status as law review articles, op-eds, other things that might be of some interest as evidence of the right answer to constitutional questions? Well, it’s a little more complicated than that. So I’m going to give four qualifications to what I call the prima facie case against the constitutionality of the use of precedent. And they’re important qualifications. Randy touched on a couple of them.

One is, well, of course it’s possible—not only possible, but indeed, I believe, mandatory—to pay attention to prior decisions to see if maybe they do, in fact, constitute good evidence of the right answer. Sometimes, they will. Sometimes, they won’t. The mere fact that it’s a judicial decision doesn’t tell you anything. But if it’s a judicial decision written by really, really smart people who are using a method that you can count on as more or less reliable, yeah. Then there’s a decent chance that maybe they’ve come up with something that you haven’t.

So all judicial decisions are not created equal. Clarence Thomas and Antonin Scalia are not Harry Blackmun and Earl Warren. They’re just not. They’re not the same things. One is likely to be, all things considered, better evidence of the right answer than others simply because they’re asking different questions. One set is asking more or less the right questions than one. So it’s entirely possible to use precedents for what I call epistemological purposes. What does it tell you about what’s the right answer?

Second, there actually are some contexts where the seeming sweep of the lawsonian craziness does actually run into a wall. There are times when I think you actually can get out of judicial power certain circumstances where those opinions do have some measure of legal force, even against your best constitutional judgment.

In order for them to be exercises of the judicial power, they at least have to be binding on the parties to some extent. They have to be binding on the executive for enforcement to some extent. Otherwise, it’s an advisory opinion. So you can get things like law of the case. You can get res judicata. You can get any number of things that are specific to the judgment that do seem to have that kind of power.

More controversially, you might even be able to get a doctrine that says Judge Pryor does have to suck it up and follow Earl Warren and Harry Blackmun. Why? Because he is inferior to them, right? The Constitution says so. And if you try to parse what it means to be an inferior-to person in the context of the Constitution, this would be a whole other panel, a whole other talk. There’s a pretty good case that it means you’ve got to follow what they say, even if you are quite sure that they’re wrong.

All of which leads to number three, and this is one of the most important points that Randy meant. How sure, right? Anytime you’re making a judgment about what the law means—whether it’s a statute, the Constitution, or anything else—you’re implicitly adopting what I would call a standard of proof. You have to have in mind, “How confident do I need to be in this answer before I can say it’s right?” Sort of, “Yeah, okay. Seems okay” or, “I’m really confident” or, “I’m sure beyond a reasonable doubt,” the Constitution itself doesn’t seem to answer that question.

Is there an argument that the existence of precedents—and here, we can get into mechanics—does it have to be a long line of precedents? Does it have to be precedents from judges who you think are applying the right methods and so forth? But whatever universe you narrow down, is there a case for saying those precedents at least raise the confidence level that you need to have before you actually declare that there’s a conflict between those prior decisions and the Constitution? Because, after all, the loss and problem only arises.

The precedent says X, and the Constitution says Y. How do you determine that that the precedents say X, and how do you determine that the Constitution says Y? I mean, that’s actually a very, very serious question to which, as I say, I don’t think the Constitution provides a textualist answer. So there may be a ground on which Randy and I can join forces around that kind of problem of proof.

And then finally fourth—and then I’ll shut up for a while—everything I’ve just said is just about what I think the Constitution means, right? Most people in this room aren’t actually interested in what the Constitution means. I’m guessing that. What you’re interested in is how government officials are likely to behave and should behave. And it’s a natural assumption to think that if you know what the Constitution means, well, that tells you how government officials are supposed to behave. And over a large range, that’s probably a reasonable assumption. It’s not an inevitable one, right?

Notice what some of the considerations that Randy was invoking were consistency, stability, prosperity, things that make a society function. What if the Constitution is a botched job? To what extent do you, at some point, say, “Wow, okay. We’ll take it this far, but we actually have a society to run.” I’m actually not commenting on that. It may very well be that the practice of precedent offers all sorts of positive advantages that some people might think are more important than the meaning of the Constitution. I’m not here to argue that one way or the other. I’m just reading the thing and trying to figure out what I think it means.

And I do think it creates -- I mean, Randy says “high burden.” I think there is a prima facie case against the use of precedent, at least at the horizontal level, in constitutional cases. And, at that point, I think the burden shifts to others to come up with reasons why, in this particular circumstance, either the Constitution instructs us to ignore itself, or we choose to ignore it instead. And that’s still where I am. Sorry.

[Applause]

Prof. John O. McGinnis:  Originalism, I think, may now be the leading jurisprudence on the Supreme Court. Yet the Court’s many important—but I fear plainly—non-originalist precedents create a dilemma. If the Court overrules those precedents, it will, in some cases, impose enormous costs on those who relied on the statutes and rights that were believed to be constitutional. But if it leads them as good law, constitutional law will remain partially—perhaps only marginally—originalist.

Thus, I think this central question in some sense for what I would call “second-generation originalists”—when originalism, unlike when I went to law school, has become a real thing—is the question of precedent and originalism. The original justices themselves are now debating the appropriate rules for overturning precedent.

Justice Bret Kavanaugh has proposed a three-part test that would likely entrench much non-originalist precedent because it requires “special reasons for overruling cases.” Justice Clarence Thomas, in contrast, as we’ve heard, would overrule any precedent that is demonstrably erroneous under original meaning, but doing so would overrule some precedents that are indeed demonstrably erroneous but on which much of modern government is built, threatening chaos and upsetting settled expectations. I don’t think any court is likely to adopt his proposal.

So, in this talk, I want to propose two ways that Mike Rappaport and I propose to solve this dilemma of restoring originalism while protecting settled expectations and thus promote originalism on the ground. The first is prospective overruling.

Prospective overruling is a practice by which the Court would apply its ruling retroactively to past statutes and actions but only prospectively to future ones. The advantage of prospective overruling is that it allows the justices to respect past reliance where necessary while nevertheless moving the law decisively to the original meaning. Precedent rules should protect mistaken precedents when overturning them would impose enormous costs on society. But prospective overruling would allow the Court to apply mistaken precedent to the past, thus avoiding the imposition of such costs but still applying the original meaning for the future.

This kind of overruling avoids the problem of entrenching mistaken precedent because the Court needs no special reason for overruling it, as Justice Kavanaugh demands. But it also avoids the chaos of immediate overruling that Justice Thomas would cause. As an example, let’s assume that the original meaning requires a much stricter non-delegation doctrine. Prospective overruling would allow the Court to avoid upending the existing regulatory regime and thereby creating chaos. Agencies could continue to enforce their regulations in place, even if the statutes under which they have been promulgated violated the original meaning. Instead, the original meaning would apply only to future statutes, giving Congress time to pass tighter regulatory laws as needed and perhaps create new institutional procedures designed to streamline passage.

The most significant obstacle to our proposal is the fact that many originalists have never been comfortable with prospective overruling, just as Antonin Scalia, for instance, was an outspoken opponent. Scalia’s argument arose in the aftermath of the Warren Court, which itself used prospective overruling when it overruled precedents on the basis of living constitutionalism.

Scalia, of course, believed that many of those decisions violated the meaning of the Constitution, and we agree with him. Scalia thus, not surprisingly, argued against prospective overruling on the ground that it facilitated judicial activism. But that’s a policy argument, not an originalist argument. Moreover, today, prospective overruling should help the Court return to its original meaning. It will foster fidelity to the Constitution.

Now, Scalia’s most important legal argument is that prospective overruling is beyond the judicial power of Article III because judges must base their rulings on what the law is, not what it will be. But I think the stance creates a problem for Scalia precisely because he was an originalist, and, as Randy has pointed out, he also respected precedent. After all, the original meaning was the law. What allows him to follow precedent contrary to the original meaning? The justification must be that precedent rules, too, are the law, and that they permit judges to retain precedent in some circumstances, even if contrary to the original meaning.

I think that’s right. Precedent rules were well established common law rules that English courts, colonial courts, and federal courts in the early Republic applied. And they applied it even in cases of written law when they thought the previous decisions were demonstrably erroneous.

Scalia appears to accept the constitutional legitimacy of such rules. But if precedent rules are the law, then a judge may follow a precedent rule that permits prospective overruling. Scalia appears to argue that at the time of the Framing, justices did not engage in prospective overruling, and that, to my knowledge, is true. But there’s no reason to expect that there would have been prospective overruling in the early Republic. There were very few precedents, if any, to overrule, both because the Constitution was new and because, at that time, not just one decision, but only a series of decisions were required to create presidential force.

Moreover, the judges were more likely to have shared the values of those who wrote the Constitution, making non-originalists precedents much less likely than they are today. Thus, the absence of prospective overruling at the time of the Constitution does not suggest that common law rules should reject it under the circumstances of today. Courts can apply a new common law rule to new circumstances.

In the case of prospective overruling, two new circumstances justify the practice. One circumstance is that the Supreme Court and the law more generally now places a high value on the Constitution’s original meaning. We can discuss why it does. I think one of the more important reasons it does is we think that a continental consensus on what the -- creating the Constitution is likely to be a lot better than a 5-4 majority of judges, justices who live in the most artificial place in the United States—Washington, D.C. [Laughter] A second circumstance is that there are now so many non-originalist precedents on the books. We’re 200 years in. Together, these circumstances support a rule for prospective overruling.

Now, let me be clear. In some cases, the normal processes of overruling in which justices invalidate past statutes remains entirely appropriate. For instance, if independent agencies are unconstitutional, the Court should overrule prior precedent upholding them and declare them unconstitutional today. There are few reliance interests in independent agencies. Indeed, I think no one outside the beltway would notice if they disappeared.

We would also recommend another method of reconciling precedent with originalism, what we call “cutting back.” Undercutting back, the Court would partially overrule a non-originalist precedent by narrowing the scope of non-originalist holding. The narrowing would not fully return the law to its original meaning but would move it closer to the original meaning.

Like prospective overruling, cutting back also helps protect reliance interests while permitting a closer approximation of the Constitution’s original meaning. Even if replacing a non-originalist precedent with original meaning would impose enormous costs, sometimes, the Court can cut back the non-originalist precedent to move the law closer but not all the way to the original meaning without generating those costs.

Consider the Commerce Clause to show how this would work. The Court could overrule precedents that give Congress broad authority under the Commerce Clause to regulate non-economic matters, even if these matters had economic effects. This partial overruling would be somewhat similar to the Court’s action in The United States v. Lopez but would be both broader and more persuasive.

Under this overruling, the Court would define economic matters to exclude activities that did not involve a sale on the market, such as the actions at issue in Wickard v. Filburn or Gonzales v. Raich. Such a decision would be unlikely to create enormous costs. Overruling the precedents that permitted regulation of non-economic matters would cut back on the scope of the Commerce Clause under modern doctrine although would not return the clause to what many originalists believe was its original meaning. It would move us, though decisively back towards that meaning.

Our originalist approach to prospective overruling and cutting back has the advantage of creating a gradual, rule-based mechanism for returning to the original meaning. It would make it more likely that the Court would restore the original meaning of constitutional provisions while recognizing, in a kind of Berkeleyan sense, that a society comes to rely organically on non-originalist precedent.

Prospective overruling would also promote the constitutional amendment process where non-originalist precedents have come to be accepted—and I’m sure there have been some accepted by the nation. Prospective overruling would give time for social movements to arise to enact the principles underlying those precedents that are now widely supported. They could be enacted into the Constitution, and thus, prospective overruling would energize the people themselves to become once again the creators of our fundamental law.

I think it’s only through facilitating the Article V process that I think -- I fear has fallen into disuse, that we can fulfill a basic premise of the Constitution, and that is that in the United States, it’s we the people who rule, not we the judges.

[Applause]

Prof. Tara Leigh Grove:  All right, thanks so much. I’m going to switch gears a little bit. So far, we’ve been talking about horizontal precedent primarily, that is, the extent to which the Supreme Court can and should adhere to its own precedents.

I want to talk about something that Professor Lawson briefly touched on, and that is vertical precedent, that is, whether lower federal court judges have to obey Supreme Court precedent. And I think there’s a very strong argument that vertical precedent is not only constitutionally permissible but is constitutionally required, including on originalist grounds. And I actually think Gary Lawson will agree with me on this. So what’s the argument and what does it mean?

The basic argument comes from Article III. Article III says that the judicial power shall extend to one Supreme Court and such inferior courts as the Congress may from time to time ordain and establish. Article I, Section 8, Clause 9, also refers to inferior tribunals. What the U.S. Constitution does is establish that some -- one court is supreme and the other courts are inferior.

And many scholars have looked at this text as it was understood in 1787, 1789 and said, “The historical understanding is that the Constitution creates a hierarchical judiciary,” which means both of the inferior federal courts have to listen to what the Supreme Court says, and conversely, that the Supreme Court has a leading role in defining federal law for the federal judiciary.

And there is a surprising amount of agreement on this constitutional principle among both originalists and non-originalists. They come to it in a different way. But a lot of people agree there’s a hierarchical judiciary. And many of you might think, “Well, I never even thought of an alternative.” Okay. So then what does that mean?

Well, it certainly means that if a case goes to the Supreme Court from a lower federal court, the Supreme Court can reverse it. But it also means something more, that the U.S. Supreme Court can establish precedents, not just in the case before it, but for all those lower court cases the Supreme Court can no longer review.

We don’t often think about this, but when the Supreme Court first started out, it didn’t have the power of certiorari. It couldn’t pick and choose the cases that it heard. It had mandatory appellate jurisdiction in every single case. So it actually could, on a case-by-case basis, review what the lower federal courts did. But then, starting in the late nineteenth century and really kicking off in 1925 and 1988, gradually, the Supreme Court had discretionary review because it simply could not hear all of the cases from the lower federal courts.

Now, I will pause and say in the early twentieth century, the Supreme Court—which had only limited discretionary jurisdiction—could barely handle 500 cases per year, 500 cases per year. In the 1980s, they were deciding 150 cases per year on average. One wonders why they have the summers off [laughter].

Anyway, today they’re deciding only 70 or 80 cases per year and sometimes even 50 or 60 in recent terms. And so that means when the Supreme Court decides a case, it needs to set a precedent for all of those now hundreds of thousands of lower court cases that it cannot review on a case-by-case basis. Just imagine the world if Miranda only applied in Arizona or if McDonald—which purported to extend the Second Amendment to states and localities—had no application outside the city of Chicago? A very different world. And so we accept that the Supreme Court can establish precedents for the lower federal courts. But how should it do it?

I’ve referred to one thing a little bit. It’s actually arguably problematic under the constitutional scheme that we have if the Supreme Court decides cases on extraordinarily narrow grounds because it’s only deciding somewhere between 50 and 80 of the hundreds of thousands of cases that lower federal courts are hearing.

And when the Supreme Court decides cases on very narrow—often called “minimalist grounds”—the Supreme Court’s effectively delegating to the lower federal court’s enormous power to define the content of federal law with very limited guidance from the Supreme Court. So there’s at least a case to be made that minimalism itself is problematic at the Supreme Court.

But there’s also a case to be made that maybe the kinds of precedents the Supreme Court establishes matter. And here, I will say, even if one is an originalist and even if one believes the Supreme Court could be originalist, it may be problematic, as a practical matter, for the Supreme Court to just tell lower courts, “Go do originalism.”

And I’m going to point to one recent case that I think is arguably problematic along these lines, and that’s the recent Bruen decision on the Second Amendment. The Bruen decision certainly held that there is a broad individual right to bear arms. And then it said to lower courts, “Look. The government now has to identify some historical analog to justify its regulation.” So to justify a regulation today, you’ve got to look to something in the past that seems similar. Okay. Well, you can kind of see the argument.

But here’s what the Supreme Court didn’t say. It didn’t say when in history one should look: if one should look when the original Constitution was written and ratified in 1787, 1789, when the Bill of Rights was ratified in 1791. Are we supposed to look at the 1860s when the Fourteenth Amendment was added to the Constitution?

Bruen does not say -- and there is kind of a difference between the late eighteenth century and the late nineteenth century. Bruen does not tell lower courts what the level of generality is for determining what is a proper historical analog. And I think the Supreme Court right now is considering a case that raises these questions and may provide some clarity. But it certainly did not provide that clarity in Bruen.

Another problem with an analysis like Bruen, historical -- good historical inquiry takes time. It takes institutional resources. An institution with 9 members that hears only 50 to 80 cases per year and gets dozens upon dozens of amicus briefs to help it out might be able to conduct that originalist analysis and do a pretty good job. But lower courts—that don’t get the summers off—and have a much larger caseload than the U.S. Supreme Court, courts of appeals that have mandatory appellate jurisdiction and not certiorari power and do not get many—sometimes any—amicus briefs to help out, they may not have the institutional resources to conduct this kind of historical inquiry.

And the final thing that may be problematic about a decision like Bruen—again, not in terms of what it held, but what it told the lower courts to decide -- to do going forward—there’s always the possibility of some lower court resistance.

Now, I do believe that every lower federal court judge in this country believes deeply in our legal system, in our Constitution, and believes deeply in a system of hierarchical precedent. But I think we’ve all seen over the course of time, decisions that we might define to be right or wrong from the Supreme Court. And lower court judges feel the same way, right? They are a little reluctant to take some precedents all the way where the Supreme Court might want them to.

And so standards like strict scrutiny as opposed to rational-basis scrutiny really do provide guidance and also arguably rein in lower court judges that might not be too keen on applying a particular precedent. And what we have seen in the post-Bruen era are widely different lower court decisions, as they’re trying to come up with, “Which historical analog? When?” And one has to think that some of that might have to be -- might have to do with how the lower courts view Bruen itself. So the types of precedents matter in providing guidance.

Now, I do want to continue on with one thing. Are there some areas where the Supreme Court cannot establish precedent not only for itself but even for the lower courts, too? And here, I want to say a couple of words about methodological precedent. There’s a really strong assumption in our culture that every single judge can decide for himself or herself which methodology to apply.

There’s not a really good explanation for why this is the case, but the assumption seems to be that although some aspects of the judicial power apply to a court, other aspects of the judicial power actually apply to each individual judge. And one part of the judicial power, it seems, is to choose a methodology. And that would be true not only for each individual Supreme Court justice, but also every single individual lower federal court judge. This is kind of a mixed bag for originalism.

The lack of presidential status for methodology allowed Justice Scalia to start, basically, a methodological revolution in the 1980s, advocating originalism in constitutional interpretation, textualism in statutory interpretation, even though those methodologies were by no means ascendant or even recognized by the majority of the Supreme Court at the time.

But this also means that at a time like now when originalism is ascendant, that strongly limits its staying power because new methodologies can come along; new justices can come along; new lower court judges can come along and say, “Actually, we prefer something different.” The lower court judges will apply the precedents. Many members of the Supreme Court will also apply the precedents. But they’ll say, “Going forward, we want a new methodology.” And so the staying power of originalism may be quite limited.

But I want to say, on a positive side, that could be a good thing, not just to stick with the methodology because that’s how we’ve always done it, but continuously to question, try to improve, try to change, and try to re-justify the methodologies that we have chosen. If one believes that methodologies should be defended on normative grounds, that’s a very good thing for our legal system.

[Applause]

Hon. William H. Pryor Jr.:  Okay, fascinating discussion. I suspect that there are some panelists who would like to react and respond a bit to each other. So, Professor Dean Kozel?

Prof. Randy Kozel:  Sure. So I’ll just say very briefly, I think all of us have a lot of common ground in our discussion, and I love the points about vertical precedent. I think there’s a lot to discuss in terms of the scope of Supreme Court vertical precedent.

But one thing I’ll mention for now, going back to Gary’s comments—which were great as always—I suppose I just don’t see the issue of deferring the precedent as preferring precedent to the Constitution itself any more than I would see looking to the original history of a constitutional provision as preferring that original history to the Constitution itself. I guess I see it more as interpreting the Constitution in light of factors, including the text, including the structure, including the history, and including precedent. And I suppose I think of it this way.

Technically, you could interpret the First Amendment, say, without regard to the original meaning of the text—and in fact, the Supreme Court has done it for years. But it would take an awful lot to convince me that historical considerations were off the table for a judge who wanted to bring them to bear in thinking about the meaning of the First Amendment. And I suppose I think of precedent the same way.

You could interpret the First Amendment without regard to precedent, but I’d need to see an awful lot before I thought that a judge actually couldn’t make that decision, that the Constitution somehow took that away. So I think that’s where I come out.

Prof. Gary Lawson:  Well, I would agree with all of that. If all you’re doing with prior decisions is looking at them and using them as potential sources of guidance and wisdom on a case-specific basis, a hundred percent. I’m all in favor of that. My only issue is whether, as a matter of law, they acquire a certain force or status simply by virtue of being a prior decision rather than being good evidence of the right answer.

You can make categorical arguments that certain classes of judicial decisions are, by their nature, by certain features of them, especially likely to be good evidence of right answers. And I’m totally fine with that as well.

Prof. John O. McGinnis:  So I have two comments, one on Gary and the other on --

Hon. William H. Pryor Jr.:  Could you pull the mic a little closer?

Prof. John O. McGinnis:  I’m sorry. One on Gary and the other on Tara’s remarks. So I think one difference between Gary and me—and I think, in that sense, I’m along with Randy—is the way of interpreting the Constitution. The way I think of the way we should interpret the Constitution is the Constitution is not created ex nihilo but against a background of Anglo American jurisprudence.

And I think the practice of precedent was so well established. There’s nothing in the Constitution that seems to me to displace it. And the fact that there’s judicial review isn’t really different from England—and Parliament was supreme there. And yet the judges, on occasion, applied precedent even when they thought it was completely wrong in written law. And so they were preferring their precedents to something that was supreme under their structure—the statutes of Parliament.

So now, with respect to Tara, I think I want to weave two points together in responding to a very cogent remark. So one is about the question of, “Can lower courts deal with history and their institutional capacity?” I think we have to not look at institutional capacity as static but as dynamic.

So if we start to see decisions like Bruen—and I’m not talking whether it’s correct or not—but if we see more decisions that require inferior courts to do historical inquiry, the bar will reorient itself to historical inquiry. And maybe there’ll be actually some law professors at our schools who actually will teach originalism and constitutional law. And that, I think, will be a huge advantage. So I think that will change. Now, again, a big objective of what I would call “second-generation originalism” is to create a culture of originalism. And therefore, a decision like Bruen has some really great secondary consequences.

And I think that goes to the next point—which is, I think, a very powerful point—which is, it’s quite true that I think we never have had methodological settlement. In some sense, it’s a debate about what the rule of recognition is for constitutional law. And I don’t think that has been settled. I disagree a little that I don’t think originalism and textualism were ever off the table. I don’t think that. But I think you’re absolutely right that originalism and textualism are now not still the only things on the table.

But that brings me back to the important element of the judiciary in creating a self-sustaining culture to support it. You might think—and there’s a great article about this—that the justices themselves are not only deciding cases, but they’re kind of Republican schoolmasters. And one of the things they can do is to create a culture of small ‘R’ republican judging, which includes originalism. And that makes it harder to displace. And that’s a real challenge for originalists today precisely because of our law schools and our legal establishment. And so I think they have to think of all sorts of ways of creating a dynamic culture that will make originalism more easy to sustain for the future.

Prof. Tara Leigh Grove:  Thanks so much for those comments. I’m certain that lower courts could get more institutional capacity to do the kind of historical analysis that Bruen requires. And also, Kennedy v. Bremerton in the Establishment Clause context asks lower courts to do something similar. So I think we are getting more decisions along these lines.

I think, realistically, no matter how many law professors ultimately teach originalism in the way that your -- in the way that Professor McGinnis is hoping and Professor Lawson is doubting, I think just looking at the dockets of a lower course, I think they need more clarity. And we shouldn’t be in a situation where you’re not even sure which century to look at to figure out which -- what history to apply.

I do think we’re not going to get methodological settlement. I think you’re right that originalism and textualism were by no means off the table. There was a deep history of textualism, depending on how you read our Supreme Court decisions, also a deep history of originalism that Will Baude and Stephen Sachs have pointed to. Again, it depends on how you define originalism to get there.

And I think the Supreme Court can certainly provide guidance. Just to stir the pot a little bit, I do want to say I think there’s broad agreement that courts can’t require certain methodologies. The Supreme Court can’t require that of lower courts and that each individual judge can decide for themselves. I think it’s unclear exactly what counts as a methodology, though. This is coming up in the debates right now over Chevron.

Courts actually do a lot more than just articulate particular tests in particular cases. They articulate standards of review, like abuse of discretion, reasonableness, substantial evidence. And this is something that’s been part of our system for quite some time. And I think a big question that we have is, “Is that okay?” because the Supreme Court and courts of appeals have been doing it for a long time. And depending on how we define methodological precedent, we could actually be taking some really, really important precedents off the table, even in the vertical space.

Hon. William H. Pryor Jr.:  Professor Lawson, you’ve been furiously writing notes and perhaps fairly could be described as taking some fire. I wondered whether you had --

[CROSSTALK]

Prof. Gary Lawson:  Yeah, just a couple of very quick observations, and then we’ll hear from everybody else. Two incredibly important points that came from the folks to my left—one you just heard about methodological precedence—I think Tara is exactly right about this. What courts can do, even under my theory where the Supreme Court can bind courts inferior to it, what can it bind them to? It can bind them to meanings of texts, but that’s not the same thing as binding them to a method of decision making.

Outside the context of the Constitution, as we all know, the Supreme Court is hearing a case this -- two cases this term about whether it’s going to overrule Chevron. Well, what does it mean to overrule Chevron? Does that mean the EPA will no longer be able to draw bubbles over factories because that was actually the judgment in the Chevron case was that it could reasonably draw bubbles? No, of course, that’s not what it’s about.

The question is whether it’s going to be giving instructions to lower courts about how they’re supposed to go about deciding a whole series of future cases. And I have grave doubts whether they have that power for the same reason that I have grave doubts about whether Congress can order federal courts how to decide cases. I don’t know that the Supreme Court’s superior status -- supreme status lets it do that either.

On the background of the Constitution, John is asking all of the right questions, is posing all of the right issues. I mean, of course, the Constitution is not written on a blank slate. It’s written in the context of -- at an earlier panel yesterday. I don’t know if Professor Stinneford is in the audience here, but he invoked the common law background—what I would call the ancient Constitution—which sort of predates, underlies, is incorporated into the Constitution that we have. Yeah.

There is no doubt that the judicial power includes certain things. I mean, that’s why it’s not defined in the Constitution. Everybody kind of knew what the judicial power was. You read the Judiciary Act, right? And it says basically nothing about how the forms and methods of the equity courts and the methods and procedures of the admiralty. Everybody kind of knew what it was that courts did. Yeah. And there’s no doubt that one of the things they did was look to their prior decisions.

The two questions that remain from the standpoint of the original meaning of Article III are, number one, what exactly is that practice that they were doing? Was it looking at long-settled ancient Constitution-like norms because they were good evidence of what was right, just, and natural good evidence of the right answer? That’s a very different thing from simply looking at past decisions because they’re past decisions. It’s what I call epistemological use of precedent, and I’m fine with that.

And then the other is whether the notion that you can do that, whatever that is, in the face of supreme law—like parliament or the king in Parliament or the queen in Parliament—how does that translate into a regime that provides a written rather than unwritten Constitution which announces itself pretty obviously as supreme law? So again, I don’t think the case that I make is a knockdown drag-out case. I’ve never thought it was.

As I said, I was looking for three decades for people to talk me out of it. I think it’s a presumptive case. And the question is whether the kinds of practices that John describes are sufficiently well defined, well established, part of what I would call the ancient Constitution, so that they can generate a strong enough doctrine of precedent to get to where John or Randy or anyone else would want to go.

Hon. William H. Pryor Jr.:  Yeah. Professor Grove? If other people want to.

Prof. Tara Leigh Grove:  If other people want to say stuff, that’s fine.

Hon. William H. Pryor Jr.:  Pardon me?

Prof. Tara Leigh Grove:  Do other people want to say something first?

Hon. William H. Pryor Jr.:  Well, I think it’s okay if you respond. There’s something I want to get to next about—if everyone’s okay with it—about inferior court judges. And I’ve not taken offense at that term because it is in the Constitution, of course, and I’m a textualist, but go ahead.

Prof. Tara Leigh Grove:  And one term that’s not in the Constitution is “justice.” So we can call them all judges. So Gary Lawson was just saying that the Supreme Court cannot establish certain types of precedents for the lower courts. And I’m genuinely raising this as a question because this is something that I’m puzzling about a lot, as people are now questioning the presidential status of Chevron.

And just putting aside what people think of Chevron on the merits—and maybe there are problems with it in the view of some—but the idea that the Supreme Court can’t say to lower courts, “This is how you should review agency decisions” strikes me as very antithetical to what courts have been doing for quite some time as I referred to setting standards of review, abuse of discretion, reasonableness, substantial evidence.

And also, if the Supreme Court can’t do that, how can it issue a decision like Bruen that says, “Here’s how you need to analyze Second Amendment cases going forward” because both of them are about methodology and analytical analysis and approaches to decision making and not just this, that and the other, not just saying that the Constitution means Y in a particular case?

The other thing I’ll say about the broader theory of precedent—and I think this is what makes many folks squeamish about Gary’s views—if the Constitution does indeed, as he argues, prohibit precedent -- prohibit reliance on precedent, then the Supreme Court acts -- and yet, the Supreme Court’s going to rely on precedent as he acknowledges. The Supreme Court’s actions seem highly illegitimate to us.

And this is something that I think is not recognized enough how often the Supreme Court in our history has actually viewed the law in a particular way and done something else which seems legally illegitimate. Now, if that happens once in a blue moon, as I think it has, maybe that’s okay. But what Professor Lawson is suggesting is they’re doing illegitimate stuff all the time.

Prof. Gary Lawson:  Well, I would say they’re doing unconstitutional stuff all the time. No, I’m serious. This is a serious question. Whether that makes it illegitimate is actually a separate question. It’s not the same question.

Hon. William H. Pryor Jr.:  So parochial interests. [Laughter] I’m interested in a perspective about a question as it pertains to precedent in inferior court judges that you haven’t addressed. So, as I understand, there seems to be broad agreement with the idea that Supreme Court precedent binds inferior courts. What about the horizontal precedent of inferior courts, where courts of appeals—the precedent-setting inferior courts—judge typically in three judge panels and can only overrule precedent en banc and rehearings en banc? Does that square with your perspective, Professor Lawson? If so, why? If not, why?

Prof. Gary Lawson:  No, I have the same problems with that, that I have a horizontal precedent at the Supreme Court level. And, of course, think about district courts within a circuit. They don’t consider themselves --

Hon. William H. Pryor Jr.:  Well, they don’t make law.

Prof. Gary Lawson: -- bound by --

Hon. William H. Pryor Jr.:  District judges always don’t like it when I say this. But district judges don’t make law.

[Laughter]

Prof. Gary Lawson:  No. As I said, what I think gives the Supreme Court power to do things that the Constitution normally frowns upon is because the Constitution authorizes it to do it. Your panels are not inferior to each other, and therefore, I don’t think you can get a textual escape from the obligation to decide cases in accordance with governing law.

Hon. William H. Pryor Jr.:  Well, what do you think, though, about the notion that, by statute, Congress—which created those inferior courts—also created a process en banc review that would seem to contemplate that that is how it has to operate?

Prof. Gary Lawson:  Well, Congress can create whatever structures it wants. What I don’t think Congress can do is tell federal judges how to decide cases. Where would they get that power? Power to make all laws necessary and proper for carrying into execution the judicial power? Well, that means they can give them buildings and funds and law clerks if they’re foolish enough to allocate funds for law clerks and computers and all those sorts of things.

I don’t think it gives Congress the power to tell the courts how to decide cases. Congress does it all the time. I’m an administrative law guy. Administrative law is full of statutes ordering courts to affirm agencies, even if the court thinks the agency is wrong, as long as the agency isn’t terribly wrong. I’ve never understood where Congress gets the power to do that.

Hon. William H. Pryor Jr.:  All right. Any reactions to that?

Prof. Randy Kozel:  Sure. I would say I have the same take on courts of appeals as Gary just noted. I think requiring en banc review in order to deviate from circuit law can be understood as a prudential practice and a good idea, but I think it’s not lawfully required. And I think the best evidence of that is the cascade of situations in which courts of appeals allow three judge panels to overrule circuit law, right?

Sometimes with some sort of procedural mechanism, like circulation of an opinion to the off-panel judges first, but sometimes in light of other events, like the Supreme Court has issued an intervening decision, right? And so I think, as I said, I think it’s a good [inaudible 01:32:40] to require en banc review before you overrule precedent in lots of situations—at least putting aside something like a clear change in the Supreme Court’s case law, for example. But I view that as more of a prudential judgment.

And I’ll mention one other thing. I think—and this is something I think about a lot—a lot of the discussions we’ve been having about stare decisis are going to find their way into discussions about the en banc process really soon. They’re starting to emerge more and more, even things like the pure question of, “Well, is it a suitable reason to vote to go en banc that you thought the three judge panel got it wrong?” or, “Should you require some sort of special justification to vote to go en banc in the same way that you might require special justification to reconsider horizontal precedent on the U.S. Supreme Court?” I think these are really fascinating questions. They’re incredibly important, and I think they’re just beginning to get attention.

Prof. John O. McGinnis:  So one question I think is raised by this, a more deeper --

Prof. Randy Kozel:  Closer to the mic.

Prof. John O. McGinnis:  I’m sorry. A deeper question may be that whether or not Congress can change rules of precedent because, of course, if the rules of precedent are common law rules, it may be that Congress can change the rules of precedent and create these structures.

Now, of course, they’re limited by the Necessary and Proper clause. They can’t create precedent -- special rules for certain kinds of cases. But I don’t think it’s clear if you agree that precedent rules are common law rules that come from the structure of the Constitution’s power. That doesn’t necessarily mean that Congress is disabled from getting involved.

Prof. Gary Lawson:  Well, if they were common law rules in 1787, did they get baked into Article III in 1788 so that they are no longer common law rules? They’re now constitutional norms.

Prof. John O. McGinnis:  Well, I don’t think so. I mean, there were -- certainly, the judges applied hearsay rules, all sorts of rules, and -- as common law rules as rules of evidence. And I’m not sure they were baked in. They had the judicial power, I think, to create them, but I don’t think we would think they are baked in. And because, of course, the common law can change—and I certainly think the practice of the Supreme Court -- maybe we shouldn’t evaluate that at all—is certainly not to look to exactly what the precedent rules are in 1787 to decide what our precedent rules are today.

Prof. Tara Leigh Grove:  So getting back to Judge Pryor’s initial question, I think one thing we could step back and say, “Well, if Congress clearly has the power to constitute tribunals inferior to the Supreme Court”—that’s in Article I, Section 8, Clause 9—“and Article III contemplates that there will be inferior courts as Congress decides.”

So if we step back and say, “Well, let’s just say Congress established these courts and said to the courts, ‘Go and figure out the precedent stuff. We don’t know what you’re going to do. Just figure it out on your own,’ could they have established horizontal precedent at the court of appeals level with an en banc review session -- review system?” I think that under Gary’s theories, the answer is no. But under Randy’s and John’s theories, the answer is yes, they absolutely could for all the reasons the Supreme Court can follow horizontal precedent.

If that’s true, then it strikes me as not problematic at all for Congress exercising its authority over the inferior federal courts under the Necessary and Proper Clause to establish the system, too. And let’s be clear. It’s not Congress telling the lower courts how to decide cases. If Congress were telling the lower courts how to decide cases, we would have a very different system.

And cases out of the Fifth Circuit would be exactly like cases out of the Ninth Circuit, which, last I checked, they’re not. The courts of appeals are quite capable of doing things on their own. It’s setting up a system for judges to follow, and if it would be okay for those judges to do it on their own, then I think it is also okay for Congress to set some boundaries.

Hon. William H. Pryor Jr.:  As they establish rules of jurisdiction and procedure, etc., right?

Prof. Tara Leigh Grove:  Right.

Hon. William H. Pryor Jr.:  All right. We’ve had a lot of great discussions among the panelists. We have about a half an hour left. So we’re now at a time where we could, I think, open it up, unless someone has something burning they want to say last for Q&A. We have microphones in the middle of the room. We have a lot of people lining up. All right.

So I’ll do what I usually do with some success and sometimes not. We have a lot of time here, but there’s a limit. None of you are panelists. [Laughter] We want questions so that we can hear from our experts. So it’s okay to set up a question with a little bit of background. But let’s keep in mind we want a question and we want to get to it fairly quickly. So I’ll begin with the front mic first. Yes, sir.

Chuck Hurley:  Chuck Hurley, Iowa. My question to any or all panelists is, “Have you heard of this quote from Abe Lincoln? And, if so, what are the implications of it? Do you agree with it or disagree with it?”

And it’s a quote in regard to Dred Scott in his inaugural address. He said, “The candid citizen must confess that if the policy of the government on vital questions affecting the whole people is to be irrevocably fixed by decisions of the Supreme Court the instant they are made in ordinary litigation, the people—we the people—will have ceased to be our own rulers, having to that extent practically resigned their government into the hands of the eminent tribunal.” I’m just wondering if that lies -- if he was way out of bounds. I’ve used that a lot of times in argumentation.  

Prof. Gary Lawson:  I think he’s dead right. But I’m not sure you’d get a lot of dispute because the position he was responding to was that the Supreme Court decision foreclosed all other interpreters in all other contexts from disagreeing. That’s not a position that -- I don’t think anybody today on any spectrum, in any context, takes that kind of hardline view.

The real bite of President Lincoln’s comments is that—this would be a whole different panel—the Supreme Court is not the only interpreter of the Constitution. There are lots of other interpreters: Congress, presidents, state officials, jurors, citizens when they’re voting. And certainly, the Supreme Court has power over courts inferior to it. It does not have power over anybody else.

Hon. William H. Pryor Jr.:  Anybody else? In the back, next.

Randy Barnett:  Hi. Randy Barnett from Georgetown Law. I have a genuine, good-faith question for Randy and Tara because I share with you the belief that there’s such a thing as vertical stare decisis. And in such a system, I’m curious to know what exactly lower courts are bound to follow.

So what is your conception of the holding of a case—which I think is crucial to knowing what the scope of precedent is—and how would that conception of the holding be reconciled with the fact that, at the Founding, the Supreme Court issued seriatim opinions justice by justice and did not issue opinions of the Court like we see today?

Prof. Randy Kozel:  Sure. So thank you for the question. It’s a great question. It plugs into the debates we’ve been having about methodological precedent and about Chevron. So maybe I’ll just set the stage a little bit to contextualize based on what Randy said.

It’s been, I think, implicit in what we’ve discussed so far. But there’s this question of how strong precedent binds, right? But you don’t get there until you define what the precedent is. What I always think of is its scope. The universe of propositions for which it stands is binding authority because even an opinion that we all agree was lawfully issued, well, not all of it binds, right? As Randy said, it goes back to this age-old debate. What’s holding, and what’s dicta?

Well, that starts to get us down the road, but as Tara and as Gary were talking about, if you look at the realm of Supreme Court opinions, there’s a lot of stuff that isn’t obviously holding but that gets treated as binding commonly vertically, for example. I always think of it as a spectrum.

So, on the one hand, you’ve got the targeted application of a legal rule to the specific facts of the case. That’s definitely going to be binding vertically, okay? On the far other end, you have what Tara alluded to as a sort of broad methodology of interpretation. If a court says, “In all future cases, regardless of the constitutional provision before you, lower courts must be originalist,” I think that’s a much harder case to say is binding, right? That’s a methodological precedent that I think is pretty broad.

What gets hard are all the spots on the spectrum in between those two, and there are tons of them, right? The doctrine of strict scrutiny, okay? If you have a content-based restriction on speech, you need a compelling interest and narrowly tailored means to uphold it. So I’ve got to apply that to every statute that has a content-based restriction on speech.

Might that not seem like dicta in the classical sense -- or similarly, Gary mentioned Chevron. Even though I’ve defended a pretty strong version of precedent, I agree that Chevron is beyond the scope of precedent. I’ve argued that Chevron doesn’t get binding effect because what it asks of future judges is to make an interpretive inference about statutes that aren’t presented to the Court in Chevron, right? So I think it goes too far, but it’s a spectrum. It’s a really hard case.

And so I think it’s a really difficult set of issues. To my mind, the best we can do and what I’ve tried to do is focus on what are the parts that are at least pretty well established, and can we use them to start to build up a tradition-based or a practice-based account, right? So even though I think doctrines like strict scrutiny could create some real questions of whether they’re vertically binding, the courts have seemed to accept that, right? The next generation of these discussions is going to be cases like Bruen, for example, and maybe cases like Chevron that push the boundaries a little far.

I don’t have my mind made up on all those, frankly, but I think the sets of considerations that we’ve been talking about are the ones that we have to keep focusing on—this notion that, at the end of the day, precedent is about requiring of the judge something as an institutional matter, but also allowing the judge to bring to bear the individuality that is part and parcel of why the judge received the commission in the first place.

Prof. Tara Leigh Grove:  Yeah. So fabulous question. And I believe, Randy, you’re doing some work in this area as well. So I look forward to hearing more from you on this. One of the reasons I’m concerned about the argument that something like Chevron can’t even be presidential, if it is true -- and I think a lot of us on this panel and throughout the legal academy agree that Article III creates a hierarchical system of precedent.

If it is also true that the Supreme Court is only going to hear a fraction of the lower court cases and so can only serve as the leader in defining the content of federal law by going beyond the case and saying, “Hey, here’s what you guys should do in all these cases we can’t review,” then the holdings of Supreme Court decisions necessarily have to be broader than, “Is this particular action in this particular case valid or invalid?”

The Court needs to be able to establish standards of scrutiny, implementation tests. It needs to be able to establish historical tests if that’s what it decides to do. And so I feel like the attack on methodological precedent—which I agree with at the broad stage that Randy was talking about, “Go and do originalism”—Even if the Supreme Court can’t do that, it kind of needs to be able to do a lot in between just as a matter of theory and constitutional structure.

I will say, as a matter of practice, this is something we should not overlook. Lower court judges really pay attention to everything in Supreme Court decisions. So there’s been some empirical work on this. Even stuff that we would all agree is dicta has a tremendous impact in the inferior federal judiciary. And so I think when we’re thinking about the theory, we also have to look at how much our theories may actually be misaligned with what’s going on in the lower federal courts.

Hon. William H. Pryor Jr.:  Yeah. There’s a precedent in my court where our court said there is dicta, and there is dicta, and then there is Supreme Court dicta.

[Laughter]

Hon. William H. Pryor Jr.:  In the front.

Adam Griffin:  Thank you to the panel. It’s been a great discussion. Adam Griffin with Pacific Legal Foundation. My question concerns Bruen. There’s been a lot of criticism of Bruen and its methodology—particularly sort of practical—from the standpoint of both finding sort of how difficult it is to do the history and tradition analysis for lower courts that are very busy and then also maybe practical consequences.

And so my question, though, is, “How much of this is just it takes time to work things pure and that part of precedent moving forward, if we’re making originalist precedent, is to work the doctrine pure? So how many First Amendment cases have there been, and how many Fourth Amendment cases have there been before we get to a more coherent doctrine?”

And so I’m wondering if, rather than Bruen being necessarily incorrect, if it just takes years of lower courts percolating and deciding cases and then you get different district courts having done historical research and it starts to coalesce, I’m wondering how much of it is a problem with the framework and being something new versus taking time to work the doctrine out over time.

Hon. William H. Pryor Jr.:  Go ahead, Tara.

Prof. Tara Leigh Grove:  No, go ahead.

Prof. Gary Lawson:  It’s a beautiful tie in, actually, with Randy Barnett’s question because it goes to what it is that you get out of decisions. Formally, what you get out of a decision is a judgment. The thing that deprives people of life, liberty and property is not the opinion, the press release that accompanies what the Court does. The thing that deprives people of life, liberty and property, that presidents can execute, that the Constitution considers law, is the judgment.

So the explanation for the judgment, how far it goes to what other circumstances it covers, how much content are you providing to the legal terms that form the basis for the judgment, I think you’re absolutely right. That may take a whole series, years, decades, in order to get a larger flavor of exactly what it is that the content of the legal norm consists of that’s generating these judgments.

Hon. William H. Pryor Jr.:  Anybody else? Anybody else?

Prof. John O. McGinnis:  If I could just add? So going back to something that Tara said, nevertheless, you can have a criticism of Bruen. I think [inaudible 01:48:41] is very cogent that if it doesn’t focus on where you should look at the history—whether it’s in 1860 or in 1789—that’s an error of the Court that, really, it should be clearer about because if we have those judgments, we’re going to get to the results much more quickly than if we’re confused about even where we’re to look at matters. And so I think that’s something that the Court needs to be very careful about.

But precisely, because Judge Pryor’s point, the lower courts are going to look very carefully at what the Supreme Court does in this respect. And if the Supreme Court is clearer about -- if it’s clearer and not sloppy about these things will percolate much more quickly. And that’s a real advantage to the rule of law.

So, really, I think originalism and certainly changing the law puts, I think, an even greater premium on clarity so that whatever the shock to the system is—and, of course, there is going to be a shock to the system in changing the law—is the least possible to get the right determination. And that, I think, the Court may have fallen down in Bruen precisely for the reasons that Tara suggested.

Prof. Tara Leigh Grove:  Right. So first, I want to give a shout out to Ryan Williams, which I meant to do earlier, who’s written about lower court originalism and raised some of these institutional capacity concerns.

So I think one can always do better, right? And I also think it’s important to recognize. I understand that it is hard to define “doctrine,” whether you’re a Supreme Court justice or a court of appeals judge. There’s a lot to do. There’s a huge, huge desire often to decide only the case before you. Sometimes, that’s the only thing you can get two or five votes for, depending on whether you’re a panel or the U.S. Supreme Court.

So what I’m advocating is an effort to do more and to do better. And I think the Supreme Court can. I think when you look at various doctrines, yes, they can get worked out over time, but they can get it worked out a lot more quickly when the Supreme Court issues clearer decisions. And so the effort should always be, in my view, to do that, even recognizing that real world judges are always going to come up short some of the time.

Hon. William H. Pryor Jr.:  Okay. Next turn is the back.

Garrett Anderson:  Thank you to the panel. Garrett Anderson from Columbus, Ohio. So Judge Bork wrote and spoke a lot about old opinions he didn’t necessarily agree with, and that might have not been based in the Constitution. But he nevertheless said that some of those opinions need to be upheld because they’re so deeply embedded in jurisprudence. Is the deeply embedded argument a valid justification for upholding bad law?

Prof. Gary Lawson:  No. [Laughter] Justice Scalia thought the same thing, by the way. He actually had a very strong belief that if there were established reliance institutions built up around something, no matter how bad he thought it was, he analogized it to adverse possession. You can actually get someone’s title even though you’re a wrongdoer.

Hon. William H. Pryor Jr.:  This raises a question I’ve been curious about, Professor Lawson, and that is, it is true that in his writing about stare decisis, Justice Thomas has cited your scholarship and drawn on it. But he’s also cited Caleb Nelson’s scholarship. And I wonder to what extent Caleb Nelson’s formulation of demonstrably erroneous precedent, in your mind, differs from your own, if at all.

Prof. Gary Lawson:  Yeah. It goes to the question that Randy raised earlier. “How confident do you have to be that something is a mistake before you proclaim it a mistake?” that is, just take as a given for a moment the loss and insanity, that if there is, in fact, the meaning of the Constitution and there’s the meaning of the precedent, you choose the meaning of the Constitution. That doesn’t tell you how you have to ascertain the meaning of the Constitution and how confident you need to be that you’ve got it right.

For all the reasons -- some of the reasons I suggested that I’m dubious about Thayer’s rule of clear error for reviewing statutes, I’m also dubious about applying a demonstrably erroneous as opposed to an erroneous -- I mean, if you can’t demonstrate it, then it’s not erroneous, right? So, of course it’s going to be demonstrably erroneous.

But what I think it means by that is a level of confidence that is fairly high—something approximating a beyond a reasonable doubt mental state. I don’t think that’s necessary in order to figure out what you think the answer is. So if he means by that, which I think he does, that heightened standard of proof, I’m open to argument on that but skeptical.

Hon. William H. Pryor Jr.:  Anybody else? Okay, next question from the front.

Tom Fogerty:  My name is Tom Fogerty. I’m a student at Duke Law School. Professor McGinnis, you mentioned before how we can’t simply do stare decisis and precedent as it was done back in 1787. But today, as we attempt to redefine what stare decisis looks like, to what extent is the historical practice of precedent and stare decisis relevant to defining what factors we look at when considering whether to overturn a decision?

Prof. John O. McGinnis:  Well, I think it really just tells us that, in my view, that there were things that the courts looked at other than the correctness of the decision to apply or to retain a precedent. And the most important, I think, is reliance. I could conceive in some other world we could think of maybe there’s some other consequential effect. So I think that’s really what it tells us.

Exactly how we weigh that against other matters, I don’t think the common law exactly tells us. And that’s really, once one decides that this is a matter of the common law, things can change. Now, I don’t mean it changes in a way that is just a kind of cost/benefit analysis, but really -- because that’s a question about how the -- debate about how the common law changes. It has to change in accordance with much more general issues.

I’ve offered some reasons why it should now embrace prospective overruling that try to capture some facts about our modern society that really weren’t present at the time. And that’s the advantage of understanding precedent as a common law rule. It’s not set in stone, but judges have to be responsible in reflecting the changes, to reflect real transformations, and not just change them willy-nilly according to what their preferences are. And that’s always a difficult matter once one entrusts judges with any common law responsibilities.

Hon. William H. Pryor Jr.:  Any reactions? Okay. In the back.

Sakethram “Ram” Desabhotla:  Good morning. I’m Ram Desabhotla. I’m a two L at Notre Dame Law School. My question was regarding Professor Grove’s point about the need for clarity and the drawbacks of more narrow holdings. I’m wondering, on the flip side, how -- I wanted to hear about how the Court could potentially do that without running into the dual risks of, one, giving advisory opinions, and two, preventing their ability to explicate doctrine in a more nuanced way in the future if you have a broad precedent that you have to narrow versus having a narrow precedent that you can expand.

Prof. Tara Leigh Grove:  So I think this is along the lines of the debates over holding versus dicta, and it goes back to Randy’s points about the scope of a precedent. Can precedents go beyond deciding the case at hand? I think that in our legal system, the answer is yes. And we disagree, maybe, about how broad they can go, but they can go beyond deciding the case at hand.

And one of the things I’ve tried to underscore is that the Supreme Court can only perform its constitutional function as the hierarchical leader of the federal judiciary if it can go beyond the case at hand. Even if they were deciding 150—or my preference, 4 or 500 cases per year. I know a lot of people don’t share that preference—it still would not -- it would be only a drop in the bucket as compared to what the lower courts do. So I think just, if that’s incorrect, then we’ve lost our hierarchical system. And I think that that’s at odds with the original meaning of the text of Article III.

I do think it’s a very fair point to say, “Well, what if we’re going in a new area, and we don’t really know what to do with it?” I think, for example, Justice Scalia’s decision in Heller is quite defensible along these lines, right? The Supreme Court, for the first time in a very long -- first time in history recognized an individual right to bear arms. And whether you agree or disagree with that, that was a very new thing.

And Justice Scalia, I think, very understandably said, “We’re not going to decide everything here.” But that was 2008. And one would have thought that by 2022, when the Supreme Court decided Bruen and scores of lower court decisions were out there to help guide the Court, the Court could have done a lot more in Bruen.

So, as I said before, it’s not that I think the justices can automatically come up with great answers in every case, but I do think the goal should be to strive for that rather than striving to decide the cases on the narrowest ground.

Prof. Gary Lawson:  Just one more thought on that—and this is so trite and banal. But, I mean, if you had a scheme of what I guess we would call khadi justice—people show up; you win; you lose; you win; you lose; you win; you lose—very hard to generate a doctrine of precedent out of that.

I would think by the time we get to 1788 and we have a term like the “judicial power,” it’s contemplating something quite different than that kind of khadi justice. It’s contemplating that the judgments—the legally binding things—are actually based on reasons. And that’s where you get the notion that it can go beyond the case at hand because if the judgment exists because, let us say, a text means X, okay. Now, you’ve got the text means X, and that’s for the next case and the next case and the next case and the next case as well. So I think that notion is baked into Article III.

Hon. William H. Pryor Jr.:  In the front.

Nick Iacono:  Thank you all for your compelling dialogue. My name is Nick Iacono. I’m a law clerk and a Georgetown law graduate. I’d like to hone in on this issue of reliance. It seems clear that for the stare decisis originalists, the issue of reliance is a paramount factor in the analysis. But this is sort of complicated by the fact that reliance is sort of a nebulous concept.

What manner or quantum of reliance is required? Is former Judge Lee of the Utah Supreme Court correct that only reliance that establishes rights of property, contract, financial affairs, only that -- those types of precedents can have decision-altering force. Or perhaps, as Justice O’Connor correct that other precedents like Casey and Roe can engender sort of societal reliance. So I’m wondering if the panel has any thoughts on how do we really define and apply this concept of reliance?

Prof. Randy Kozel:  Oh, sure. Great question. So I think I would take the two categories you mentioned, and I would add one more. And so here’s what I mean. You’ve got the kind of targeted private reliance connected to investment back expectations, reliance of the sort around contract and property, say, and I think you have a pretty long established Supreme Court practice of treating that reliance as legitimate to consider—although I think it can be really hard to evaluate in lots of cases—but at least comparatively is something that the Court is comfortable considering.

I’d add a second category of reliance, where the Court’s approach has been uneven. There’s this sort of public reliance in the governmental sphere. So this idea that, “Well, the Supreme Court’s edicts lead legislatures and other public officials to take actions, and those actions cost money and take resources and time.” And there’s a question whether that sort of reliance ought to be part of the judicial calculus. And I think if you look at the Supreme Court’s case law, you’ll actually find different answers to that, even in relatively recent cases.

I tend to be one who thinks that sort of public reliance should matter, that if the Supreme Court is revisiting decisions that are undermining legislative enactments, that’s a relevant consideration. It doesn’t mean that that protects the precedent necessarily, right? There still might be countervailing and overwhelming reasons to overrule, but I do think it’s a legitimate part of the judicial calculus.

The third category, you mentioned the kind of broader societal reliance interests. I think that’s tougher. I think they’re hard to define, and they strike me as very hard for any court to specify with any sort of confidence level. To my mind, to the extent that there’s a broader societal concern for stability, which I think there is, I think that’s built into why there’s a doctrine of stare decisis in the first place. I think that’s why there’s a presumption of deference to precedent in the first place.

So I like to see that -- those sorts of broader societal considerations that connect stability more as general reasons that support a doctrine, not as something that an individual court should try to do in an individual case. That’s my take, at least.

Hon. William H. Pryor Jr.:  Yeah. I wonder whether if societal expectations and reliance were legitimate consideration and precedent, would we have ever got -- overruled Plessy, right?

Prof. John O. McGinnis:  Can I just say? I think that also goes to at least, I think—which is common between Randy and I—the common law nature of it because in considering what are the factors in the common law, we have to consider—and this is, of course, a theme of Tara’s remarks—judicial capacity. And I think it’s really very difficult for judges to determine what societal reliance is. And so that’s why I think that really isn’t a plausible part of common law doctrine of precedent.

Hon. William H. Pryor Jr.:  Okay. The next question. I’ll take it at the back.

Anna Bergstrom:  Yes, sir.

Hon. William H. Pryor Jr.:  Someone still there?

Anna Bergstrom:  My name is Anna Bergstrom. I’m a former law clerk to two federal courts, who hopefully was not foolishly paid by Congress, as Professor Lawson has jokingly suggested.

My question has to do with prospective overruling in that theory. How would that functionally work with cases such as Griswold v. Connecticut and its penumbras and emanations, assuming the case was prospectively overruled? More concretely, would Griswold be limited to its facts or its lingual framework eviscerated along with the relying cases that have been built upon it?

Prof. John O. McGinnis:  Well, I think your -- at least from your comment, you’re talking about prospective overruling, but your discussion seems much more like cutting back to me. So I propose two aspects. One is prospective overruling. I can say how that would work. If we looked at Griswold, we would say we overruled it completely root and branch, but we wouldn’t overrule it in this case. And so it would be, say, that next time, it would -- we would apply it.

I’m not sure how much difference that would make in that context. I’m also not sure that that would be a wise decision. I have other precedent rules, including the idea of entrenched precedent. Everyone sort of accepts Griswold. I’m not quite sure that would be the best idea for the Court to go down that route, but that’s how it would work. I think it would work in a simple way.

Another way of thinking about my suggestion about precedent is we would cut back on precedent. We would say, “Well, we’re not going to overrule actually this precedent according -- that gives a right to contraception, but we’re going to limit that precedent. And we’re not going to, for instance, develop some idea of substantive due process that -- on which it may depend. So we’re going to cut it back in some way.” That’s another possibility.

And those are two different kinds of ways of limiting precedent. Again, I’m not quite sure how we would do it in each of those cases, but those are very different. One is a way of changing the rule only for the future, and the other is not changing the rule for the future—changing the rule also for the past, but cutting what the Supreme Court has done back to a place where it really isn’t going to create many huge reliance costs, but it’s going to be closer to the original meaning.

Hon. William H. Pryor Jr.:  Okay, we’re really out of time. I will take one last question from the front. Lightning round question—a quick one.

Clark Forsythe:  Clark Forsythe, Americans United for Life. Stare decisis is really stare decisis et quieta non movere, which means “stand by the decisions, and don’t disturb what’s settled.” If settled, precedent is the starting point, does that create a better analytical framework?

Prof. Gary Lawson:  That goes to the question of whether what you mean by precedent is, “Okay, here’s one of the things in the stack of five decisions that the Court just issued,” or whether you’re talking about—and I’ll defer to John and Randy on this—whether you’re talking about long established lines of authority, drawing on custom, tradition, natural reason, whatever it is that they drew upon. It’s a very different conception of what it is that you mean by “precedent.” I think that’s exactly right.

Hon. William H. Pryor Jr.:  Please join me in showing your appreciation to this panel.

 

 

[Applause]

10:45 a.m. - 11:15 a.m.
Book Signings

2023 National Lawyers Convention

Mezzanine
The Mayflower Hotel
1127 Connecticut Avenue NW
Washington, DC 20006

Share

Description

The Words That Made Us: America's Constitutional Conversation

  • Prof. Akhil Reed Amar, Sterling Professor of Law and Political Science, Yale Law School

Mere Natural Law: Originalism and the Anchoring Truths of the Constitution

  • Prof. Hadley P. Arkes, Founder and Director, James Wilson Institute on Natural Rights and the American Founding & Edward N. Ney Professor in American Institutions Emeritus, Amherst College

How to Save the World in Six (Not So Easy) Steps: Bringing Out the Best in Nonprofits

  • Prof. David M. Schizer, Harvey R. Miller Professor of Law and Economics and Dean Emeritus

The People's Justice: Clarence Thomas and the Constitutional Stories that Define Him

  • Hon. Amul Thapar, United States Court of Appeals, Sixth Circuit

The Politically Incorrect Guide to the Supreme Court

  • Prof. John Yoo, Emanuel Heller Professor of Law, University of California Berkeley School of Law

Speakers

11:15 a.m. - 12:00 p.m.
Fireside Chat with FTC Chair Lina Khan

2023 National Lawyers Convention

Topics: Administrative Law & Regulation • Regulatory Transparency Project
Grand Ballroom
The Mayflower Hotel
1127 Connecticut Avenue NW
Washington, DC 20006

Share

Event Video

Listen & Download

Description

Featuring:

  • Hon. Lina M. Khan, Chair, Federal Trade Commission
  • Prof. Todd J. Zywicki, George Mason University Foundation Professor of Law, Antonin Scalia, Law School, George Mason University

Speakers

Event Transcript

Svetlana Gans:  Good morning, everyone. If you could please take your seats. Good morning, everyone. My name is Svetlana Gans. I’m a partner at Gibson Dunn and the chair of the Corporation, Securities, and Antitrust Executive Committee of The Federalist Society. I’d like to welcome you all here on behalf of my committee to the Fireside Chat with FTC Chair Lina Khan. Our committee is so thankful for Chair Khan to be here with us today and delighted for her to feature her priorities for the agency.

 

Before I turn it over to Alida Kass of the Thought Leadership Project [sic], I’d like to thank Federalist Society staff Nate Kaczmarek, Emily Manning, and Sam Fendler, as well as FTC staff Sarah Miller and Elizabeth Wilkins for their assistance with today’s event. I’d like to wish everyone in the audience who is in the military or has served in the military a happy Veterans Day. And lastly on a last patriotic note, to get CLE credit, attendees must sign in and out only once per day using the CLE QR codes found in your programs.

 

The Federalist Society has been the home for robust thought leadership on the most important competition policy issues facing the nation today, from the consumer welfare standard to the proper role of administrative agencies in the free market economy. We have an array of webinars, podcasts, and blogs, and we welcome those interested in antitrust policy, including law students and young lawyers, to contact me or Nate Kaczmarek for more information. So with that, I’d like to welcome Alida Kass from the Thought Leadership Project to introduce the Fireside Chat. Thank you.

 

Alida Kass:  Thanks so much, Svetlana. I’m Alida Kass, Vice President for Strategic Initiatives at The Federalist Society and Director of the Freedom of Thought Project. Why are we here? Why is this the Freedom of Thought Fireside Chat? Just two thoughts, first, sadly, it’s become useful, I think, to model good faith discussion. It is my sense that Todd Zywicki and Lina Khan might disagree on some things. It is also my sense that they do not fear that disagreement but really embrace it. And I welcome this as part of the ongoing process for all of us in refining our own thinking.

 

And then second, just on the substance, I have been intrigued by some of the themes in FTC Chair Lina Khan’s work that resonate not just with the ideas that we are exploring with the Freedom of Thought Project but that resonate also with some foundational ideas discussed within The Federalist Society. Her interest in the original understanding of antitrust statutes as essential to the rule of law is of course foundational, and her focus on structural protections against consolidated power in the private sector are reminiscent to me of how we might discuss vertical and horizontal structural protections for liberty in the constitutional context. And that is just part of why I am so looking forward to this morning’s conversation.

 

I’m confident that our speakers are well known, so very briefly Lina Khan is the Chair of the Federal Trade Commission. She wrote “Amazon’s Antitrust Paradox” while a 3L at Yale Law School and led the congressional investigation into digital markets before joining the faculty at Columbia Law School where she is currently on leave. Todd Zywicki is the George Mason University Foundation Professor of Law at the Scalia Law School. He is also research fellow and former director of the law and economic center and perhaps most relevant on the long list of career accomplishments served as the director of the Office of Police Planning at the FTC. Professor Zywicki and Chair Khan, thank you so much for being here today. The floor is yours.

 

Prof. Tood J. Zywicki:  Thank you, Alida, and thank you, Chair Khan, for being here for this discussion. Welcome to The Federalist Society. We appreciate having you here.

 

I figured I would start this off by sort of -- I’m working through these things, thinking through these things. I’ve been intrigued by a lot of the things that you’ve said, and so I want to have a discussion, sort of first give you a chance to sort of flesh out your views and then maybe ask you some questions. And as I was thinking about this conversation, it came to mind Irving Kristol’s old observation that a neoconservative is a liberal that has been mugged by reality. And I feel like I’m sort of I’ll say a market fundamentalist who’s been sort of mugged by reality over the last few years.

 

As many of you know, several years ago I sued my employer when they tried to force me to get vaccinated and I already had had COVID. And the world has been very surreal since that time, and it’s made me really think about a lot of the themes that Chair Khan has been talking about for many years. What have we seen since? I’ve seen -- I’ve never spread a single word of misinformation. You can read my complaint that I filed in 2021. Everything I said in there was true then; it’s true now.

 

Since that time, I’ve had videos removed from YouTube. I’ve been shadow banned on Facebook. I’ve had people who I follow for medical advice disappear from Twitter. Google has manipulated search results with respect to the Great Barrington Declaration and other things that have been done. Brett Weinstein of the Dark Horse Podcast has been demonetized.

 

Everybody said, well, if you don’t like it, start your own social media company. There was one. It was called Parlor. You may remember what happened to Parlor. And we’ve seen really what amounted to election interference with the suppression of news stories during the 2020 election. And we know one in particular. So I’m speaking for myself here, but what I have experienced over the last few years is this realization that there are these impacts on society.

 

And I’m a little slow. I’m getting a little older, but I eventually came to realize that these are the kind of things that you and some of your colleagues have been talking about for some time at least broadly in terms of political influence, private power, and that sort of thing. And so I’d just invite you to kick us off by just telling us a little bit about how your thinking has progressed on this and how you think we should be thinking about these sorts of questions. So thanks for being with us.

 

Hon. Lina M. Khan:  Well, thanks so much. And let me just say first of all it’s so great to be here. Happy Veterans Day and thanks so much to anybody in the audience who serves. The FTC has a whole set of work devoted to protecting our veterans, and it’s some of the most important work we do. And I so appreciate both Professor Zywicki and Alida for putting together this conversation and just really admire the commitment to open-hearted and open-minded discussion and debate.

 

So I want to pick up on something that you offered, which is a broader reassessment that’s happening right now. And I think we see it happening across the political aisle, across the legal spectrum, and I think it’s stemming from a clash between theories and models and reality. And I think what’s coming from that is a renewed appreciation for the ways in which concentrated economic power, concentrated private power can also pose a real threat to core liberties and the rule of law. And so for those of us who care about liberty, who care about the rule of law, recognizing not just the ways in which state power can threatened those core values but the ways in which unchecked economic power can threaten those values I see as such a rich area of discussion and debate at this moment. And so I’m really looking forward to this conversation.

 

So I got my start in this work through talking to chicken farmers. I was a business journalist and researcher, and one of my first assignments was to understand how had the poultry market evolved over the last few decades. And chicken farming as an industry is shaped like an hourglass. You have millions of consumers, thousands of farmers, and they’re all connected by just a handful of companies. And talking to chicken farmers it became clear that a lot of them were oftentimes dependent on just a single company for their economic livelihood, and that could lead to a whole set of coercive business practices.

 

But what was really striking was about a decade ago the federal government was doing a whole set of listening sessions with chicken farmers, and they invited chicken farmers to come to these workshops and speak up. And at that time, chicken farmers, a whole set of them actually decided not to show up, not because they didn’t want to but because the chicken processors had threatened them and said if you go and talk to the feds, we’re going to retaliate against you. And so it was just a sharp illustration for me of the ways in which unchecked private power could also infringe some of our core rights, the freedom of speech, in ways that also, I think, deeply offend some of the core constitutional values.

 

And it’s been really interesting as we kind of go deep into the antitrust laws, the antimonopoly tradition to see how it was conceived of as a parallel to the kinds of checks and balances that we so take for granted in our political sphere. And there was a recognition that in the same ways that if you have unchecked concentration of public power, that that would pose a deep threat to liberty, that similarly you needed safeguards against the concentrations of economic power. And the antitrust and antimonopoly laws were seen as a key form of those.

 

Prof. Todd J. Zywicki:  And that’s one of the things I find striking about all this, and your chicken farmer example is a good one. When I look at the history, the original understanding of the antitrust laws, we do see of course consumer welfare discussed, and we’ll come back to that. But we also see this sort of sense of competition and the like as being a social value in some sense as you’re saying in terms of protecting core individual liberties and kind of the political process. Do you want to elaborate on that at all?

 

Hon. Lina M. Khan:  Yeah, I mean, look, as an enforcer we really hue to the text of the statute and really want to be faithful to the laws that Congress has passed. And I think it’s been really striking and I think the discussion yesterday with Ashely Keller and Doha Mekki and some others was really interesting on this point. I think in some ways we’ve seen a departure from some of the core values and statutory interpretation tools that we ordinarily apply. But those have not been applied with as much fidelity in the antitrust context, and I think that’s what’s leading to a lot of the reassessment at this moment.

 

Prof. Todd J. Zywicki:  And so one of the things we hear if we turn to economics and I understand your point is sort of the cartoonish version of what you and DOJ is essentially -- you’re just saying big is bad, right, which I assumed you’d disagree with. But tell us, then, given all this, how does economics weigh -- how do you weigh economic analysis with sort of the values of competition, the other sorts of goals that we see the antitrust laws trying to promote?

 

Hon. Lina M. Khan:  So as an enforcer, our goal is really to be faithful to the statutes. And the first thing to note is that there isn’t just one statute. There are a whole set of statutes. We have the Sherman Act, which Congress passed in 1890, and the following the Standard Oil decision where the Court introduced the  rule of reasoned framework, Congress was really frustrated. They actually saw the rule of reason as a power grab by judges and said, hold up. We don’t want the rule of reason to basically be a blank check for judges to import whatever social values they have into the law. We want -- through the Clayton Act and through the FTC Act want to create different statutory schemes, want to create the FTC to also be a set of experts who can be a complement to the case by case adjudication that we see.

 

And so we try to honor the fact that there are three different statutory schemes and those have different statutes. And so one thing we’ve been looking to do with the FTC is making sure we’re being fully faithful to the FTC Act in particular. So the FTC Act prohibits unfair methods of competition, and there’s been an effort over the last couple of decades to read unfairness -- the word “unfair” out of our statute. I think there’s been a sense from some enforcers that the word “unfair” is distasteful, and so let’s just pretend it’s not there. And let’s just assume that the FTC Act and the Sherman Act and the Clayton Act are basically all and one the same.

 

And as an enforcer that approach really worries me. I think that’s enforcers and regulators substituting their own judgement and supplanting what’s actually written in our statutes. And so our core principle has been to make sure we are fully enforcing the laws as written by Congress in a way that’s consistent with what these statutes set out.

 

Economics is a tool. It’s a tool that can inform our analysis, but I do worry about tendencies that we’ve seen to import words that are not in our statute and let those words override what actually is in our statute, be it consumer welfare or be it forms of efficiencies. I was really struck by Ashley Keller’s comments yesterday around how even from a point of administrability this is actually created a regime that’s produced uncertainty, produced unpredictability. And so from a whole set of metrics, I think there’s an impetus to really go back to some of the core values.

 

Prof. Todd J. Zywicki:  Let’s pick up on that, then, because as you’ve sort of alluded, you think that antitrust has sort of gone in a different direction over the past several decades, maybe going back to the ‘80s. We’ll just call the short answer the Chicago School Revolution. And one of the things I wonder about is thinking back to that time sort of the direction antitrust law took didn’t really just kind of fall out of the sky. They didn’t wake up one day and say we need to turn the -- Richard Posner and Robert Bork had it right. Let’s just go for it.

 

If you look back at the history, one of the reasons we had the antitrust laws develop, I think, was in the ‘60s and ‘70s the United States was -- we had declining competitiveness globally. We had stagflation. We had high unemployment. We had sluggish economic growth, and there was a big movement at the time for regulatory reform that was bipartisan. It started under Carter -- airline deregulation, trucking deregulation, all that sort of stuff. And as part of that was reform of the antitrust laws. At least that’s the way I see history.

 

And so I’m curious for somebody like me who’s thinking about that, how should I think about what you’re doing now in the sense the world’s not less competitive now than it was then? A lot of the companies that we think about as the ones I was just criticizing -- I think it’s horrible that Amazon can and does essentially decide whether a book will get published. Think about that. One company can basically decide whether a book gets published because they have so much control over distribution. If they won’t carry it, they’re not going to publish it. So this is very dangerous, the private power.

 

But at the same time, a lot of these -- and I’m just speaking for myself obviously. But a lot of these companies are also sort of global leaders with competitiveness and that sort of thing. In the ‘80s it was Japan. Today, it’s China. How should I be thinking about those issues and how sort of those general, broader macroeconomic and global competitiveness issues relate to how we think about antitrust? That’s a very long question, but…

 

Hon. Lina M. Khan:  Yeah. It’s an important question, and I think it’s a strain of the discussion that we hear a lot. Look, back in the ‘70s we similarly faced these questions. As the Justice Department was investigating AT&T, the Department of Defense said, hold up, don’t go ahead with this antitrust action because it’s going to jeopardize our national security. Ultimately, we did see the Justice Department take action against AT&T. We saw the Justice Department take antitrust action against IBM, which lent to the unbundling of the hardware and software.

 

And those were some of the most important antitrust actions we had in that they actually positioned the U.S. to get ahead. They really sewed the seeds for the Silicon Valley revolution, the microchips, the opening up of the Bell Labs patent vaults. And so I view that as actually a really key set of antitrust actions. And if you do a bit of a comparative advantage against Japan or parts of Europe that actually doubled down on their national champions, the U.S. ended up coming out ahead because those national champions weren’t able to innovate in the same way.

 

Similarly, we hear arguments today about how especially with the large tech companies that we should hold off against antitrust action because we need to protect these national champions. And I think that framework sometimes assumes that we’re in some type of cold war type arms race where these companies are exclusively advancing U.S. interests. If you look closely, these companies are actually deeply ingrained in China. They’re deeply integrated in China. They’re looking to expand in China. And those types of economic dependencies can actually leave the U.S. more vulnerable.

 

And we’ve seen how some of these foreign states can use that economic leverage as a way to impose their own social values on the U.S. So we’ve heard about some companies censoring, changing the content of their products and services to please the political leaders of other countries. And so the entire paradigm here is a bit more scrambled when these companies have interests that maybe aligned against U.S. national security interests.

 

I think the other area where some of this comes to bear is in the context of our defense industrial base. And so for several years now we’ve been seeing top military leaders come out and say the degree of consolidation that we see in our defense industrial base poses a risk to national security. This has happened across administrations, but it was really during the Clinton administration where there was a policy choice to spur consolidation.

 

And so we’ve seen 50 major defense contractors whittled down to five today. And so for major weapon systems, oftentimes the government is just dependent on one or two or sometimes three contractors. And that can be a problem both from the perspective of the government paying more but also from the perspective of just challenges in scaling up at moments when you need.

 

Take another example. Just a couple of years ago there was a factory in Louisiana that blew up, and as a result of that one explosion, the U.S.’s production of a particular type of gunpowder, black powder which is a really elementary input that has hundreds of military uses, we no longer have any factories in the U.S. that produce that gunpowder. That factory is still offline. And so it’s just another vivid example of how concentration of production can concentrate risk in ways that leaves us vulnerable from a national security perspective. So those two examples strike me as areas where more competition and more antitrust is really what’s going to promote our national interest rather than propping up national champions, promoting consolidation, especially when you have such deep interests of these companies aligned with those in China.

 

Prof. Todd J. Zywicki:  And you’re sort of talking now about them I think appropriately about thinking about the other values of competition other than consumer welfare standard. And as we all recall the subtitle to Robert Bork’s book The Antitrust Paradox is “A Policy at War with Itself.” And one of the arguments he makes and one of the arguments I hear is -- and you alluded to this with describing Ashley Keller’s comments yesterday is the sort of rule of law values.

 

And one of the concerns I hear expressed and one of the things that Bork sort of describes is yes, the consumer welfare standard is imperfect. It’s kind of fuzzy around the margins but in some sense at least kind of tells us what the target is. Whereas, are you suggesting we kind of open up antitrust to something more than just consumer welfare? And then the following question would be, then how do we balance these sorts of goals? How do we get predictability if it’s consumer welfare versus competition in some way, however that’s defused, or these other kind of concerns that I share with you about private power?

 

Hon. Lina M. Khan:  Yeah. So my colleague at the Antitrust Division, Jonathan Kanter, said the other month if you ask five people what consumer welfare means, you’re going to get six different answers. And so the idea that consumer welfare is this unified standard that everybody agrees what it means I think is overstated. Initially, it was seen by some to mean total surplus. Then it was seen to mean consumer surplus. Now people have said, well, actually it means trading partner welfare. And actually, it’s also compatible with worker welfare.

 

And so you have a term. Its meaning seems quite slippery. That term is not in any of the statutes we’ve been charged with enforcing, and so I do think that this instead is an example of some of the very things that we should be worried about. Unelected bureaucrats supplanting their own standards into the text of the statute. And a world in which that standard is not even providing a single set of values across the board, it’s not providing a regime that’s administrable that’s providing certainty -- I think that has serious shortcomings.

 

Prof. Todd J. Zywicki:  When I look at the economics literature from the ‘60s and ‘70s, one of the things that’s related to this is at that point -- and this is an area that I think it’s less of a problem now than at least it seemed to be at that time was the economics literature finds a lot of sort of public choice interest group political interference with the merger process and that sort of thing. And one of the arguments that’s been made is, again, opening -- trying to do something other than consumer welfare, whatever that might mean, also raises the potential for more political interference, rent seeking, inefficient competitors protecting themselves from more efficient competitors and the like. Should I be concerned about that?

 

Hon. Lina M. Khan:  Yeah. Look, I think those are reasonable things to be worried about. Though I think in practice what we see more is dominant firms and monopolists being best positioned to engage in regulatory capture at the expense of some of the smaller and independent firms. And I think these are some of the concerns that we hear today, including in the context of AI where a lot of the start ups are seeing the big tech CEOs be invited to Congress and are worrying are these big tech execs basically going to help craft regulations that are going to lock out startups and innovators.

 

I think more generally, look, the Supreme Court has said the Sherman Act is a consumer welfare statute. And so as enforcers we’re bound by that. But this is where I think it becomes important to recognize that the Clayton Act and the FTC Act are separate statutes that are supposed to lay out different standards. And so one thing that we at the FTC have been doing is really going back to the text of the statutes, looking at all the precedent on the books.

 

We put out a policy statement last year on Section 5 that was looking to move away from the effort to collapse the FTC Act onto the Sherman Act, which we didn’t see as a faithful execution of the statute. And there, we took the text of the statute seriously. It says unfair methods of competition, so it has to be a method of competition and it’s unfair. Yes, “unfair” is broad, but let’s look at what the courts have said unfairness means; right? And so we went through and read every single court decision where the court had actually interpreted what standalone Section 5 of the FTC Act actually means.

 

And so I think these can be hard questions, but we have a tried and true set of tools that we apply when we’re trying to figure out what does the text of a statute means, and it’s just been really striking to me that antitrust is an area where all of those ordinary rules of the road have been suspended and there’s just this special and exceptional set of tools and modes of reasoning that get applied. And I think we should be wary of that.

 

Prof. Todd J. Zywicki:  And I think this is an important point that I had not really appreciated until I heard you and General Kanter talking about these questions. We tend to think of everything as being the Sherman Act, and I think perhaps it’s  because Bork’s book has been so influential on thinking for people like me as well as the courts. But I think you’re making an important point here, which is it’s not just the Sherman Act. There’s the FTC Act. There’s the Clayton Act and the like, and they were passed at different times. And not all the policies necessarily align perfectly with each other.

 

Hon. Lina M. Khan:  That’s right. And in 1950 we had amendments to the Clayton Act because the Clayton Act was viewed as not adequately covering certain types of vertical mergers, certain types of conglomerates. And the political backdrop at that moment was really interesting because it was during the Cold War, and lawmakers were really worried that if we allowed economic consolidation that would really open us up to the type of communism that we saw elsewhere. And there was a real recognition that preserving competition in our economic sphere was really critical for preserving liberty values in our political sphere.

 

Prof. Todd J. Zywicki:  One of the things -- so you’ve talked a lot about I think very interestingly about structural protections for liberty that competition provides, and that really resonates with me in a very powerful way. One thing, when I talk to people about this and I raise this, one of the things that people say to me is, well, yeah, I get your point. But antitrust isn’t the right tool. We should reform Section 230, or we should do common carrier regulation or these sorts of things.

 

My first question is, well, if you are concerned about government, why do you think that’s a less intrusive way of regulating these things or smaller government? But more generally what do you say to somebody who says, well, antitrust isn’t the right tool to get at these questions?

 

Hon. Lina M. Khan:  Yeah. Ultimately, it’s for lawmakers to decide what’s the right regulatory paradigm for different contexts. Traditionally, common carrier had been a key tool, especially in transportation, in communications. And it was primarily applied to entities that policymakers had determined were affected with the public interest, entities that had held themselves out to serve the public. And there was a worry that if you allow these entities, be it the railroad or some type of telecom infrastructure -- if you allowed them to discriminate, if you allowed them to choose who got to ride the rails and who didn’t that that was a form of outsized power that could have distortionary effects, be it in our economy or be it in our public discourse. And so I’ve been really interested by the move to re-designate some of these modern day forms of speech infrastructure, forms of common carriers.

 

And I think some of the legal questions that are being teed up around that are really interesting, but I think fundamentally these are two different paradigms. Antitrust is about providing -- through competition basically providing checks and balances and limiting the outsized power of any single entity. The common carrier regime is more about accepting that competition is going to be insufficient. And so if you’re going to have concentrations of power, you need something like common carriage and nondiscrimination to check the unfettered power, to check the ability for that entity to use its arbitrary power to pick winners and losers. And so I think directionally these are both aimed at similar endpoints, but they’re fundamentally doing it through different means.

 

Prof. Todd J. Zywicki:  And one of the things that’s sort of dawned on me with respect to that is if you look at, say -- and I won’t ask you to comment on it -- but if you look at, say, the Fifth Circuit case on the censorship, the First Amendment infringement cases of censorship, these highly concentrated industries make it much easier to collude to suppress speech, but it also makes it much easier for the government in my opinion to coerce. If you’ve only got a handful of social media companies you need to lean on rather than a lot of them, I think there’s a structural protection there it strikes me against the government as well that comes from this one -- we’ll open it up I think. We’ll have a couple of minutes for questions from the floor if you’re okay with that.

 

Hon. Lina M. Khan:  Sure.

 

Prof. Todd J. Zywicki:  But I’m going to ask -- so you can move to the microphones if you like, but one area that you’ve tackled that I think very intriguing and is in this same vein about sort of antitrust policy is one of the other things that is part of my being mugged by reality experience is I’ve really -- something I never really fully appreciated before, maybe because I was a tenured professor, but employer power and the idea that my employer forced me -- was trying to force me between my health, literally my physical health from an unnecessary treatment and my job that I love more than anything except for my wife and kids -- my entire sort of reason for being. And luckily I was a tenured professor. Luckily I got an exemption. But I heard from hundreds of people around the country who were coerced by their employers into deciding between their career and their jobs. And I know one of the things that you guys have tackled is covenants not to compete, but I would just invite you to sort of comment on that, sort of how you see that aspect of it, employers, covenants not to compete if you want to talk about that specifically -- but why you see this as an FTC issue as far as jurisdictionally.

 

Hon. Lina M. Khan:  So antitrust laws were designed to protect everybody, and there’s a long history of recognizing that they also protect workers. The Supreme Court’s decision in Alston a few years ago kind of ratified that once again. And our work on non competes has been really interesting. This had been ongoing before I arrived at the agency, but over the last decade, there’s been a whole set of empirical research finding that labor markets in the U.S. are much more concentrated than previously assumed, that there’s monopsony power being exercised by employers, and that that can result in a form of coercion.

 

Non competes in particular started off in the boardroom, but they’ve really proliferated across sectors, across income levels. So they’re now applied to fast food workers, security guards, engineers, journalists. And when you look at the empirical research we found that this is harming the workers who are covered by the non competes but also those who are not covered by them and that there’s harm to competition. So we hear from startups and new businesses that are able to get financing. They’re able to start entering the market, but then they quickly hit a ceiling in terms of how much they can scale because all the relevant workers are locked up through non competes.

 

As part of this work I actually also got a chance to talk to some religious liberty advocates, and they were sharing how especially over the last few years where you’ve seen people feel coerced by their employers and wanting to exercise religious liberties that the existence of non competes, which can really eliminate a whole set of really important exit options, can also then limit people’s ability to exercise those core rights. And so I think we see from a whole set of ways how these can -- the employer/employee relationship can intrinsically be coercive but then these non competes can kind of further make that coercion more acute in ways that I think can be a problem from a competition perspective but also from what you’re noting.

 

I also wanted just to go back briefly to your point around the structural protections because revisiting the Fifth Circuit opinion I was struck by analogs that we see between overbreadth doctrine and what’s that designed to do from a First Amendment perspective where it basically says that there are certain forms of restraints that are so intrinsically problematic because they’re having a chilling effect. And so you don’t need to have an actual exercise of government power; the mere possibility of it through certain types of statutory schemes is intrinsically problematic because it’s chilling speech. I think there are analogs to that in antitrust and antimonopoly where it was recognized that certain types of concentrations of power, certain types of mergers created structures that could intrinsically create certain types of chilling effects on procompetitive behavior such that you don’t have to show endless types of key certain effects because the structure itself would create risk. And so I think there’s really just interesting analogs between parts of First Amendment doctrine and parts of antitrust doctrine that we’ve seen historically as well.

 

 

Prof. Todd J. Zywicki:  Interesting. We can go to a question from here in the front. And I’ll got to the mic in back next.

 

John Shu:  Hello, madam chairwoman. Thank you very much. Todd, thank you. I’m John Shu from Newport Beach, California. And thanks for coming. Madam Chairwoman, would you please describe your concerns, if any, on whenever the FTC or any other regulatory agency takes antitrust action -- the balancing between protecting competition as opposed to not protecting competitors? Thank you.

 

Hon. Lina M. Khan:  Yeah. So this often gets kind of posed as a dichotomy, and there are instances in which protecting competitors can be in tension with protection competition. But I think there’s also a basic way in which you need to have competitors to have competition or the potential of competitors to enter a market. And so I think honestly this dichotomy is a little over simplified.

 

As a practical matter, we look at the specific facts. We look at are there entry barriers. We look at if it’s a merger case. Are there presumptions being met? And so it ends up being a case by case analysis, but I do worry about the ways in which that dichotomy being superimposed can kind of turn us away from wanting to make sure that structurally we’re preserving the opportunity for competition, which includes preserving the opportunity for competitors to come into the market. So I think our laws and the judicial process are very well equipped to make sure that the antitrust laws are not being weaponized in any way to serve any particular interest.

 

When putting together our cases, we certainly interview third parties, but we have other investigative tools. We also look at what do the documents say, what does the economics say. So it’s not like cases are put together exclusively because you have complaining parties. You really need to do a full 360.

 

Prof. Todd J. Zywicki:  Because that is, I think, one of the big questions. When I look at the legislative history, what I see is -- like the Clayton Act, when they talk about competition, it’s kind of ambiguous, which is they talk about it in terms of good competition when you think about it. But it’s also pretty clear a lot of those things had -- to me at least, that a lot of the antitrust laws were protecting competitors from more efficient competitors -- the research on the Swift Meatpacking Company and local antitrust laws to block them. We have the whole experience that Tim Muras has talked about with AMP, these sorts of things. And I think trying -- it seems like that’s the hard line to navigate, or that’s what Bork suggests is to try to -- how you keep protection of competition from collapsing into protection of inefficient competitors.

 

Hon. Lina M. Khan:  Yeah. The way that I read the common law and I think there’s actually a lot more room for academic work on kind of research the deep common law and the originalist understanding of antitrust is that a lot of the common law, including at the state level, was designed to distinguish between permissible and impermissible forms of competition. So it’s impermissible to --

 

Prof. Todd J. Zywicki:  Interesting.

 

Hon. Lina M. Khan:  -- compete by colluding with your rival and trying to through that compete against one of the other big guys in the market. It is permissible through having more -- to compete by having greater operational efficiencies. And so I think the language of competition as a standalone doesn’t really serve us well in terms of what is the underlying analytical inquiry. This is where I think the FTC Act’s text on fair methods of competition creates a better anchor for realizing what we’re doing is distinguishing between methods of competition, which ones are permissible and which ones are impermissible. There aren’t always going to be easy answers, but I do think that some of that history provides a roadmap.

 

Prof. Todd J. Zywicki:  Interesting. So for all the law students, if you want to write your third year note on the common law of antitrust, maybe some day you too could be chair of the FTC. I’ll take a question in the back, from the mic in the back.

 

Mark Chenoweth:  Mark Chenoweth, president of the New Civil Liberties Alliance. It was our honor to represent Professor Zywicki in his successful lawsuit. My question for Chair Khan is I was struck by your professed fidelity to the statute, the Clayton Act and the FTC Act. I wonder  if you would further that fidelity by pledging to eschew non statutory merger conditions in the future at the FTC?

 

Prof. J. Zywicki:  Now you know why I liked having him as my lawyer.

 

Hon. Lina M. Khan:  So we just issued draft merger guidelines this summer, and leading up to that we went back and looked at every litigated merger decision and wanted to make sure that these merger guidelines were being fully faithful to the text of the Clayton Act but also the precedent. One thing we found when looking closely at prior iterations of the merger guidelines was that in some instances the guidelines actually had departed from the case law on the books. And so that’s been core to that inquiry. We got thousands of comments. We’re currently in the process of digesting them.

 

One thing I’ve shared publicly is sometimes we get companies coming before us saying we know the merger is problematic from a competition perspective, but let us make certain ESG commitments to you all to wave that through. And we firmly reject that. Those types of ESG commitments or ESG promises or any other types of social justice type commitments can never rescue an illegal merger, and so we’ve tried to make clear that firms should not come to us with those types of non statutory commitments because we really are bound by the text of the law.

 

Prof. Todd J. Zywicki:  On this point, it sounds like what you’re saying is you feel like the case law has departed from the original understanding. Are you guys attempting to overturn precedent, or are you guys seeing to distinguish precedent -- how should we -- like The Wall Street Journal for example has made much of your one loss record for example. And a lot of people have said this is kind of contrary to where the law has been. How do you respond to critics who talk about how this fits with the precedent that has been built up over time?

 

Hon. Lina M. Khan:  So the guidelines are entirely anchored in the case law, in the legal precedent, including major Supreme Court decisions, major decisions from the court of appeals. These are decisions that get cited routinely in modern day antitrust decisions. One change that we saw around mid century is before it was, I believe, the 1970s we had something called the Expediting Act where antitrust cases that were appealed by the Justice Department the Supreme Court had to take up.

 

And so just through the ‘70s you have much more Supreme Court jurisprudence on antitrust than we’ve seen since then, and so some people use that to suggest, well, these major cases from mid century are just outdated. They’re no longer in fashion. We don’t take that view. And actually even if you look at modern day merger decisions from the courts, they too are citing these same decisions, which are kind of key pillars of antitrust jurisprudence. How they get applied in modern markets is going to differ slightly than how we apply them in the smokestack context. But we don’t think it’s for us as enforcers to just decide that because case law is old it’s just out of fashion. We kind of have to wait for it to be overruled.

 

Prof. Todd J. Zywicki:  Well, I think with that we are out of time because we have lunch. I want to say thanks for being here with us.

 

Hon. Lina M. Khan:  Thanks so much.

 

Prof. Tood J. Zywicki:  And you’re welcome back any time, so thanks for being here.

 

Hon. Lina M. Khan:  Thank you so much.

 

 

     

 

 

12:00 p.m. - 1:45 p.m.
The Administrative State, Its Supporters and Its Discontents

2023 National Lawyers Convention

Topics: Administrative Law & Regulation • Federalism • Separation of Powers
East Room
The Mayflower Hotel
1127 Connecticut Avenue NW
Washington, DC 20006

Share

Event Video

Listen & Download

Description

The administrative state - the agencies comprising the Executive Branch of the U.S. federal government - has exploded in size and reach since 1946 when President Truman signed the Administrative Procedure Act into law. The APA has been amended a bit since then, but has it kept up with current challenges? While the Executive Branch has been growing, the other two branches of government have been changing as well. Congress has increasingly tended to delegate authority to agencies. And courts are changing their views not only of how much leeway agencies have in interpreting and applying statutes, but also of what methodology courts themselves should employ when interpreting statutes, including the APA. This panel will discuss how these changes impact the government and the governed.

Featuring:

  • Hon. Steven Bradbury, Distinguished Fellow, Executive Vice President’s Office, The Heritage
  • Prof. Emily Bremer, Associate Professor of Law, University of Notre Dame Law School
  • Prof. Ronald M. Levin, William R. Orthwein Distinguished Professor of Law, Washington University in St. Louis School of Law
  • Mr. Andrew Tutt, Senior Associate, Arnold & Porter
  • Moderator: Hon. Steven J. Menashi, United States Court of Appeals, Second Circuit

Overflow: Chinese Room

Speakers

Event Transcript

Gary Lawkowski:  We’ll go ahead and get started now if that works for everyone. Thanks. So my name is Gary Lawkowski. I’m a counsel over at Dhillon Law Group, but more importantly, I’m a member of our administrative law practice group here for The Federalist Society. That is the organization that is sponsoring today’s lunch panel, which will be a fascinating discussion on our administrative law issues. If you like what you see, if you are fascinated by administrative law, you want to help organize these things, please contact us. We’d love to have your help with the administrative law group. Contact Nate Kaczmarek. He can get you set up with that.

 

I’ll also give you the CLE announcement if you haven’t already. So for those of you who are pursuing CLE, we remind you that you need to get -- to get credit, you need to sign in and out each day. Signing in and out is done by scanning the little CLE display. There’s a couple out in the hallway. It’s also on the back of your program. If you look there, there’s a little QR thing. Scan that. You just have to do that once per day, in and out when you’re coming in and out. Once per day, in and out. That’s all you need to do. That’ll make sure you get your CLE credit.

 

And with that, I’d like to give you a brief introduction of our moderator, although I suspect for many of you he needs no introduction. Judge Menashi is a judge on the court of appeals for the Second Circuit. He previously served in the White House in the White House Counsel’s Office as a special assistant and associate counsel to the president. He was also the acting general counsel for the Department of Education. Before that, he taught administrative law and procedure at George Mason University, was a partner at Kirkland & Ellis, and was a clerk to Justice Alito and to Judge Ginsburg on the D.C. Circuit. Finally, he graduated from Stanford Law and Dartmouth University. With that, I will turn the panel over. Judge.

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi:  Thanks very much. This works? You can all hear me? Okay. Great. Welcome, everybody, to our panel on the “Administrative State, Its Supporters, and Its Discontents.” The charge for this panel explains that the administrative state, the agencies that compose the Executive Branch, has expanded in size and reach since the Administrative Procedure Act was adopted in 1946. The APA has been amended to some extent, but has it kept up with current challenges? And what about changes in the other two branches of government? Congress has tended to delegate increasing authority to agencies, and courts are changing their views about deference to agencies and the methodologies that courts themselves employ in interpreting statutes, including the APA.

 

So I think our panel will address two basic questions. One is how far has administrative practice diverged from the original expectations of the framers of the APA? And second, with so many administrative law doctrines now open to question, what changes are on the horizon? To help us understand these issues, we have a distinguished panel of experts. We will hear several remarks from them and then some discussion amongst the panelists. And then we’ll open it up to you all for questions.

 

So I’m first going to introduce our panelists in the order in which they’ll be speaking. First, we’ll hear from Ron Levin. Ron Levin is the William Orthwein Distinguished Professor of Law at the Washington University in St. Louis School of Law. He’s the author of a case book on state and federal administrative law, now in its third edition, and a nutshell volume on administrative law and process now in its fifth edition. Professor Levin is chair of the ABA section of administrative law in a regulatory practice and served as the ABA’s advisor to the drafting committee to revise the Model State Administrative Procedure Act. He also serves as a public member of the Administrative Congress of the United States, and previously, he clerked on the Fifth Circuit and graduated from the University of Chicago.

 

Next, we’ll hear from Emily Bremer, who’s a professor of law at the University of Notre Dame Law School where she teaches and writes in the areas of administrative law, civil procedure, and business associations. Her scholarship focuses primarily on matters of procedural design and issues that arise at the intersection of public law and private ordering. She also serves as a public member of ACUS and as a council member of the ABA’s section of administrative law and a regulatory practice. Earlier in her career, she was an associate in the telecom and public litigation group of Wiley Rein, clerked on the Ninth Circuit, and graduated from NYU.

 

Third, we’ll hear from Andrew Tutt who’s a senior associate at Arnold & Porter here in Washington where he litigates cases involving administrative law, intellectual property law, and civil rights law. He has argued and won three cases in the U.S. Supreme Court, and he has led appeals and complex cases in appellate and district courts across the country. Earlier in his career, he served as an attorney advisor in the Office of Legal Counsel, clerked on the D.C. Circuit, and graduated from Yale.

 

Last but not least, we’ll hear from Steven Bradbury who’s a distinguished fellow at the Heritage Foundation. He served as general counsel of the U.S. Department of Transportation from 2017 until 2021 and in that capacity oversaw the department’s rulemaking and enforcement efforts. He served as acting deputy secretary of transportation and as the acting secretary for a brief period. Earlier in his career, Steve served as the principle deputy and the acting assistant attorney general for the Office of Legal Counsel, and he has also been a litigation partner at Kirkland & Ellis and at Dechert in Washington. He clerked for Justice Thomas at the D.C. Circuit and graduated from the University of Michigan. So with those introductions, we’ll turn first to Professor Levin.

 

Prof. Ronald M. Levin:  Okay. Well, thank you, everybody, and I appreciate being invited to speak to the administrative law and regulation practice group. The designated topic for this convention is originalism on the ground, and so I thought I would get this panel discussion going by talking about the role of originalism in interpretation of the Administrative Procedure Act. But more accurately, I’m going to be talking about the almost complete absence of originalism in APA interpretation.

 

I’ve done a good deal of writing on what I call the evolving APA, and in these remarks I’ll mention a few respects in which that label is descriptively accurate and a few ways in which I think it’s been beneficial to administrative law. And finally, I will comment on a current controversy that tests the limits of that premise.

 

So I’ll start on the descriptive level by reminding you of some of the numerous ways in which the courts have read into the act an array of meanings that would’ve surprised its drafters. Many of those innovations are a direct response to the fact that beginning in the 1960s and ‘70s and continuing to the present day agencies have chosen to do most of their policymaking through rulemaking rather than case by case adjudication. And that development made a lot of sense in terms of efficiency and rationality and transparency.

 

But it also created a demand for procedural safeguards that Congress did not think to put into the APA because it did not foresee that shift. But the courts have essentially decided that if rulemaking is going to be where the policy action is it’s important to make sure that agencies will give serious consideration to competing points of view in the rulemakings and be rigorous in their decision making. So that’s how we got innovations in Section 553, the rulemaking provision of the APA, such as the duty to maintain a contemporaneous record for judicial review, the duty to disclose facts and data underlying the premise of the rule, the duty to respond to comments. None of that was part of the original model nor written into the text of the statute. And at the same time we also have gotten the hard look doctrine, which interpreted the arbitrary and capricious standard of the APA to require that in judicial review agencies have to display a much higher level of reasoned analysis than had previously been expected.

 

Now, some of you may think of yourselves as originalists and think that what I’ve been describing sounds an awful lot like the dread specter of living constitutionalism, which this convention has been convened to exorcise. And if you’re thinking along those lines, you may prefer the narrower rationale that Justice Scalia once proposed before he became a judge -- and I think Andrew Tutt will be talking about that in a couple of minutes. But whether or not you agree with either or both of these rationales, I think there’s no denying that society as a whole has accepted the concept of an evolving APA. Congress certainly has not pushed back against these developments.

 

On the contrary, when legislators have proposed bills in recent years to revise the APA, the thrust of those proposals has been to extend these developments even further, not to roll them back. And that’s not at all surprising because the modern glosses on the APA have largely served to benefit challengers to the agency actions, which is just fine with the business groups that have led the recent efforts to amend the APA. And the premise has even penetrated into the thinking of leaders of The Federalist Society.

 

The program description for this panel poses the question “Has the APA kept up with current challenges?” I’m sure some of you have thought to yourself, well, who said they had to do that? But I think most people would not have reacted that way and would’ve taken that as a perfectly ordinary premise.

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi:  I think that statement is preceded by the idea that it’s been amended, so maybe the idea is that you should amend the statute.

 

Prof. Ronald M. Levin:  Maybe. Now, when I’m saying that -- sorry, at this point it’s largely a defense. What I’ve been saying is largely a defense of settled law and the status quo. But now I want to turn attention to an issue of current controversy, which does pose a choice between originalism on the one hand and a modern problem solving approach to interpretation on the other. And I’m referring to the debate about the legitimacy of nationwide injunctions and the vacatur of agency action.

 

On a policy level, there are many valid criticisms of judicial misuse of that device which sometimes do enable the individual judges to exercise a disturbing amount of power to set aside nationwide policies. And so yes, I do favor some curtailment of that practice. But I want to focus on a more legalistic approach that Justice Gorsuch has recently been proponing most recently in his concurring opinion in the United States v. Texas during the past term.

 

He argued that judicial vacatur of agency rules is generally unlawful because it is not mentioned in the APA. In a way that argument is curious because the act does say that a reviewing court shall set aside an unlawful agency action, and in the abstract vacating a rule certainly sounds like setting it aside. So how did Justice Gorsuch conclude that the act couldn’t be read that way? He relied more or less entirely on inferences that he drew from other textual provisions of the act and the historical background of the act.

 

Entirely missing from that discussion was any recognition of the tradition that I mentioned at the beginning of these remarks, the tradition of interpreting the APA to accommodate the emerging practice realities. And in this instance, vacatur is a fundamental feature of rulemaking practice. It enables reviewing courts to avoid the chaos that could result if one company in an industry were able to derail a regulatory requirement as to itself while every other company remained subject to it. That differential treatment would be workable in some contexts, but in others it would result in fundamental incoherence in the program. And I think it’s unfortunate that Justice Gorsuch essentially took a static approach to interpreting the APA, which led him to overlook those realities.

 

So to sum up, I’ve argued that originalist methodology has proved inadequate and will continue to prove inadequate to meet the challenges of implementing the APA. And if you agree with me that this methodology is not well suited to construing this important 80 year old statute, you might go on to conclude that it also is not well suited as a methodology for interpreting a 200 year old Constitution. That might not be a bad result either.

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi:  Thank you very much, Professor Levin. Professor Bremer.

 

Prof. Emily Bremer:  Thank you. I’m so happy to be here today. There’s nothing I like talking about better than the APA, and if you think I’m kidding, I regret to inform you I am not. So I think I was invited as the originalist because I’ve spent the last several years doing a really deep dive into what Kenneth Davis called the intellectual foundation of the APA, which is the research foundation that the attorney generals committee on administrative procedure provided to Congress that helped inform the statute’s enactment.

 

But I think I’m going to disappoint those of you who consider yourselves to be originalists because I think in the context of the APA the implications are actually quite a bit different. And my basic thesis is that the history matters quite a bit in understanding the meaning and intended operation of the APA. But at the same time, that history does not require one to reject and in fact I actually think it supports what Professor Levin describes as the evolving APA. And if that sounds contradictory to you, I’m going to do you the favor of sort of working my way towards that thesis by identifying four other contradictions, perhaps you might call them subsidiary contradictions, in the APA in the way that it was drafted and the way that it was structured and in the challenges that it faces today.

 

So contradiction number one, the APA’s short, but it’s really complex. It’s a very concise statute, but it conveys an incredible amount of content. So for example, the provisions in 553 that define the minimum requirements of notice and comment rulemaking span a sum total of 143 words. I sometimes joke that given how often I look at the APA I really should just tattoo it on my arm. And that’s a credible threat because the statute is actually short enough.

 

But at the same time, that’s deceptive. It suggests that there’s just not a lot of there there, but nothing could be further from the truth. In fact, there’s quite a bit of complexity. One of my favorite statements from the APA’s legislative history is a statement from someone in the House of Representatives, a legislator who says, I’ve read this bill and the committee report several times, and I still have no idea what it means, which I feel like is really relatable to my administrative law students. But it is also a very good pithy indication of just how complex the statute is despite its brevity.

 

Now, contradiction number two, when Congress was enacting the APA, it did two things simultaneously. It codified and it reformed. And those things were not sort of separate. They were very much integrated into each other. So in terms of codification, Congress was informed by a vast body of administrative law doctrine; pre-APA judicial decisions, fleshing out the meaning of the due process clause in a way that feels actually quite unrecognizable for those of us who are familiar with Mathews v. Eldridge; pre-APA judicial decisions defining the scope and availability of judicial review, as well as the voluminous research of the attorney general’s committee into the actual procedures and practices of administrative agencies under the statutes that Congress had previously enacted and under the judicial case law that I previously mentioned.

 

And to a substantial extent, Congress codified a lot of that. It drew on the concepts in defining the sort of all important categories of rulemaking and adjudication that really finds its roots in pre-APA due process case law as well as in statutes and administrative practices. And it codified and used a lot of sort of the terms and the best practices that were found in administrative agencies. But at the same time, it reformed.

 

Congress didn’t enact the APA just to applaud agencies and courts on a job well done. Like, we’re going to codify all this awesome stuff you’ve done. They also sought to reform it. So a lot of the agencies were doing good things that were codified in the APA, and a lot of agencies were doing things that Congress thought were serious problems and that the APA was intended to correct by extending to those problematic agencies the codified good practices of other agencies.

 

And so you really have to have, I think, a pretty sophisticated understanding of the pre-APA landscape in order to kind of pull apart which parts of the APA are codification and which parts are reform. And any time you hear someone simply say, well, it just codified what the courts were doing pre-APA, a little red flag should go up because Congress wasn’t just doing that. It was also reforming.

 

My third contradiction is that the APA is a legislative specification of the rules of judicial review and of the procedural rules that agencies have to follow. But it was also intended to be a framework that would be durable for the future and that would apply across agencies. And Congress meant to do both of those things simultaneously. And what that means is that where the statute has clear meaning, it’s mandatory. Courts have to enforce it. Agencies have to conform to it.

 

But it’s a lot of standards, and it was intended to be a flexible structure that would be fleshed out through administrative practices and also through judicial common law. And I think there’s substantial evidence in the legislative history and the research underlying the APA that in fact Congress intended it to be a durable and evolving framework. One clear textual sort of indication of that is in Section 559 which says that future statutes shall not be interpreted to deviate from the APA unless they do so expressly. That’s not an exact quote, but it’s very close. Congress meant for this to be something that would apply across all agencies and for a long time.

 

Now, the fourth contradiction is a contradiction not in the APA itself but in the challenges the statute presently faces. And that contradiction is that on the one hand administrative law has changed really significantly since 1946. In the words of Anne Joseph O’Connell and Daniel Farber in their excellent law review article on this subject in a significant sense the APA is based on the lost world of administrative law that existed during the New Deal period.

 

On the other hand and at the same time, an awful lot of administration on the ground has not changed since 1946. The structure of adjudication is the same. The needs and the demands of procedures and administrative hearings and judicial type hearings conducted by administrative agencies are the same. And agencies do an awful lot of adjudication. We just don’t spend that much time paying attention to it. Why? Because of what Professor Levin sort of acknowledged which is that shift from adjudication to rulemaking as the preferred means of policymaking in the administrative state during the ‘60s and ‘70s.

 

Now, part of that was a shift of existing agencies, but more of it was a shift in terms of Congress creating new agencies, giving new regulatory authorities, but not getting rid of pre-existing authorities and requirements for agencies to adjudicate. Administrative law, however, really changed its focus. And today, administrative law sort of defines itself as a field primarily by reference to precedents that come out of judicial review of pretty significant policymaking through legislative rulemaking by agencies. And the landscape of administrative law, if that’s going to be your focus, is just very different from the landscape of administrative law that comes if you pay substantial attention to adjudication.

 

But at the same time, adjudication is still happening, and in fact a lot of the agencies that were studied by the attorney generals’ committee they still exist. And they’re still adjudicating, and the statutes under which they are adjudicating have not been amended or have been amended very little since that time.

 

Now, there are lessons that you can sort of draw out of this morass, and they’re different on the adjudication and the rulemaking side. I’m going to be very brief, but I’m happy to get more concrete during the conversation. On the adjudication side, you can’t understand the adjudication provisions or their applicability unless you understand the pre-APA due process case law and administrative practices that informed that part of the statute.

 

Today, we have a three-way circuit split in terms of approaches to sort of interpreting and applying Section 554’s reference to hearings on the record. If you read the history of the APA and the pre-APA due process case law, the meaning of that term becomes immediately obvious. And if you understand the placement of a hearing in the adjudicatory process, it becomes immediately obvious.

 

I think over time we’ve lost a lot of that knowledge, that knowledge of the due process case law as it existed when the APA was enacted, a lot of understanding about what adjudication is and how it is structured and how it operates, because that’s not what we focus on. And as the legal profession and judges have lost that knowledge, they’ve lost the ability, I think, to clearly understand what the application of the APA’s hearing provisions is.

 

On the rulemaking side, the situation’s actually very different because rulemaking is really different than it was during the New Deal era. And at the same time, the APA’s rulemaking provisions were sort of inspired by some agencies practices, but they were less codification and more sort of creative development of minimum procedural requirements with the expectation that further detail would be fleshed out by administrative agencies as they implemented those minimum procedural requirements and by the courts as they reviewed as Section 706 requires them to do to enforce the procedural requirements of the APA. So to a substantial extent, I think the expectation of Congress was that especially when it comes to the rulemaking provisions there would be in part through judicial review and in part through agency procedural discretion a development of notice and comment beyond the 143 words that appear in the statute. And I’ll end there, and I look forward to the rest of the conversation.

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi:  Can I just ask because I can’t resist but because Ron ended on this provocative note about maybe if we don’t do APA originalism it might lead us to reconsider constitutional originalism? Some of the arguments you make about the APA being brief, being a reform and a codification, being a framework that’s supposed to last and so on are arguments you both make about the Constitution, too.

 

But then maybe a last point you make about what Congress’s actual intent about being filled out might point in a different direction. So are these arguments that you think apply to originalism in general, or is there something distinctive about the APA where the methodology is not appropriate?

 

Prof. Emily Bremer:  So I live and breath APA, and I give much less attention than probably ever single person in this room to constitutional originalism. My suspicion is that it does sort of mirror it in the sense that of course the history matters, and of course the law also has to accommodate evolution. And I do think we have to be able to hold those two ideas in our head at the same time if we want to have a durable regime, and I don’t think it’s necessarily an indictment of originalism to say that broad-based standards intended to be durable can have application to new scenarios in ways that probably weren’t anticipated at the time the document was enacted.

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi:  Okay. Thank you very much, Professor Bremer. Mr. Tutt.

 

Andrew Tutt:  Okay. The mic is on. Good. Thank you. Thank you for having me today. For those who’ve seen me speak in the past, I know there’s an expectation that I will start with a few lawyer jokes, but I’ve stopped doing that. The lawyers in the audience didn’t think they were funny, and the non lawyers didn’t think they were jokes. (Laughter)

 

But seriously, we’re here today to talk about the interplay between originalism, textualism, and the APA. The issue of the right way to interpret the APA’s been around as long as we’ve had the APA. In his opinion for the Court in Wong Yang Sung v. McGrath in 1950, for example, Justice Robert Jackson characterized the Court’s role in construing the APA as being “so far as the terms of the act warrant, to give affect to its remedial purposes where the evils it was aimed at appear.”

 

My thesis this afternoon is twofold: first that the APA has long been construed in the purpose and manner Justice Jackson suggested in Wong Yang Sung and second that as a result the APA’s in a good place. The glosses the courts have placed on the APA have been appropriate, indeed necessary, to achieving its aims of ensuring the substantive correctness of administrative outcomes and safeguarding the legitimacy of agency action in a nation where ever more decisions of ever greater importance are entrusted to administrative agencies.

 

So let me start by substantiating my first claim that the APA has not been construed according to the originally expected meaning of its originally enacted text. And to do that, I have to go back and explain a bit of the history of administrative law. And the right place to begin, I think, is a 1978 article by then University of Chicago law professor Antonin Scalia entitled “Vermont Yankee: The APA, the D.C. Circuit, and the Supreme Court.”

 

As Professor Scalia explained in his article when the APA was enacted adjudication, not rulemaking, was where the action was in administrative law. Adjudication was how administrative law was done for the first 150 years before the APA. And the dramatic expansion of the administrative state brought about by the New Deal did not change that. Rulemaking by agencies played only a minor role in New Deal Administration. There were exceptions to be sure, but the vast majority of agencies acted primarily through adjudications: the ICC, the FTC, the NLRB, the FPC, the SSA, the FCC, the SEC, the Civil Aeronautics Administration. I could go on. There are literally dozens. All do their work primarily through adjudication.

 

But in the decades after the APA’s enactment with the Court’s blessing I should add, they abruptly changed course and began to make national policy through rulemaking instead. As Professor Scalia wrote in his 1978 article reflecting on this change, “Perhaps the most notable development in federal government administration during the past two decades is the constant and accelerating flight away from individualized adjudicatory proceedings to generalized disposition through rulemaking.” And as Professor Scalia documented in his article, though anyone who reads the APA can see for themselves, the APA was not designed for the use of legislative rulemaking, rulemaking that would set national policy for many parties at once all with the force and effect of law, in any kind of serious way.

 

To respond to the profusion of rulemaking, Professor Scalia explained, the D.C. Circuit tried to fix the APA through interpretation. In a series of decisions through the 1960s and ‘70s, the D.C. Circuit layered onto rulemaking ever greater procedural requirements. But that project abruptly ended when Justice Rehnquist and the unanimous Supreme Court in Vermont Yankee issued a sweeping rebuke of the D.C. Circuit’s project. In Vermont Yankee, the Supreme Court held that agencies engaged in informal rulemaking, no matter its breadth or importance or complexity, do not need to do more than offer up the proposed rule for comment and respond to the comments as required by 5 U.S.C. § 553.

 

Vermont Yankee was a triumph of textualist originalism. Yet Professor Scalia’s praise for the opinion was decidedly less than enthusiastic. He wrote, “There seems to me little to be said for the Supreme Court’s assumption that its Vermont Yankee opinion represents a firm adherence to the settlement of the APA. That is so only if one considers the APA’s abstract principles rather than the concrete dispositions it was expected to produce and then only if one considers those principles in isolation from related assumptions which the Supreme Court itself has since drastically altered. It is ironic but true that the D.C. Circuit’s irreverent approach to the text of the APA served to render the nature of agency resolution of particular cases and the nature of judicial review closer to what was the expectation in 1946.

 

“The Court was, in a sense, restoring the balance which the Supreme Court” -- this is all the quote -- “consistent approval of the contrivance of more expeditious administrative methods had upset.” He says, “I think it is more than coincidental that a high proportion of the D.C. Circuit cases imposing extra APA requirements involved precisely instances in which agencies had sought to transfer traditionally adjudicated issues into rulemaking.” He continued a little bit later, “On that view of things, one might plausibly assert that the courts had a positive obligation to reinterpret the statute in order to prevent their own actions from subverting its basic intent.”

 

Again, for those planning to write me angry letters, that is a verbatim quote from Professor Scalia’s article. And of course notwithstanding Vermont Yankee’s proclamation of fidelity to the APA’s original text and meaning, in fact Vermont Yankee is the exception that proves the rule. The courts, both the D.C. Circuit and Supreme Court varieties, not to mention Congress itself, have never liked that the APA does such a horrendous job policing rulemaking. Thus notwithstanding Vermont Yankee’s insistence that agencies need to do no more than what 553 requires, the courts have long read into 553 far more than it was intended to require.

 

Section 553 says it requires only that the agency shall incorporate in the rules adopted a “concise general statement of their basis and purpose.” There is no doubt that the burden meant to be imposed by that provision was minimal. The 1947 Attorney General’s Manual on the Administrative Procedure Act literally says that no “elaborate analysis of the rules or of the considerations upon which the rules were issued are required by this provision.” And in his testimony on the proposed provision, the attorney general described it as serving much the same function as the whereas clauses which are now customarily found in the preambles of executive orders.

 

And as Steve can tell you better than I can, the whereas clauses in those orders are not substantive. Anyway, the D.C. Circuit almost immediately held that agencies are not allowed to take an overly literal interpretation of the provision. And now it’s just accepted that preambles are concise and general in the same way the Bible and Moby Dick are concise and general. In his article, Professor Scalia called the D.C. Circuit’s conversion of the statement of basis and purpose provision into a “requirement that major arguments against a proposed rule be answered” “heresy.” Nevertheless, it persisted.

 

And the APA is shot through with examples of these judicial glosses. Judge Wald attributed Judge Leventhal’s invention of the concept of hard look review to “the shear massiveness of the impact of the urgent regulations issued under the new rulemaking provisions in the APA and the diffidence of judges in the face of highly technical regulatory regimes. Professor Sam Bray has posited the rise of national injunctions, which he traces to a pair of opinions by Judge Friendly in the 1970s, is also possibly attributable to the rise of the agency rulemaking.

 

So is all this gloss on the APA a good thing? When we have an old statute like the APA, should judges and lawyers in Justice Scalia’s words maintain “strict judicial adherence to statutory text?” Or should they in Justice Jackson’s words construe it “to give affect to its remedial purposes”? The question is a hard one.

 

On the one hand, one might think a court’s role is to interpret, not to make the law. And one might think that in the realm of statutory law where Congress can correct any error following the APA’s original meaning would do little harm without sacrificing fidelity to textualism. On the other hand, one might think for this specific statute that too many have relied for too long on the judicially glossed version of the language for us to change our approach now. Or one might think especially given the quasi constitutional ends of the statute and its ludicrously capacious language that Congress intended for the courts to take an activist constructive role in its development and evolution.

 

My own view is that we can take a page out of the major questions playbook or at least draw an analogy. Many subscribers to that doctrine view it as at least partially compelled by what the Constitution itself demands, and while Congress could theoretically delegate the resolution of major questions to the Executive Branch by forcefully telling the Supreme Court in a statute that it does indeed want major questions to be resolved by agencies, even where the actions of the agency seem both extraordinary and unintended, until it does so the thumb is going to be on the scale against that view. The APA itself is a statute like any other, and many of the glossiest glosses on the APA are tinged with a major questions flavor.

 

For those who support the major questions doctrine, as I do, I think to take the bitter with the sweet we must also accept that there’s a fair bit of room to interpret the ambiguities in the APA in favor of certain constitutional values. Just as the major questions doctrine protects Congress’s role as law maker, the glosses on the APA seem to protect other important constitutional values. All I can say at bottom is that at least with Scalia on one side and Jackson on the other, whether you choose a textualist or a purposive approach, whichever side you choose you’re in good company. Thank you.

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi: Can I ask, because I’m throwing in some questions after comments, so you talk about these glosses that are consistent with maybe some of the values of the APA? There’s some critiques about the accretions of additional procedural requirements and so on. One is that it leads to agency ossification, that the agency is burdened by all these extra procedures and lacks the flexibility that maybe it should rightfully have to do policymaking. Another one is that some of these doctrines lead to kind of arbitrariness in judicial review.

 

Like if you’re evaluating whether the agency has done reasoned decision making or if something’s a logical outgrowth or if there’s adequate response to comments, you addressed every problem, courts can reach very different conclusions about that because it’s often very subjective. And maybe it would be better if we had a system where there was a lot of deference to policymaking and process but not a lot on legal questions -- on the legal framework. So do either of those critiques have some purchase as a reason why we might want to cut back on some of the judicial glosses?

 

Andrew Tutt:  Well, I think they have a lot of purchase, and that’s why if you’re going to locate I think for me the legitimacy of constructive judicial interpretation, you have to locate it in something beyond just sort of would it be better policy to do rulemaking one way or the other. You have to be construing the Constitution in some way. Maybe it’s because you think that you’re sort of adapting the statutory construction to some important constitutional aim. But to this point about ossification, that’s a classic policy question that should be resolved by Congress. So I’m not sure if that’s helpful, but that’s kind of how I think about it.

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi:  Okay. Well, thanks. Thank you, Mr. Tutt. Mr. Bradbury.

 

Hon. Steven Bradbury:  Thank you. Thank you, judge. Great to be here. I guess it falls to me to be the skunk at the APA garden party. I think our system of agency rulemaking is seriously broken. I think the administrative train has jumped the tracks and is bumping across the field, going places that we never could’ve imagined. Certainly, the Congress that enacted the APA in 1946 I believe never could’ve imagined agencies would take their power.

 

We see vast new rulemakings reaching into areas that the Congresses that enacted the substantive statutes never contemplated, and we see swings in administrative policy from one administration to another that are as radical as they could be, 180 degree shifts. And these shifts in administrative policymaking through rules have enormous economic impacts on the country, across all sectors, sometimes in one sector vast economic dislocations.

 

So how did we get here, and what’s the next step? Because I do believe that we’re at a watershed time in administrative law that call it what you will, whatever analogy you want, metaphor, it’s an inflection point. The Court is going to consider -- I think there’s a strong chance it will repudiate Chevron deference this term. But that’s seriously up for grabs at the Court, obviously.

 

Congress has been considering a very major structural change in the whole approach to agency power through the REINS Act, the Regulations from the Executive in Need of Scrutiny Act, which has passed the House. And then there’s the major questions doctrine where the Supreme Court has addressed in a number of different contexts agency efforts to take old statutes that had settled meanings and settled understanding about their scope and apply them in entirely new ways to entirely new issues and problems that the Congress that enacted the statute never had in mind for that statute.

 

And so I think these are symptoms of the problem we face and that there is a dire need for a major structural reset in the whole scheme of administrative power. Back in 1946 when Congress enacted the APA, I think Ron has done great work as have others, Emily certainly, in laying out kind of what the landscape was like then. The country had reached a point in the 1940s where there was a general acceptance of this huge new enterprise of administrative power coming out of the New Deal. And the Supreme Court in its opinions in the ‘40s began to empower that machine, that rulemaking machine.

 

There was a general feeling that this was a good enterprise, that it had value and should be promoted. And so Congress adopted a framework for advancing the effectiveness of agency exercises of power through the APA, and I think that was a general consensus at the time. In the years since things tipped one way or the other, as Andrew described, you had Judge David Bazelon and Judge Skelly Wright in the D.C. Circuit getting fixed into judge made doctrines about what statutes would allow for in terms of interpretation. And you got yourself in a position where, for example, with the bubble concept D.C. Circuit under its own interpretation of the purposes of the Clean Air Act concluded that, well, the bubble rule was required in attainment areas but prohibited in nonattainment areas. So the same term elicited from the court a conclusion that a certain approach was required in one context and prohibited in another.

 

And so that was of course slapped down in the Chevron case in 1984, probably Justice Stevens’s most influential opinion ever, I think. And that was actually if you recall at the time -- some of you may recall at the time that was applauded by the Reagan administration. On the other side of that case was Justice Gorsuch’s mother, Anne Gorsuch, head of the EPA in the Reagan administration, because the Reagan administration wanted to interpret that term to allow for the bubble rule in concepts where Skelly Wright had said no. And actually Justice Ginsburg, then Judge Ginsburg, wrote the opinion below in that case.

 

And I think that generally reflected a consensus that the court imposing its will in terms of what statutes mean on agencies could gore everybody’s ox at one time or another, and so we needed a new national consensus that the agencies needed more leeway to do their job. And that became a kind of settled view. And so now in the many years since 1984, Congress has certainly gotten used to the notion that there’s a broad scope of policymaking discretion in agencies and their ability to interpret their statutes substantively for purposes of rulemaking. And boy have the agencies run wild with that.

 

Ron has focused on the judge made rules that have grown up since 1946 to provide additional procedural protections in the rulemaking process which have the benefit of giving petitioners, challengers to rules more triggers, more hooks to focus on. That can be a good thing, but I don’t think it’s really made much of a difference at the end of the day. These agencies hire outside experts, contractors, kind of like parties who hire economic experts or other technical experts, and they write two, three, four, 500 page regulatory impact analyses and huge preambles with detailed analysis and oh, boy, the language sounds reasonable.

 

And they kill you to death with paper. And so when you go into court on a court of appeals, you’re not going to be able to raise 225 different issues with all the problems in that 1,000 page rulemaking. Inevitably, it’s going to come down to one or two major issues of focus for the court. So you’re really not getting an opportunity to take advantage of those protections.

 

And then the scope of discretion allows what we’ve seen. So in the Clean Power Plan, EPA tried to change the whole electricity generation model for the whole country, something Congress never contemplated. With the tailpipe rules now that the EPA is issuing for new vehicle emissions standards, they’re doing the exact same thing, setting standards that cannot be met by gas powered cars and setting them on an average basis for a fleet of vehicles to force the whole industry to shift to the manufacture and sale of electric vehicles at precisely the percentage that the administration as a political matter wants to achieve.

 

So this is obviously massive legislative power that Congress is the only one who should be exercising under our Constitution. And so you see the court reacting now with the major questions doctrine, quite a natural reaction, and Chevron deference in the gun sights. And so here we are with the end of the Biden administration, which in the age of the climate change crisis where they’re now trying to regulate out of existence carbon dioxide emissions. Well, if you’re going to do that, right there that hands administrative agencies the most pervasive power you can imagine. From the sky to the ground, everything, every economic activity involves carbon dioxide emissions.

 

So they can just do almost anything. And in light of that now Chevron. And if Chevron goes away and we come in with a new conservative administration in the future, there you go. Now we don’t have Chevron, and what you’re going to see probably in the D.C. Circuit is full Bazelon all over again. And then there’ll have to be some equilibrium. And so if Chevron doesn’t go away, I think that both sides’ ox will be gored again by this radical swing in policymaking.

 

And perhaps the Senate would actually get some traction in considering the REINS Act because that is a structural solution. The REINS Act every major rule would not go into effect until Congress passes a joint resolution signed by the president to authorize it to go into effect, clearly a structural solution to the problems we face. So how about that? Thank you very much.

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi:  So it sounded like you were making some point in favor of APA originalism that a lot of the additional procedural protections and additions to process were not actually that beneficial because the agencies bury you in paper and so on. And maybe something about going back to the APA would be a benefit, which is to have the courts decide questions of law. Some people think that Chevron deference is inconsistent with Section 706 which says courts decide questions of law. I guess that’s debated, but that’s an idea.

 

Hon. Steven Bradbury:  Yes.

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi:  But then you said after Chevron, we’re going to have full Bazelon, which might not actually -- I guess it does provide accountability in a way, but is it desirable? So what do you see as the change?

 

Hon. Steven Bradbury:  Well, I think it’s almost inevitable in this sense. If we do go -- and I was talking to Ron before the panel that Paul Clement in his brief in Loper Bright says five justices have already signed onto the proposition that 706 requires de novo review by courts of all questions of law. In two different opinions, two concurring opinions by Justice Gorsuch you get a total of five justices on the Court who’ve agreed to that proposition. So it’s already game over according to Paul in his brief.

 

But if you do that, then, okay, what does that mean, de novo review? Well, courts are going to develop doctrines. They’re going to be interpreting terms, and then they, the D.C. Circuit -- it’s really the D.C. Circuit generally speaking -- and the D.C. Circuit’s going to be --

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi:  We get some, you know.

 

Hon. Steven Bradbury:  I know. Sorry. But the D.C. Circuit gets bound by its own precedent. So you got a doctrine. It gets entrenched, but that is the way court decisions work. And if maybe Justice Kavanaugh, Justice Gorsuch, Justice Thomas, maybe others go back to a Vermont Yankee trimmed down originalist or textualist -- let’s say textualist application of the APA so some of these other protections go away, well, then the agencies have their flexibility. They can do the rulemaking.

 

I like Emily’s idea of maybe emphasizing more formal adjudication again. Maybe that will develop. But then the courts, they’ll have to deal with established judge made doctrine in terms of what the law requires under a particular statute. So there will be less room on substance in the ultimate substantive interpretation of the statute to swing radically and bring this ship which was intended for these kinds of pollutants and chemicals and apply it to carbon dioxide, which makes absolutely no sense in this scheme, which they’ve been trying to do. And maybe they just won’t be able to do that, but they’ll have more flexibility in terms of process.

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi:  And just to fit into the debate of the panel, it sounds like you think that’s a beneficial change, and it is a kind of return to original envision of the APA.

 

Hon. Steven Bradbury:  It’s consistent with textualism. It’s consistent with the role of courts in addressing questions of law, and I think more practically speaking it’s where I see probably a majority of the Court. So I think that’s where we’re heading, and then we’ll just see if it shakes out in a way that is acceptable to the political culture in Washington on both sides of the aisle. And if not, then I think the REINS Act will perhaps come back as a possibility.

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi:  So thanks very much. Before we get to questions from the audience, I want to give the panel an opportunity to react to some of these ideas about possible reforms. So we talked about changes, getting rid of Chevron deference, which the Court might do, the REINS Act, which Congress might do; the development of the major questions doctrine. And so just to have some comment of what’s on the horizon, why don’t we go down the panel again? So Professor Levin.

 

Prof. Ronald M. Levin:  Yeah. I’ve got my skunk extermination points ready to go. I just don’t know how many I can work in in the limited time we have available here. Okay. We could start with the REINS Act, which in substance means that not only are we going to have paralysis in Congress but also paralysis in the rulemaking process because Congress would have to sign off on any major rule. So it’s bad enough that we aren’t getting legislation to deal with today’s social problems, but the Executive Branch would be hobbled as well.

 

That’s just with a dysfunctional Congress, but even with an ordinary Congress, the House and the Senate would have to agree on the exact text that the agency put forward, no limits allowed. And then it would have to survive judicial review too. Essentially, you’re killing all rules of consequence. This looks good to people in this audience, to the Heritage Foundation, but it is a sign of the pulverized nature of our times that views of that kind look credible to some portion of society and anathema to others.

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi:  Can I ask something about that?

 

Prof. Ronald M. Levin:  Yeah.

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi:  So does it have to be a paralysis in Congress? So in a way it’s difficult for Congress to get together and pass actual legislation, but if all of the proposals came out of the agencies and then Congress just had to do an up or down vote on whether they liked it or not, might that not make Congress’s job easier if they just had an agenda of votes to take on already baked in proposals?

 

Prof. Ronald M. Levin:  No, it would not. This is another subject on which Assistant Attorney General Scalia was eloquent, and you can read the quotes from him in my compelling article on the REINS Act. No, it wouldn’t be easier because you’d have to agree on the exact text, and if you then agree through political compromise on something, it may be something that would not stand up on judicial review. And so the process of getting agreement among all the parties -- and again, it would have to be agreement on the exact text. Usually in Congress you make a deal. The House and the Senate agree on some middle ground. You can’t do it with the REINS Act. So it is not feasible even with a functional Congress, let alone the one we’ve got.

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi:  All right. Thanks very much. Professor Bremer.

 

Prof. Emily Bremer:  So I just want to make two points. One is I’m going to disagree with everybody—go big or go home—about the idea that the administrative common law fleshing out 553 is contrary to the text and would be rejected from an originalist perspective. I just think that’s wrong. The APA says that agencies are required to give people, the public, an opportunity to participate in the rulemaking. And so a lot of these requirements are easily located in that text.

 

If the agency doesn’t provide the privately developed, like in house research, on which its rule is based to the public, how can anybody have an opportunity to participate in the rulemaking? Right? Section 553 requires that agencies consider comments. You don’t just take comments. You have to consider them. I always think of the Seinfeld episode where he goes to rent a car, and they’re like, well, we don’t have any cars. Well, you have the reservation? Anybody can just take reservations. You have to hold the reservations. Anybody can just take comments. You have to consider the comments.

 

And how does a court know to do its duty under 706 which says that courts shall set aside agency action that’s inconsistent with procedural requirements? How can you know if the agency considered the comments if it doesn’t respond to the comments at least briefly in a concise statement of basis and purpose? I could go on, but I just think the case that this is all just totally law making with no grounding in the text is just wrong.

 

And then the other point I’ll make is on Chevron, and my question with the debate over Chevron is always the same. We talk about Chevron as this monolith, as this single thing, and we all know exactly what it is and what its consequences are and how its done. But which Chevron? There’s the Chevron of a judge who glances at the statute and says, eh, doesn’t seem obvious what that means to me, so I’ll just defer. And then there’s Chevron by a footnote 9 kind of guy in Justice Kavanaugh’s words who really does a pretty serious step one analysis that’s a de novo review before deferring at step two where the agency’s interpretation is within the bounds of the statute and has been adequately explained and survives arbitrary and capricious review.

 

So I think the Court could actually do quite a bit more good by retaining Chevron but giving the lower courts guidance, preferably not in a single opinion that sort of gathers everything together like Kaiser did but in actually taking cases and applying Chevron. And I think you could do a lot to tighten that doctrine up in a way that would solve a lot of the problems and the critiques of Chevron without creating another area where we’re sort of left bereft of a framework for a couple of decades before we sort of figure out what we’re doing.

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi:  Thanks very much. Andrew.

 

Andrew Tutt:  So I’ll just be brief. So to defend my view that 553 has been construed in an -- 5 U.S.C. § 553, sorry, has been construed in a non original way, I would just look at the text of the provision that just says they have to give notice and an opportunity for comment. And sort of in terms of whether or not there was going to be all of this extra sort of obligation on the agency to respond to meaningful comments, we can use various methods of interpretation to sort of figure out what was intended by this.

 

So I’ve got the Attorney General’s manual saying we were just going to treat the response to the comments as like whereas, this is important, therefore, the rule. Courts obviously wanted to make sure that certain really important values were protected, so I feel like I’m arguing against myself a little bit here. And so they said, well, we can’t do our job of reviewing this in a meaningful way unless you give us more.

 

But all over administrative law they get this presumption of regularity, so it’s really just where are you going to start the presumption of regularity. If you start it at an early enough step of well, they said they considered the comments, what more do you want, that seems to be how they actually thought about it based on, again, the legislative history that I’ve sort of looked at.

 

On Chevron, on terms of what kind of Chevron, I like the major questions doctrine limitation on Chevron. If you think you have sort of Chevron stays the law, maybe we get rid of Chevron for gaps in statutes, which has always been kind of a weird place for Chevron to be operating -- like, there’s something not in the statute, and the agency says, well, that means it’s ambiguous. I guess I can add it to the statute. That’s always been kind of an abuse of Chevron. That seems like it might be at stake in the Loper case. There just isn’t anything in the statute that they’re interpreting. In Chevron, you’re interpreting the words “stationary source,” so what is a stationary source? Reasonable minds can disagree, so that’s why you’ve kind of got Chevron. So those would be my kind of views on that. I don’t know.

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi:  Steve, do you have a final comment.

 

Hon. Steven Bradbury:  I’ll just go back to the REINS Act, Ron. It would get Congress back in the game. Right now, Congress is just quiescent. They just let the Executive Branch run wild. They decide not to take on the biggest issues that potentially are threatening our entire planet, the climate change crisis. And our elected representatives in Congress have not addressed that issue. They’ve not decided is this really the road we need to go down, and if so, how are we going to address it as a nation? They’ve thrown money at projects, but that’s about it.

 

Meanwhile, almost every agency of the Executive Branch in this administration is doing momentous policymaking to push vast sectors of the economy, dislocate economic relationships left, right, and center to push us toward a regulatory solution to this huge problem that Congress has never taken on, never thought about, never voted on. So at least forcing them to do an up or down vote on rules gets them in the game. And if they don’t like the rule, Ron, and they want to change it, they always have the ability to, hello, do legislation of their own, get their act together. So that’s --

 

Prof. Ronald M. Levin:  I just want to add that there were actual studies of state legislative veto schemes, and Hal Bruff and Ernie Gellhorn found that they discourage legislatures from making decisions on their own because they say oh, we’ve got this legislative scheme. We can just turn it over to the agency and we’ll be able to decide later. That makes them less likely to make the decision at the front end.

 

Hon. Steven Bradbury:  Yeah. That’s exactly what they’ve been doing now for the last --

 

Prof. Ronald M. Levin:  No, that’s what would happen if they have the ability to --

 

Hon. Steven Bradbury:  But that’s what Congress has been doing.

 

Prof. Ronald M. Levin:  -- say oh, we’ll decide it later.

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi:  I think we have both perspectives on that. We have some people lined up to ask questions, so why don’t we start hearing from the audience. So let’s go to this microphone first.

 

Mario Loyola:  Hi, Mario Loyola. I had the enormous fortune to have Professor Levin for not one but two classes in law school, and that was awesome. And thank you. One of which was administrative law.

 

When I first got to the White House in early 2017, one of the first conversations I had I walked into the office of a very senior advisor to the president and said, why don’t we push -- this is a great time to push for the REINS Act. Why don’t we do it now? Surly we can find ten Democrats that will vote to restrain the power of the dreaded President Trump? And he said -- and the response was, no, you will not find one.

 

Because why? Because it would restrain future. And he pointed out to me that we would now want to undo by rulemaking a bunch of rulemakings that we hate, and if we put a REINS Act in, then we can’t do that. And so I think that it’s very difficult to image how -- it would be great if you could convince them.

 

But I guess my question is the animus for this whole desire to see something like the REINS Act is coming from a real concern about an increasingly unbridled administrative state. Patrick Henry railed against the proposed constitution because he said it would become a big consolidation of government, and a lot of people now think that that is what is happening. And so Justice Gorsuch has been writing what amounts to a lengthy Wikipedia article over several concurrences on nondelegation doctrine. So I would ask Professor Levin, are you worried about the increasing consolidation of power in the Executive Branch, and is there a workable nondelegation principle that could restrain that in the courts?

 

Prof. Ronald M. Levin:  First of all, Mario has had a very successful career in conservative public policy advocacy, which really shows you how much of an impact I have. So I don’t think nondelegation doctrine revival is an answer because -- for the same reason it’s been rejected for the last century or two, which is there are no ascertainable criteria for deciding which ones should be upheld and which not. That has always been one of the serious problems with any kind of judicial implementation. The same is true, of course, with the major questions doctrine where there’s just no way to decide in any objective way which ones are major and which ones are not, which may be why the Supreme Court has not given even a hint of where they would draw the line because there isn’t a good line.

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi:  We’ve lost -- oh, this microphone we’ll turn to.

 

Questioner 2:  My question is for Professor Bremer and Mr. Bradbury. Professor Bremer, you used the term “judicial common law,” but federal courts are not common law courts. State courts are, and that also voids to -- they don’t have the same law making power. And with respect to Mr. Bradbury, you said that agencies have assumed massive legislative power, and that links the common law court versus massive -- I’d like you both to comment on it.

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi:  Why don’t we take those in order, first on the common law question?

 

Prof. Emily Bremer:  The reality is we have an enormous amount of federal common law. It’s not general law. It’s not law of torts and contracts and the like, but it is law under statutes and law under the Constitution. I don’t think you can have courts deciding cases and have a system of understanding the law through precedent without inevitably having some degree of common law emerging from the judicial process. The other thing is -- and we don’t have time for this conversation here, but I teach civil procedure too. And I will say I would be open to the conversation about whether Erie was rightly decided.

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi:  Okay. We’ve got some Swift v. Tyson folks. Okay. Steve.

 

Hon. Steven Bradbury:  In terms of legislative power, I don’t think there’s any doubt that agencies in the current administrative state are exercising vast legislative power. Now, is that consistent with our Constitution? The beginning of Article I of the Constitution says “all legislative power of the federal government shall be vested in the Congress.”

 

 At the same time, clearly if an agency is administering a statute as an incident of executive power to administer and carry out the law, the agency has to interpret the law. The Executive Branch must have it’s own interpretation of the law to understand what it believes the law requires in order to carry out that law. And a fundamental part of that is defining terms.

 

So inevitably you get to an exercise of interpretation in the exercise of executive power, and then when courts are confronted with that agency’s interpretation, the question is whether to respect it. How much respect is it due? Skidmore respect, for example, is the agency technically experienced with that industry? Is it closer to the facts? Does it know how those chemicals interact the way a generalist court isn’t really going to be in a position to do? In which case, it may be fully appropriate to recognize that interpretation and give it great respect as the courts have consistently said. But we’re way beyond that now.

 

Now with Chevron it’s really just a question when the agencies embark on rulemaking, this is just the way it really works. As a policymaker and a general counsel, I tried to tell the agencies, no, our job is to determine what we think is the best interpretation of the statute and stay within those bounds. But the natural inclination of the regulators under Chevron is not to do that.

 

It’s to say what is the limit of a reasonable interpretation? How far can we go and what’s your policy objective in this administration? Okay. So let’s go as far as we can, right to the edge of what we think the D.C. Circuit or another court, sometimes the Second Circuit I suppose, but usually the D.C. Circuit will allow you to do. And that is not a healthy way to do -- for the Executive Branch to undertake its administrative authority.

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi:  Thanks very much. Let’s go to this microphone here.

 

Art Macomber:  Yes. Thank you. Art Macomber from the common law state of Idaho, and I’m trying to square the circle here. We just spent 5- to 600 years clarifying when the Executive can make the law, enforce the law, and adjudicate the law by cutting back on the king’s prerogative to the point where we got this thing called the Constitution. And here we actually wrote it down with the separation of powers. And now I’m faced with some 1,500 ALJs in the Executive Branch, and I’m wondering are they really Article III judges.

 

Did Congress really say the inferior courts that we’re creating to the Supreme Court under Article III we’re going to put into the Executive Branch? Did they actually have the power to do that? I don’t see that in the document, so I’m very confused.

 

And I’m wondering -- I understand Professor Levin about sclerosis of the government. Many of us in Idaho would agree that it’s muscle bound and it needs to be cut back. But where do you start? How do you do that? Is the REINS Act even going to be sufficient?

 

But getting back to the core document, how do we even justify the APA? Where did Congress get this power to slice off a piece of the Judiciary and give it to the Executive -- slice off a piece of its legislative power and give it to the Executive? And everybody wonders why the Executive power is so strong. I am just -- I’m going to go back to Idaho where it’s safe. But what is going on here? What is happening?

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi:  Would anyone like to take that on?

 

Prof. Emily Bremer:  Can I?

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi:  Yeah. Go ahead.

 

Prof. Emily Bremer:  So I don’t think this is the APA’s fault, and I don’t think the solution is the REINS Act, although maybe not for any of the reasons that Professor Levin identified. You need Congress to do its job. If the problem is Congress has -- if Congress has delegated too much power, the solution to that is for Congress to rewrite the substantive statutes in a way that doesn’t delegate too much power. And trying to solve this problem through procedural rules strikes me as indirect and unlikely to be successful and a whole lot of heat and noise that is not really addressing the actual problem. So I think one thing you have to do is you have to convince Congress. I don’t know how you do that. Fortunately, that’s not my job.

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi:  Anybody else? It was a pretty broad statement, so I thought I’d invite --

 

Hon. Steven Bradbury:  Yeah. To react to Emily’s point, look at these rulemakings that these agencies are doing. You’re never going to get 60 votes in the Senate to do what they’re doing. So Congress isn’t in a position -- isn’t likely to take that on and move that regulatory policy forward in that way. But 50 percent, what’s the more easy solution?

 

As Paul Clement says in his briefs in Loper Bright, at any one time 50 percent of the members of Congress have friends in the Executive Branch. And they can just pick up the phone and talk to the agencies and get the agencies to do what they would like to do by legislation that they’re not going to be able to get through the 60 vote margin in the Senate. And that’s really where we are.

 

And so Congress never takes on these huge vastly important economic questions, or rarely does, and the REINS Act would force them to do the vote. But I’m not delusional. I’m not predicting the REINS Act is going to pass the Senate, but I do think that there’s a prospect of that currently.

 

But if the Supreme Court stands by Chevron and doesn’t repudiate Chevron deference, then I think there is potential opportunity because you are going to continue to see these vast 180 degree swings in regulatory policy between administrations of different parties. And that is going to gore each side’s ox. And when that situation happens and becomes more acute, that’s when Congress tends historically to come to a new structural solution, and potentially something like the REINS Act or some new balance could be struck.

 

If Chevron is thrown out, maybe then that will address the problem sufficiently, along with other reconsiderations of judge-made interpretations of the APA. And then maybe we can reach an equilibrium that way and we won’t need some major new structural legislation from Congress. That’s the way I see it.

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi:  [CROSSTALK 01:12:14] response?

 

Prof. Ronald M. Levin:  Well, I wanted to respond a little more directly to our speaker from Idaho because I think the most direct answer here is this is a really big country, 230 million people, a really complex society --

 

Hon. Steven Bradbury:  330.

 

Prof. Ronald M. Levin:  Excuse me. I misspoke. I don’t do numbers that well.

 

Hon. Steven Bradbury:  You’re living in the past.

 

Prof. Ronald M. Levin:  But the public expects a wide range of services and actions from it. And that means a lot of governmental decisions have to be made. And there’s only so many that a Congress of 535 people can do, and so inevitably you’re going to get delegations. And no matter whether you keep Chevron at the margins, it’s still going to be true that a lot has been delegated to the Executive Branch to implement.

 

And I agree with so much of what Steve said about there’ll be a necessity of interpreting these mandates along the way. That’s true. And also insofar as authority is granted to the Executive Branch, they have to make decisions about how to do it. And they’re going to put that all in the hands of Article III judges. I think that’s not very practical. So I think you’re dealing here largely with the inevitable results of a big society, and you can’t change that just by saying, oh, the standard review is going to be a little tighter.

 

And sometimes, they’re going to go too far. I agree with that. There are political answers to that. That should be decided presumptively through the political process, not by judicially imposed, ideologically driven clear statement rules such as we’ve seen recently. And I won’t mention the name of it again -- but by the political process. Some of whom live in Idaho and have one view philosophically, and others elsewhere in the country have a different view. But it should be something that the political process decides and not something that we try to hold back with new constitutional doctrines.

 

Prof. Emily Bremer:  Well, can I just --

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi:  Yes.

 

Prof. Emily Bremer:  So what if -- and I’m just spit balling here since we have such a big country. What if we broke it up into smaller areas and -- okay.

 

Matt Bowman:  That was my question.

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi: All right. With that, let’s turn to this microphone over here.

 

Matt Bowman:  Thank you. Matt Bowman with Alliance Defending Freedom. I’d like to ask about implications for standing, the shift from adjudication to rulemaking. Section 702 says a person suffering a legal wrong can seek judicial review, but cases like Transunion suggest that a concrete harm has to exist beyond just Congress’s statement that someone can sue. And so what implications would that or should that have on the court’s interpretation of standing under the APA in light of both in injury from being denied notice and comment or just the injury of being a regulated party who’s now subject to a rule but hasn’t been brought into an adjudication yet?

 

Andrew Tutt:  So not to give any legal advice or anything, but when a rule sort of goes into the federal register and it’s 60 days from going into effect, they give you that 60 days so that you can start to make preparation to comply with whatever’s in the rule. And if that costs you even a nonzero amount of money, you’ve got an immediate imminent injury and so you just go right into court. You could maybe, theoretically. I’m not giving any legal advice.

 

Prof. Ronald M. Levin:  The Transunion case is a controversial case. The Court was very much split. But whatever decision you’re going to reach, I’m sure the one that we don’t want was the concept originally intended by the drafters of the APA, which essentially said that unless there’s a special statutory provision only people whose legal interests are invaded can bring suit. And what that means is the vast majority of people who are affected by an agency -- beneficiaries for example, couldn’t have standing. We’ve moved beyond that because we want the government to be accountable. Y’all want unaccountable government? Fine. Apply Section 702 the way it was originally concepted, and almost nobody could sue for anything.

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi:  Do you think that shift in understanding is part of the transition from adjudication to rulemaking that you had to change the way you saw it because rulemaking is just different, and it’s harder to identify people who were directly aggrieved?

 

Prof. Ronald M. Levin:  Well, I think -- so under current doctrine you have to show some kind of injury, in fact. That’s true. And Transunion is sort of calling that into question. But ever since data processing in 1971 we’ve been looking beyond the minimum of Article III standing.

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi:  Okay. Let’s take another question.

 

Shiza Francis:  Hi, I’m Shiza Francis. I’m a student at Wash U, and I would like to mention that I’ve had Professor Levin four times. And that’s the max of the classes he teaches, so there won’t be a fifth. My question is related to the last question but a little bit more normative of whether Congress can grant Article III standing and how that would basically impact the administrative law apparatus of cases that come before courts. I know there was a debate about it in Professor Levin’s class, so I would like to get the take of the other speakers and Professor Levin, of course.

 

Prof. Ronald M. Levin:  Well, Shiza’s another example of the fact that my knee jerk liberal inclinations do not always come across and sink into the minds of our students. Congress creates standing all the time within the limits of Article III. It says who can sue over a given act and who cannot. The issue this real raises can Congress grant standing where Article III criteria are not met? And that would be transformative, I suppose, but you’d have to get the Supreme Court to go along with it.

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi:  Anyone else?

 

Andrew Tutt:  I mean, no they can’t grant Article III standing by statute. And there’s good reasons for that with respect to the need for the federal courts to decide concrete disputes between parties.

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi:  Okay. Let’s go here.

 

Questioner 6:  Just when we reverse the OSHA ergonomics regulation and I led the coalition on a congressional review act, we blew up on the Senate floor a statement by the person who was leading that effort at OSHA, who was Marthe Kent, who said in a magazine “I don’t know what it is about me. I was just born to regulate. I love to regulate.” And Senator Nichols hit on that mercilessly, and it was very effective.

 

My point is we’re talking a lot of fancy legal principles, but perhaps the real problem to get at the issue of over regulation is change the OPM system the way we hire people such that people don’t spend their whole life in government and therefore develop a certain attitude towards industry, which I would say is antiemployment and anti-industry. Actually, it’s a problem in the civil service system in how we hire people and the fact they can stay their forever, so when we took over in ’94 under Newt, one clever idea I had was people should only stay in the government for ten years. And then they have to get out. Obviously, the Democrats opposed that. Up here instead of looking at these kinds of principles, maybe the solution is down here where these regulations start.

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi:  Thanks very much. Any thoughts on that?

 

Hon. Steven Bradbury:  That should be a different panel, maybe a whole conference.

 

Prof. Emily Bremer:  We need to pay more attention to questions of staffing at the federal government. This is the thing that administrative law probably should pay attention to and mostly doesn’t. On the one hand, I see your point. You don’t want people to be too entrenched. You don’t want them to sort of have blinders on.

 

And at the same time, you want people to have experience and competence, so designing a system that can achieve both of those ends I think is a challenge. I do think, though, that some of the biggest problems we’re talking about here like the 180 degree flips in agency policymaking are not coming from civil servants. They’re coming from the politicals, and they’re coming from sort of the problem at the top as opposed to any problem sort of in the bureaucracy and sort of the day to day officials. So I think that’s a problem that just has to be addressed politically.

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi:  Okay. Let’s go here.

 

Questioner 7:  I think my question is for Professor Levin, and although I never took a course from him, I taught him everything he knows. We were college classmates. He’s forgotten almost all of it since. When you said, Professor Levin, that nondelegation doctrine, that line can never really be drawn -- the major questions doctrine, that line can never really be drawn, it’s too vague. They can never articulate a standard. Aren’t you really saying that this whole business of separating the Legislative and Executive powers in the Constitution, that line can never be drawn and this whole constitutional project doesn’t make any sense?

 

Prof. Ronald M. Levin:  No, I’m saying that those particular tools are not the ones to use. Nondelegation has effectively not been used at all. Major questions doctrine didn’t exist before the current regime. That doesn’t mean that it’s the only possible ways. It means you just have to find ways that are more administrable.

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi:  Well, you have these --

 

Questioner 7: Any suggestions?

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi:  -- suggestions that some other doctrines enforce nondelegation principles. Like the void for vagueness doctrine maybe prevents delegation of unlimited discretion. Cass Sunstein has this article on nondelegation canons, which is about how we interpret statutes to avoid nondelegation problems. So are there ways that you could enforce nondelegation principles without enforcing the doctrine directly, you think?

 

Prof. Ronald M. Levin:  Well, so what he does is to say here are a bunch of principles which I want to call nondelegation principles, but they’re really regulatory principles that I, Cass Sunstein, believe are good ideas.

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi:  Allow me to [inaudible 01:23:17].

 

Prof. Ronald M. Levin:  I mean, that is --

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi:  -- to that article just as an example of like maybe --

 

Prof. Ronald M. Levin:  No, but that is if you read his article critically, that is what it says. But I think really ordinary judicial review exists to find that an agency has exceeded what Congress authorized. I’m all for that. We can even change how we frame the Chevron doctrine in some ways, but that’s a longstanding safeguard. That’s entirely different from the clear statement rule that says that if Congress hasn’t spelled it out specifically we the unelected, unaccountable court appointed by -- well, anyway. I won’t go there.

 

But anyway, whoever they are the justices of the Supreme Court get to decide this highly contentious point which reflects political priorities that are really those of the individuals and not supported by any constitutional analysis that they have dared to put forward because they don’t have one.

 

Hon. Steven Bradbury:  Can I jump in here --

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi:  Sure.

 

Hon. Steven Bradbury:  There’s also same line drawn or a similar line drawing issue and vagaries and unpredictability in that holy line between step one of Chevron and step two of Chevron. What is ambiguity in a statute? And there are some judges, some courts that just find ambiguity around every textual corner. And then there are others who never get beyond step one of Chevron because they use every tool in the toolbox, and they drill down. And they keep drilling until they discern the right meaning of the statute. And then they conclude that’s plain enough, not to cross that barrier into step two land. And it’s the same kind of issue. It is not consistently applied.

 

Prof. Ronald M. Levin:  See, I don’t think that’s a problem at all. I really don’t think it’s a problem at all because it’s really the vagueness of statutory construction doctrine generally. You have the exact same issues in non administrative context where Chevron isn’t a factor but people have different ways of interpreting statutes. And some of them look at immediately and say, oh, I know what that means. And others say I don’t know.

 

Hon. Steven Bradbury:  You’re going to get differences in different courts for sure in their interpretation of statutes, but if they’re forced to use every tool and keep going and keep going rather than just jump to the conclusion, oh, it’s ambiguous and therefore anything the agency does that I think it might think is reasonable is okay, so I don’t have to do any work -- that’s the problem. And courts jump to that ambiguity conclusion so quickly.

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi:  I think your basic point was just that the line drawing problem in nondelegation is not unique to nondelegation. You see it in lots of different areas.

 

Hon. Steven Bradbury:  That’s correct. Right.

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi:  And that’s just a problem of adjudication.

 

Prof. Ronald  M. Levin:  I think the Court should say don’t blow it off. It should say do a serious job. I think the right model here is the Kaiser v. Wilkie model where the Court essentially reaffirmed current doctrine but said but do it conscientiously.

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi: All right. We’re in our last five minutes. Let’s try to get these questions in, so let’s go first to this microphone here.

 

David Tryon:  Thank you. David Tryon at the Buckeye Institute. So I want to ask a question about post-Chevron, and I know we could have a whole panel on that, I suppose. But Chevron, well, even Skidmore, relies upon the expertise of the agencies at least under some circumstances. And so as we go back and look at the expertise of the agency and the hundreds or thousands of pages of, quote, expertise put into their decisions, we don’t know if those experts really are experts because they don’t go through the Daubert process that we do in every other expertise situation.

 

So there’s been some writing about administrative Daubert, and is that a solution to a post-Chevron situation where we say, okay, now the agency, you bring your experts in? You show that your experts are good experts, and the regulated party, you bring your experts in. And we’ll evaluate -- the court will evaluate all the experts and make a decision who’s right.

 

Hon. Steven Bradbury:  Well, I think there’s definitely something to that, and there are elements of that in some reform considerations like the Regulatory Accountability Act that has been considered, different versions of it, in the House and Senate. We did a rule on rules in the Executive Branch in the last administration where when you have contested issues of economic, technical, scientific factual questions, even in a rulemaking context there should potentially be more opportunity for input and contesting those facts perhaps in something like a more formal hearing context. And then that would be the record to support that decision, and a court could review that for substantial evidence or arbitrary and capricious. I’m not sure what the standard would be. But something like that would build in something along the lines you’re saying.

 

But when it comes to a pure question of law and it’s an interpretation, well, if it’s a technical question and the agency has lots of experience with that, there is a good basis for a generalist judge to give that interpretation respect to a point. And I don’t think that kind of Skidmore deference concept is going to go away. I think it will get more important again in a post Chevron world.

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi:  All right. Let’s go here for one last question.

 

Jimmy Percival:  I definitely don’t want to put us over time. Jimmy Percival from Florida. As I was sitting here, I was just thinking about how in Florida administrative law we have no Chevron. We have a robust nondelegation doctrine, and imagine that, we have an incredibly well-functioning legislature. And I was just curious if you had any thoughts or any further thoughts about whether sort of Congress’s disfunction is more an effect of the state of administrative law or more sort of a cause of it. Because you could imagine administrative law has gotten big because Congress isn’t doing its job, but you could also imagine Congress has stopped doing its job because it’s sort of comfortable with how big administrative law has grown. And I was just wondering if anybody could comment on that.

 

Andrew Tutt:  I’ve always thought about that as one of the big questions of administrative law that I myself haven’t come to a conclusion about. And it’s difficult because we all want to change how, for instance, these statutes function based on theories about, well, if we just read the text the way that it’s meant to be read, than Congress will shape up and actually pass laws. But it’s a big gamble if they actually aren’t capable of sort of stepping up to the plate in that way.

 

And I think that’s why there’s a tendency toward incrementalism in sort of the admin law community. Ron, you can disagree with me, but I think we’re all on the same page on this that there’s a risk averseness to sort of discipline in Congress because we just don’t know if the disfunction in Congress is a result of over-delegation or not. So that’s always been the great concern.

 

Prof. Ronald M. Levin:  Well, Chevron -- Florida is an outlier in a number of ways. It experiments, if you will, in ways that are just different from 49 states. And I’ve read negative appraisals of that, but I have not studied it enough to be able to say with confidence how well it’s worked. But I’m a little skeptical here.

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi:  Okay. Before we --

 

Hon. Steven Bradbury:  But he’s testifying it’s working great; right?

 

Jimmy Percival:  Well, I think net migration would tell you that.

 

Hon. Steven J. Menashi:  So before we adjourn, I’ve been asked to encourage you all to visit the Remnant Trust’s rare document exhibit which is in the South Carolina room and is open throughout the convention at which they have on display original pieces of history, including the Life and Times of Fredrick Douglass, the History of Women’s Suffrage, and a copy of the Magna Carta. So I encourage you to visit the South Carolina Room at some point. With that, please join me in thanking our panelists and we are adjourned.

 

 

     

 

 

12:00 p.m. - 1:45 p.m.
SFFA and Beyond

2023 National Lawyers Convention

Topics: Affirmative Action • Civil Rights • Education Policy • Fourteenth Amendment • Supreme Court
State Room
The Mayflower Hotel
1127 Connecticut Avenue NW
Washington, DC 20006

Event Video

Listen & Download

Description

This year the Supreme Court issued its long-awaited decision in Students for Fair Admissions Inc. v. President and Fellows of Harvard College. The Court held that the admissions programs of Harvard College and the University of North Carolina violated the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment.

The Court’s ruling elevates a colorblind reading of the Fourteenth Amendment. In the college admissions context, the decision makes unconstitutional certain policies that would favor one applicant over another on the basis of that applicant’s race. College admissions offices across the country will have to alter the policies they’ve used for decades. How will they adapt? Will facially race-neutral policies aiming to achieve a desired racial balance for accepted classes be created as a proxy? Will colleges attempt to sidestep the ruling or find legally permissible means of achieving their objectives? If so, how will the courts respond?

Some observers argue that the decision in SFFA should be expected to affect diversity, equity, and inclusion efforts outside of college admissions. Will public and private employers have to change their hiring practices? Will competitive K-12 schools adjust their admissions policies? What about scholarships? Government contracting? How far-reaching will the Court’s interpretation of the Fourteenth Amendment ultimately be?

This panel will provide a comprehensive review of SFFA and explore its consequences.

Featuring:

  • Prof. Akhil Reed Amar, Sterling Professor of Law and Political Science, Yale Law School
  • Hon. Gail L. Heriot, Professor of Law, University of San Diego School of Law
  • Prof. Randall L. Kennedy, Michael R. Klein Professor of Law, Harvard Law School
  • Mr. Devon Westhill, President & General Counsel, Center for Equal Opportunity
  • Moderator: Hon. Stephen A. Vaden, United States Court of International Trade

Overflow: Cabinet & Senate Rooms

Speakers

Event Transcript

Kenneth Marcus:  I mean, with all that applause, I think we're done, right? We're not going to improve on that.

 

      It's good to be among friends again. I'm Ken Marcus. I chair the Civil Rights Practice Group. I've seen some of you before. How many of you have been to a Civil Rights Practice Group event before? Nice. How many of you are new? So I'm calculating I can use about 50 percent of the same material from last year. I got to tell you the other 50 percent got me into a little bit of trouble, so I'm going to try to avoid that if I can.

 

Questioner 1:  What was it?

 

Kenneth Marcus:  Well, that's the part I can't --

 

Questioner 2:  You're asking for trouble.

 

Kenneth Marcus:  Listen to the prosecutor over here.

 

      Last year I gave a little talk at the beginning, and then I got a call from a national reporter, and she said to me, "I listened to your remarks, and I heard about what you're doing with the Civil Rights Practice Group. And I just can't believe that you have managed to accomplish so little."

 

      Now, reflexively, I like to agree with people, so I said, "Yes. Yes. I think so too." And then I said, "Wait a minute. Could we talk about this?"

 

      So she said, "You talked about how you have these great panels at the convention and at other events throughout the year. You talked about the webinars that you do throughout the year; the Court Step events after Supreme Court and other decisions come down. You talked about the blog entries and the other publications that your members put together. But I know that what you're really supposed to be doing and what you're really actually doing is you are dominating the federal judiciary and the attorneys general throughout the United States."

 

      And I said to her, "That's not The Federalists. That's the Zionists." I said, "If you need to come to me in my office and see me in my day job. You can play with the space lasers. We can make some weather together. Happy to go over it with you."

 

      She said, "No, no, no, no." She said, "This has all been reported before." She says, "I know you have an executive committee." We do. "And you've got very prominent people from academia, former officials of the federal government. You've got people who are prominent in public interest organizations. And you set the agenda for the United States."

 

      And I said again, "That's the Zionists. And I'm not sure if I can break it down for you, but Federalists and Zionists." I said, "One of them is this kind of odd quasi-religious, political sect that's despised throughout the world. And the other is the liberation movement of the Jews."

 

      I don't know why that interview did not go over well. But it's really important that we not repeat a similar problem today. So I don't know whether Gene and Dean and Nate are in the room and the leadership they provided to us. I think if they are, they're probably saying, "My God. Marcus has one job -- one job -- introduce the judge -- and people still don't know who the judge is. And you're still going on and on." I want to thank them. I also want to thank Sam Fendler. I told Gene Meyer recently, I said, "I am willing to continue to take all of the credit as long as Sam is willing to do all of the work." So I thank Sam Fendler for his work in putting this together as well as the executive committee.

 

      And I thank Judge Stephen Vaden. So I'm going to say a few things about him. To begin with a boilerplate: Judge Vaden, if you don't know, is a judge on the United States Court of International Trade. Before joining the court in 2020, he served as General Counsel of the United States Department of Agriculture for four years. He began his career in the private sector, where he worked for Jones Day and Patton Boggs. I have had the privilege of hearing him speak before, and I have to say we are deeply honored to have him moderating, and we should very generously welcome Judge Vaden.

 

Hon. Stephen Vaden:  Well, thank you all so much, and it's wonderful to be here this afternoon.

     

      I would be remiss if I didn't take a moment to note what today is. It is our observance of Veterans Day. Of course, Veterans Day is actually tomorrow, commemorating on the eleventh hour of the eleventh day of the eleventh month in 1918, when the guns of World War I fell silent. We have, unfortunately, all been reminded how important it still is in the 21st century that men and women are willing to take up arms to defend freedom by events overseas. So I'd like to acknowledge each and every person in this room who has served in the armed forces of the United States and allowed us to have this discussion here today.

 

      So, with that, we're going to have a very healthy discussion about a very pertinent and timely issue in the best tradition of The Federalist Society. I'm going to provide a little introduction. Then I'm going to tell you who you're going to hear from and the order that you'll hear from them. Then I'll get out of the way and let them talk.

 

      The Supreme Court of the United States has held that no state has any authority under the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment to use race as a factor in affording educational opportunities among its citizens. After that holding, there was much consternation around the educational community. There were efforts made to decide how they could undercut it, perhaps circumvent it. And that necessitated the very next year, the Supreme Court, in the second Brown v. Board of Education case, to declare that their ruling should be implemented with "all deliberate speed."

 

      In 2023, the Supreme Court once again took up the issue of the role of race in choosing who may attend certain educational institutions. And, in that case, the Supreme Court declared, and I quote, "Eliminating racial discrimination means eliminating all of it."

 

      It was not a straight line between Brown v. Board of Education and Students for Fair Admission v. Harvard University. There were many cases that came in between, most notably the 1978 Bakke decision involving the University of California. That decision grievously split the Supreme Court 4-4, with Justice Powell's decision being the one that ultimately came to be controlling, where Justice Powell found that educational freedom—the right of academic freedom that academic institutions have—allowed them to select their own student body. That rationale came to be known as the diversity rationale and was later adopted by a majority of the Supreme Court in 2003 in the Grutter v. Bollinger decision.

 

      However, even in that decision, there was consternation among the Court and even among some members of the majority, where the opinion seemed to come with a sunset clause that limited it to perhaps 25 years and contained the following quote: "All race-conscious admission programs must have a termination point." The question we're here to address is: Did that termination point come this year, or did it not?

 

      At the conclusion of his majority opinion, Justice Roberts seemed to leave the door open. That's beyond the issue of footnote 4, which expressly exempted military academies from the holding of Students for Fair Admission. But Justice Roberts, responding to the multiple dissents at the end of his opinion, noted in passing that of course students who are writing essays are free to talk about whatever they want to, including race, and that colleges may, of course, take this into account. This has been the subject of much discussion since.

 

      Some of you may have attended yesterday's panel that was put on by the In-House Counsel Group that dealt with another part of the Students for Fair Admission. I want to tell you there are going to be two main differences between yesterday's panel and today's panel. First, we're not going to bore you.

 

[Laughter]

 

      And if you attended yesterday's panel, you know what I'm talking about.

 

[Laughter]

 

      And, second, we're going to be focused on the context of the Students for Fair Admission case itself. That is the academic context and what it means. Of course, our panelists can talk about it in the private sector context as well, but we're going to be particularly interested in the context of higher education. With that, I will introduce our speakers.

 

      Immediately to my left is Professor Gail Heriot, who teaches and writes in the area of civil rights, employment discrimination, product liability remedies, and torts. She is a professor at the University of San Diego Law School, and she is currently a member of the United States Commission on Civil Rights.

 

      To her left is Akhil Amar, who really needs no introduction because he is such a great friend of The Federalist Society and always a debater in good spirit. But I know he would want me to tell you all about his latest book, The Words That Made Us: America’s Constitutional Conversation, 1760-1840. I believe he was signing copies of it earlier today. And if you happened to miss him, I bet he'd sign a copy for you.

 

      Further to his left, but only in geographical location, is Devon Westhill. Devon is an attorney also focused on matters of constitutional and civil rights. Devon and I know each other. You used to work at The Federalist Society as one of the officers. But in addition to that, Devon and I served together at the United States Department of Agriculture, where he ably served as the Deputy Assistant Secretary for Civil Rights. Currently, Devon leads the Center for Equal Opportunity and is a frequently-quoted speaker in the press and files amicus briefs in courts on these issues.

 

      And last, but certainly not least, is Professor Randall Kennedy of the Harvard Law School. Professor Kennedy teaches courses on contracts, criminal law, and the regulation of race relations. He is also a former clerk for Justice Thurgood Marshall of the United States Supreme Court.

 

      And so, with that, I will turn it over to Professor Heriot.

 

Hon. Gail Heriot:  You're making me nervous, Judge. Now I feel like I can't bore them to death, so that's -- I'll try here, you know.

 

      My friends sometimes call me a pessimist. But if you're concerned that my talk is going to be a downer in which I list all the ways that universities will circumvent the Supreme Court's decision, you can relax. I'm pretty happy about this decision. We haven't won the war, and things could still go awry, but provided that "win" is defined realistically, the whole thing seems a lot more winnable now than it did before.

 

      Yes, universities will attempt to get around the Court's decision, but we don't need 100 percent compliance for positive things to start to come from the Court's decision. So here are my predictions. And I suspect they won't be all that different from a lot of your predictions.

 

      Some schools are going to experiment with doing away with standardized tests, but those that hope to be viewed as academically rigorous, they won't like the results. And I think a lot of them will reverse course. MIT's already done so after abandoning the SAT during the COVID-19 lockdown.

 

      Some schools are going to be experimenting more with class preferences. They will find that there are a lot more low-income Asian Americans and whites than they thought. And they will also find that their African American and Latino applicants are not all low-income by any means. If they try to get around that problem by defining social class in a way that advantages one racial group over another, they will risk being the target of the next wave of lawsuits, which is already being planned.

 

      And some will give preferences to those who purport to have overcome obstacles, as Chief Justice Roberts's opinion runs, and they're going to find that there are a lot of obstacles out there in the world, not just race. And, again, they are going to find that it's more complicated than they thought.

 

      So, realistically, universities that want to avoid litigation are going to have to start shrinking the academic credentials gap. And by "academic credentials gap," I mean the difference at each institution between the entering academic credentials of students of each race. So, currently, as a direct result of racial preferences, that gap is very, very large on most selective campuses. Even a small reduction of those gaps is going to help out.

 

      So the most immediate effect? The most immediate effect of that, when it happens, will be better grades as more minority students attend schools where they are academically competitive. Alas, the facts are very clear here: No serious advocate of race preferences denies that currently the credentials gap results in disappointing grades for preference beneficiaries. To be sure, some students outperform their entering credentials, just as some students underperform their entering credentials. But most students perform in the general range that their entering academic credentials suggest.

 

      Back in 2005, law professors Ian Ayres and Richard Brooks, both advocates of race preferences, candidly agreed that the disappointing grades problem is—and I'm quoting here—"real and serious" and that "the average black law student's grades are startlingly low." Ivy League presidents William G. Bowen and Derek Bok, who were among the most lionized defenders of preferences, also admitted to the problem. College grades present—and, again, I'm quoting here—"a sobering picture that grades earned by African American students...often reflect their struggles to succeed academically in highly competitive academic settings." That's a quotation from theirs.

 

      Over the decades, this has had a real effect. Nobody feels comfortable when they can see that minority students are disproportionately struggling. So minority students themselves often wonder whether the standards they are being held to are fair. Under the circumstances, it's tempting for students to wonder, "Is the professor really a racist?" Instructors nervously paper over the problem with grade inflation. But they haven't been able to make it go away.

 

      Once universities begin complying with the Supreme Court's decision, the problem will begin to be ameliorated as more African American and Latino students attend schools where their entering academic credentials make them academically competitive, they will earn better grades. More will be earning honors. And that can change campus culture. And I believe it will change it for the better -- slowly, to be sure, but it will change it.

 

      For example, the incentives of universities to allow runaway grade inflation should fade as low grades correlate less and less with race and ethnicity. I may be too late on that, but, you know, should get something. More important, for years now, critical race theorists have been arguing that academic standards are often just a sham, an expression of white supremacy. And struggling minority students have sometimes had an incentive to believe it. As minority students are doing better and better, that message is going to ring false to them.

 

      Another example: The tendency of many minority students on many campuses to believe they have more in common with students of their own race than they do with students with, say, their own major -- that should start receding as well. The self-segregation problem, insisting that universities provide separate student lounges, separate student dorms, graduation ceremonies all based on race -- that should recede.

 

      So the question then is: Am I being a Pollyanna for believing this can happen? And the answer is: I've already seen it done on the University of California campuses right after Prop 209 passed in 1996. That was the ban on race preferences that went into effect in 1998. GPAs dramatically changed in just a year. Yes, there were fewer underrepresented minority students at the flagship Berkeley campus. But on several other UC campuses, all of which are elite, the numbers actually increased. And it's the college GPAs that you got to keep your eye on. They are the key.

 

      Just prior to Prop 209's implementation, UC San Diego, there was only one African American freshman student out of a class of over 3,000 who earned an honors-level GPA of 3.5 or better. By contrast, 20 percent of white students had done so. Immediately after Proposition 209 went into effect, the rate at which African American freshmen earned honors shot up to—you can guess—20 percent, absolutely. Moreover, the number of African American students whose GPA put them in academic jeopardy collapsed, went from 15 percent down to 6 percent. Boom. That was exactly what we were expecting and exactly what we got. If universities are less compliant with the law this time around, the effect may be less dramatic, but there will be benefits.

 

      The effect on careers is likely to be positive, too. Having the opportunity to attend an elite university is obviously a good thing. But the weight of the evidence indicates that doing well in school is more important for a student wishing to enter a high-status career. Put differently, race-preferential admissions hurt rather than help the intended beneficiaries' career prospects. If the research into mismatch is correct—and I believe it is—we would have more African American scientists, engineers, and physicians and likely more African American lawyers and college professors if more African American students had rejected the preferential treatment they received. That's a thumping good reason to reject racial preferences.

 

      Fortunately, we don't need universities to go cold turkey on racial preferences in order to put a dent in mismatch. Even minimal compliance is likely to help here.

 

      But here comes the caveat, ladies and gentlemen. If those who oppose race preferences just sit back and hope the Supreme Court's opinion will do the magic, the gains may be ephemeral. The typical university these days employs armies of individuals who view it as their job to thwart the Court's decision. That has to be dealt with, so start with this: Governors need to appoint state university trustees who will ensure that the law is obeyed. It's already happening in Florida. Higher ed is too important to leave these boards to political donors who just want free box tickets at the football game. We need serious trustees, and they need their own independent staff.

 

      Similarly, state legislators should follow the example of Texas: cut funding to diversity, equity, and inclusion apparatus on state campuses. It only helps support race-preferential admissions. The amount of money that's involved is truly staggering. Turn off the spigot.

 

      Careful thought also needs to be given to how to reduce the incentives that push universities towards greater racial preferences. A good example is the Hispanic-Serving Institutions program, or the HSI program, which heaps federal monies on schools with student bodies that are at least 25 percent Hispanic. Unlike the Historically Black Colleges and Universities Program, eligibility for which is based on history, the HSI program creates an incentive for schools to discriminate in order to meet that 25 percent threshold. The program is almost certainly unconstitutional and should be eliminated.

 

      Do I have other ideas? Yes, I do. Like reigning in accreditors who pressure universities into discriminating. But I think I've run out of time, haven't I, Judge?

 

Hon. Stephen Vaden:  You have.

 

Hon. Gail Heriot:  Okay. Then, I'm out of here, guys.

 

Hon. Stephen Vaden:  You can stay seated or stand, whichever you like.

 

Prof. Akhil Reed Amar:  I'm given an option to stay seated or stand. I think it was Satchel Paige who said, "Never stand when you can sit down. Never sit down when you can lie down." So he also said, "Don't look back. Something might be gaining on you." So I think I'll sit.

 

      It's always an honor to be with you all. And thank you, Judge, for that kind shout-out to the book. I'm going to give myself a shout-out to a podcast. It's free. It's weekly, and there are several episodes about the Students for Fair Admissions case that might be of interest to you. We had a few -- we have 150 episodes all in all. I say "we." This is my partner, Dr. Andrew Lipka, and I. We have people on the right and on the left as guests. We have the great Will Baude, from whom I hope some of you will be hearing very shortly, and the great Michael Paulsen talking about Section 3 of the Fourteenth Amendment. We've had Ed Whelan on -- lots of other folks.

 

      But we had some episodes during the oral argument of the Students for Fair Admissions case, and we played clips from almost all the justices. You heard their voices and their positions. And then, afterward, we had at least two episodes with the former dean of admission of Yale College, Jeffrey Brenzel, talking about how he thought various schools would react to the ruling. So those might be of interest to you. And it's free. If you just google "Akhil Amar podcast," you can find it. It's got the cute title, Amarica's Constitution.

 

      So I think I have five quick points here. First, affirmative action discourse in America, frankly, has been pretty deeply dishonest in all sorts of ways because they're uncomfortable truths that people sometimes tiptoe around. Gail mentioned some. I suspect my friend Randy will mention others. But, since you mentioned Rick Sander's mismatch thesis, there has been a mismatch between what some sincere and principled believers in affirmative action actually think and what they say.

 

      What they actually think is that affirmative action is best justified as a remedy for America's historical wrongs going all the way back to 1619, but that we talk the talk—the happier talk—of diversity rather than the talk of remedy because remedy requires awkward discussions about our history, maybe finger-pointing. So, if you have a remedy -- and the reason we talk the happy talk of diversity—"Oh, it's good, and we should have more of it. And we should, in theory, have more of it forever and for every category"—is that beginning with Justice Powell's swing opinion in the Bakke case—it was a 4-1-4—and then with Grutter and Gratz and Fisher, the diversity rationale was really the only one that the Supreme Court would allow advocates of affirmative action—the racial preferences of a certain sort—to put forth.

 

      What this has meant, in part, if we're being very candid, is a less singular focus on blacks and Native Americans in America -- because I think they would have the strongest argument for -- on remedial grounds given slavery and segregation and dispossession of Native Americans. So less focus on -- unique focus on them. Hispanics have been the beneficiary, to some extent, of the diversity theory. Asian Americans, to some extent, have been the victims of this. There's been displacement in various schools, taking seats away from Asian Americans who might be statistically overrepresented, as Jews were in a previous generation, since we heard about Zionism. And these are some of the things that I think you can expect to see going forward is some -- maybe we'll have a more candid conversation about history. And maybe we'll hear about some of that from my friend Randy, although, I don't want to put words in his mouth.

 

      On -- second point. On Hispanics versus Asians and the facts, especially, of the Harvard case, even if you believe in affirmative action, you should not -- so one thing that Harvard did is took some spots that used to -- that might, on the numbers—the academic numbers—have gone to Asians and basically given them to Hispanics because, God forbid, the white numbers should ever go down, and all the non-whites kind of look alike from a certain point of view. And this is some of the dishonesty, you see, of our recent discourse.

 

      But, above and beyond that, I think the numbers showed that Harvard was affirmatively discriminating against Asian Americans, not that they weren't the beneficiaries of affirmative action, but that they were actually -- it was harder to get into Harvard—when you looked at the academic credentials—as an Asian American than it was as a white. That's not really affirmative action, especially if one is attentive to history. That's just discriminating against a group that actually came pretty late to the American experience in general.

 

      And the lower courts either were statistically illiterate and/or didn't really want to question the great Harvard University because our lead institutions have to be right. Didn't want to take seriously the limits on affirmative action that were enunciated by, first, Powell's opinion in Bakke and then Grutter and Gratz and Fisher how it's not supposed to be a quota. They were -- the lower court, in my view, was kind of under-ruling, as it were, Grutter and Gratz and Fisher, the way some of the lower courts are claimed to have been under-ruling City of Chicago v. McDonald in the Second Amendment case -- Second Amendment context leading to pushback in a case like Bruen. And you saw similar pushback in Students for Fair Admission because the lower courts really weren't taking seriously the idea that maybe you could have a plus, but it can't be a quota. And so, there was interesting dynamic between the Supreme Court and lower federal courts that was going on.

 

      Third point: Even if you think that the government should have nothing whatsoever to do with categorizing or classifying people according to race, this divvying us up on racial grounds is a sordid business. Even if you are the fiercest of colorblindness advocates, you might think that we have constitutional rules against the government, but those rules shouldn't automatically be applied against every private institution in America. Government can't have a religion, but Akhil gets to have one. Government shouldn't have a gender preference—sexual orientation preference—but Akhil gets to.

 

      And you might think that it was a mistake to bring together the rules for private schools—even those that get government funding—and the rules for the government. You might think that no private school that calls itself a charity and does get tax preference in certain ways -- the tax deductibility of a charitable contribution. You might think that even a private school should not be discriminating against historically underrepresented groups -- that not everything counts as a proper school. It's got to teach certain things: reading, writing, arithmetic, and it should act in charitable ways. And you might think a private school for whites only isn't really a proper charity, the same way you might think that Fagan's School for Thieves, that'll teach you how to pick a pocket or two, isn't really the kind of school that we should be treating as a proper charity.

 

      But even if you think that is a private school that gets charitable tax treatment, why shouldn't some private schools be allowed to vote their resources, their brand to the mitigation or the elimination of some of the historic under-representations in America that have been the product of all sorts of bad acts, many illegal, perhaps some technically legal, some by government, some by private persons? So should private institutions -- should we change current civil rights laws to allow private institutions to engage in race-conscious preferential admissions and scholarships and other things that public institutions should not be allowed to do for reasons having to do with an idea that our government should be strictly impartial and colorblind? That's an interesting question going forward. It might bring together some folks on the right who believe in private choice and some folks on the left.

 

      Fourth point: There are some areas of law that, even though we're moving away from a quota-fied bottom line disparate effect idea, are still going to have residues of quota and disparate effect analysis. I think the two, especially are jury service and voting, certain political rights. And that's in context and elsewhere, where we're going to be especially suspicious just of bottom-line disproportionality.

 

      And I think there are two reasons for this. There's a podcast episode on this particular issue here if you're interested, having to do with -- I'll call it "the denominator problem" and "the aggregation issue," or "the winner talk all issue" for certain political rights.

 

      Let's take voting. Whether your vote counts or not -- formally everyone votes. But it matters to you whether, in effect, you get to vote for a winner or whether you are voting for a loser, whether your vote is, as it were, a wasted vote. The power of your vote is going to be dependent in part on the voters around you, and that's going to require—and this is, of course, our voting rights laws—focus more on bottom-line effects, especially where there's racially polarized voting, than in other domains.

 

      So there's an article in the Stanford Law Review. It's called The Hybrid Nature of Political Rights. It's by Professor Vikram Amar and Alan Brownstein, and it elaborates this. The denominator problem is somewhat similar. There are all sorts of areas where you just might not think that everything, even in a perfectly just world, is randomly distributed. It might be that more women are interested in teaching women's studies or English Lit. That was a very gendered example, but it might be. It might be that in other domains, you're going to get a disproportionately high percentage of Asians or Jews or Italian Americans, or whatever. It might be that even in a perfectly just world for reasons—all sorts of reasons, culture, and otherwise—Kenyan -- people of Kenyan ancestry might do -- be disproportionately represented among the winners of marathons. We don't know why that might be so. Lots of reasons having to do with culture.

 

      But you don't think -- we shouldn't probably think that when it comes to voting and jury service. We should think probably if there's a really -- a world in which there hasn't been improper discrimination, or, again, we should be getting proportional representation on juries and among voters. So don't be surprised if courts continue to have more of a bottom-line disparate impact analysis when it comes to jury service and voting.

 

      Finally—and my friend, Gail, mentioned this briefly—if we're really serious about the diversity rationale, even if it's not permissible in certain contexts, if we're really serious about the full remedial rationale, our great institutions, public and private, need to do a better job—forget admissions—about integrating people from different backgrounds once they get on to campus in their residential housing, in their dining choices, in their extracurriculars and clubs, and more generally, and I think, in their choices of majors and academic programs. And we need to do a much, much better job of that. And that's what some of us who believed in diversity and remedy have always actually put forth as the ideal, and we're not doing it.

 

      So those are my five thoughts. Thank you very much.

 

Devon Westhill:  So good afternoon. I was told I have five to eight minutes to make my remarks. I'm going to try to stick to that.

 

      But I have to say, to start things off, as a person who joined The Federalist Society as a student member on Day One of law school, it is an incredible honor to be addressing this group, this convention. I've even worked to organize some of these things. I'm a big fan of The Federalist Society, so it's just an amazing honor.

 

      When I got the invitation to speak on this panel, I said, "Yes. Wow. What an amazing thing." And then I got a response from The Federalist Society staff saying, "Oh, that's great. We're so happy to have you. You're also going to be on with Professor Heriot, Amar, and Kennedy." So, obviously, I tried to think of a polite way to get of this. Obviously, I'm not smart enough to do that, so here I am.

 

      But that made me wonder, "Why me?" I can't give you the academic perspective on “SFFA and Beyond” or the scholarly perspective. You're getting that in spades on this panel here. I don't really even consider myself an expert on much of anything. I just consider myself a simple country lawyer.

 

[Laughter]

 

      I went to public schools, but one of the reasons why I think I might have been chosen for this panel or to be invited for this panel is one of the reasons why I joined The Federalist Society some years ago on the first day of law school. And that is because The Federalist Society appreciates diversity. And what I mean by that is diversity of perspective. And I think I bring perhaps some of that here. I don't want to prejudge my co-panelists, but I'm just a poor black kid from the South.

 

      I was raised by a single mother. All three of -- my two siblings and I were raised by a single mother and poor. We were homeless at periods of time. We worked our way up from there to housing projects, from housing projects to Section 8 apartments. And then, eventually, by the time I was a teenager, we had our own house in the ghetto. That was great. It was our own house. It was the best thing we'd ever had. And we really appreciated that. But I've never known my father. He's been in prison pretty much as long as I can remember. To this day, I think he is in prison.

 

      Given the rough upbringing that we went through and the statistics that suggest that children who come up that way end up in this terrible doom loop, that's what happened to my brother. My brother went to prison just as soon as he was old enough. My sister was a teen mom. And neither one of them graduated from high school. I went a different path.

 

      I say this only because, in part, the horse is out of the stable to some extent. I've already announced this to other people -- sort of my background. But also, I think it's because I'm not the type of person you expect to say, "I think the Supreme Court did the right thing in effectively outlawing race preferences in college admissions." But here I am saying that. I think, from a legal standpoint, from a policy standpoint, and also from a moral standpoint, it's the right thing to do.

 

      From the policy standpoint, I think—for many of the reasons that have already been articulated, and I'm not going to go through here, but maybe we will get into in the Q&A, I think, on the whole—affirmative action has been a problem for the individuals who are supposed to be the intended beneficiaries of it. The organization that I run, the Center for Equal Opportunity, has produced over 80 studies documenting and looking at the effect of affirmative action at certain colleges and universities around the country -- law school as well and medical schools.

 

      And our most recent one was a study of the University of Maryland. And this was before the June decision -- the entering class of 2021. We're looking at that data. What we saw was that black students—it wasn't a surprise—were about three times as likely to be admitted to the University of Maryland, College Park, than white students. But this didn't do them any favors. Based on the data that we analyzed, we saw that black students had the lowest six-year graduation rate of any race or ethnicity at the University of Maryland in that time period as well.

 

      So, again, I'm not going to go into great detail about the mismatch theory and so forth. We can talk about that, but, really, just dust off your books on that and take a look at it. I think that's something that need not -- should not be forgotten in this whole conversation. And it really obscures, in my view, what affirmative action was meant to do on the heels of the 1960s civil rights movement and successes and how it got perverted over time. This is SFFA, but also beyond.

 

      Let me just really quickly say maybe I'm a little bit more optimistic than Gail. Or maybe --

 

[CROSSTALK]

 

Hon. Gail Heriot:  Just optimistic [Inaudible 00:42:14].

 

Devon Westhill:  -- more pessimistic -- more pessimistic than Gail. So I'm going to agree that, look, I think at the end of the day, although I can nitpick, the decision from June, the era of over-racial preferences, I think, is over. I'm happy to see institutions like the University of North Carolina, where I have one of my degrees, really pivoting hard away from what -- there for a long period of time put a lot of money into, which is to treat people differently based on their skin color, based on where their ancestors are from. We've seen, also, other institutions banning the box. Getting rid of the checkbox to ask students what their race is. This is all really positive stuff. Law firms now are being sued successfully. They’re just rolling over when they get sued for their diversity fellowships that, again, treat people differently based on their race.

 

      In the service academies, I think—I've heard someone else use this terminology. I think it's right—are now being sued. They didn't really, in my view, in footnote 4 in the decision, get a carveout, but more of a day pass. That day pass is going to come due very soon.

 

      I am pessimistic though. What I've seen much more of is an attempt to evade the decision. The Biden administration, for example, I think, really did a terrible thing in putting out guidance to schools. Instead of saying, "Hey, look, the Supreme Court has said something really important here about equality under the law and about treating people in this country equally. We really need you to comply. Well, here are some ways in which you can get around this." I thought that was the wrong way to go about things.

 

      And, to this room, I say, "Look. A wise man once said, "Elections have consequences." It really does matter who runs the Justice Department, the Civil Rights Division, OCR at the Education Department, if the Education Department will still exist in another administration. These things really do matter. As a result of that, we're seeing why.

 

      But we're seeing schools change their essay prompts, for example. We saw Columbia, for example, asking for students to submit 90-second videos of themselves, which really just seemed like an on-the-nose kind of way to figure out what their skin color was and whether it was something they were interested in in their admittees. But there was a continuum of bad ideas in how schools might change their admissions practices.

 

      I think we ought to be testing in the courts, and we should be taking a look at it. It's one of the reasons why my organization, just today, made an announcement that we are launching the After affirmative action Network, which will be a bit of a clearinghouse to gather information about what's going on around the country at these selective institutions after the decision and then to give that information to lawyers who are interested in this type of thing, to journalists, and others so that we're doing two different things.

 

      One, we're ensuring compliance with the new state of the law. We're really testing the boundaries to see how far the Court will allow affirmative action to go after the June decisions. But then, also, to share best practices. Again, UNC and other schools are doing some things to change their practices, which may very well be the type of thing that we want other schools to be doing going forward. And so, if you're interested in that type of thing, get with me. I would like to hear from you.

 

      Finally, there is a case right now on petition for certiorari, the TJ case. I'm just assuming that most of the audience knows about this case -- the high school in Virginia that basically changed its admissions practices that did not include racial element in selecting its applicants. But, very clearly, had the motive, had the purpose of racially gerrymandering its classes. The Pacific Legal Foundation is representing the plaintiffs in that case. And I'm hopeful that the Court will take that case and really expound on its position that eliminating racial discrimination means eliminating all of it. In my view, that's racial discrimination. And if the Court's purpose of the Fourteenth Amendment is to eliminate all governmental distinctions based on race, it has to extend to that sort of behavior, and that won't be acceptable after SFFA.

 

      The Center for Equal Opportunity filed an amicus brief in that case, documenting the extent to which the Fairfax County School Board has been tinkering with race in this way for a long period of time. And, again, we think that that is after SFFA, especially illegal and the sort of conduct that we can't tolerate going forward.

 

      So thank you very much.

 

Prof. Randall Kennedy:  Thank you. I'd like to thank all who have played a role in organizing this event and inviting me to be part of it. I'd especially like to thank Sam Fendler, who shows exemplary efficiency and courtesy. It's been very welcoming.

 

      I have two points I'd like to make. One goes a bit outside of our specific topic. The first point I want to make has to do with the trajectory of race relations over the last 70 years. So the Judge began with bringing our attention back to May 17, 1954, the day the Supreme Court announced Brown v. Board of Education. 1954 has a special ring for me because I was born in 1954, September 10, 1954. And, indeed, I was born in Columbia, South Carolina.

 

      So in South Carolina, the year that I was born, in January of 1954 in South Carolina, the constitution of South Carolina decreed that white people would go to one school and colored people would go to another. That was part of its constitutional law. It had statutes that effectuated that, but that was so important in South Carolina, it was part of its constitutional regime.

 

      I want us to think about change in American life since 1954. There's been a lot of talk on our front pages of newspapers, with people talking about and debating about and arguing about whether there has been change in the United States of America with respect to race relations. Clearly, there has been change in the United States of America with respect to race relations. And wherever you stand on the ideological spectrum, yes, I am on the left. I am. I am on the left. Wherever you stand with respect to the ideological spectrum, there has been—thank God—change, considerable change in the United States of America.

 

      Part of that change is the affirmative action story. Now, different people have different views with respect to affirmative action and its effectiveness. And I'm going to turn to that in a minute. But affirmative action is part of the progress that America has seen over the past 70 years. And there are -- and the affirmative action ethos has been part of virtually all aspects of decent American life. Even the people who say they're against affirmative action are affected by the affirmative action ethos, even The Federalist Society. There's no question but that the center of gravity with The Federalist Society is against affirmative action. Is The Federalist Society not attentive to race consciousness?

 

      My colleague here talked about why is he part of this program. I have no doubt that at least part of the reason I am part of this program has to do with my race. I say that, and I'm not putting down The Federalist Society. I don't think that's the only thing. I hope that my record gives me standing to take up some of your time. I've written. I've spoken. I hope that people, whether they agree with me or not, think that I have something useful to say. But I don't think that's all of it.

 

      I think that there has been, amongst the authorities in this institution, a decent feeling of, "Well, gosh, we're putting together a program. We're putting together a program. Do we want to make an effort to bring in different people? Ideological difference? Yes. Racial difference? Yes. Is there a part?" There are many conservatives, many conservatives who, in making employment decisions, other sorts of decisions, ask themselves, "Can I do something? Can I do my part in assisting the country to remedy its history—its terrible history—of racial oppression?" The answer to that is, "Yes." Judges, some of whom were on record as being against affirmative action, do they make a special effort to go to law schools to go to student societies in an effort to bring in racial minorities? The answer is, yes, they do. That's race-conscious. In my view, it's good.

 

      Second point, we've been talking about the Supreme Court's decision. A number of speakers have said they thought it was a good decision. I don't. I think it was a bad decision.

 

      Number one, let's get clear what the Supreme Court of the United States said. The Supreme Court of the United States, in its decision, outlawed racial affirmative action. That's right. And in doing so, they took it off the table. It is no longer a matter of regular politics.

 

      I think that my colleague, Professor Heriot, had some -- in her writings and in the writings of other critics of affirmative action, I think they made some very strong points. I think they make some very strong points. And I think that these points should be subject to debate. I think that people should be able to listen to the debaters. And, at the end of the debate, maybe come to the conclusion, "No. We don't want affirmative action," just like nine states outlawed affirmative action prior to the Supreme Court's decision, like California did. Seems to me that should be a matter of regular politics.

 

      What happened to judicial restraint? Conservatives. What happened to fairism in the idea of the way the Supreme Court ought to deploy its power? What happened to the idea of experimentation? Some institutions have it: affirmative action. Some don't. We can see. Let people decide. Let's let a record erupt. Let people vote with their feet. What about ideas of localism as opposed to the imposition from on high of one national standard? What about that?

 

      Now, one response to me might very well be, "Well, yeah, Kennedy, that's fine. But we're talking about invidious racial discrimination." I don't think we're talking about invidious racial discrimination. I do not think that Harvard University was discriminating against white people or people of Asian American ancestry. Was Harvard University and the University of North Carolina and other institutions, in their admissions policies, was their admission policy disadvantaging white candidates, Asian American candidates? Answer, yes. If you have 100 seats and you were giving a boost to, let's say, the black applicants and Latino applicants, is that disadvantaging people who are not black, not Latino? Yes. Yes, it's disadvantaging them. Is it discriminating against them? That's where I'd say no. It's disadvantaging them.

 

      Oh, I heard -- I heard the laugh. I heard the laugh. Okay. I'm willing to go with the laugh. Yes, there's a distinction in my mind -- there's a distinction in my mind between the government or not just the government because we're talking about Harvard's a private institution. There's a distinction between disadvantaging and discriminating against. I think there's a difference between a racial distinction -- a racial discrimination -- and an invidious racial discrimination. We can push that. We can talk about that more later, but just as an opening gambit, that is my position.

 

      Now, I want to end -- I want to end by taking up where my colleague left off with the issue of racial neutrality. It will be very interesting to see how the courts handle the issue of racial neutrality. So, for instance, there's some institutions -- well, Texas -- Texas's Top Ten Percent Plan. If you're in the top ten percent of your class, no matter what your class is in Texas, you get your ticket to the University of Texas. Clearly, clearly part of that was race-conscious.

 

      The numbers had gone down for Latinos and blacks in the aftermath of the outlawing of racial affirmative action, and this was viewed as politically intolerable. And so, Texas authorities figured out some -- the Texas Ten Percent Plan. In other places, we will see other workarounds.

 

      Question: What will the courts do about that? My colleague thinks that the courts will comprehensively outlaw that. I don't think so. We'll see. Time will tell. I think, rather, what we'll see is the court's compromise. I think that they will muddle through. I think that, too, with devices that are sufficiently ambiguous, the courts will let them go. If you are too obvious in your workaround, I think the courts will strike those selection schemes down.

 

      But I don't think that the Court is going to be comprehensive and thoroughgoing in its effort to erase all race lines in American life, including race lines in American life that are clearly aimed at continuing the work of redressing our historical past. I don't think they're going to be willing to do that. And, again, I don't think they're going to be willing to do that because they are going to understand that the affirmative action ethos is part of the progress that America has made over the past 70 years.

 

      Thank you all very much.

 

Hon. Stephen Vaden:  Well, I promised you all we weren't going to bore you, so mission accomplished.

 

      I just want to ask one question of the panel that I was thinking about when all of you spoke, and then I'm going to turn it over to our audience members for their questions. But, in particular, Professor Kennedy, I want to pick up something that you drew on, namely, the suggestion that this should be subject to experimentation and let different people try different things and see what the results are and see what we like better and adjust accordingly.

 

      We are 45 years from Bakke. We are 20 years from Grutter. At a bare minimum, I think 20 years is an opportunity to take a look at what we've got and see whether or not some things have succeeded and some things have not.

 

      My own personal opinion: I think that college campuses now, to most American citizens, are symbols of intolerance rather than tolerance when it comes to dissenting viewpoints. I also note that you mentioned 1953, '54, '55, and the Brown decisions. Taking that, there's another difference that I can think of between what we might have expected in the United States of the 1950s and what we are seeing in 2023. And that is that the explosion, post-Hamas invasion of Israel, and anti-Semitism is not taking place in Philadelphia, Mississippi. It is taking place in Philadelphia, Pennsylvania, on the campus of the University of Pennsylvania and on the campus of multiple Ivy League and other respected universities nationwide.

 

      So I'm wondering, given what we are seeing today, do you believe that the policies that were previously allowed by Bakke and Grutter played any role in agitating that or perhaps militating what we would see without it?

 

Prof. Randall Kennedy:  That's a really good question. I'm not sure about the relationship between affirmative action and some of the pathologies. And I'm happy to say "pathologies" that we find in our institutions of higher education. I'm not sure. I think it's worth studying. Maybe there is. I'm not sure.

 

      I do want to say a couple of things about higher education because higher education has certainly -- if you read the newspapers, there's a reason why higher education has been sinking in the esteem of the public. I'm very sorry about that. We need our institutions of higher education. We are absolutely dependent upon our institutions of higher education. I will say I do think that some of the -- there's no doubt that there are aspects of collegiate and university life that warrant strong criticism.

 

      One always has to ask the question, though: Compared to what? So if we ask about what's going on on our campuses—the overall feel of our campuses—compared to 1960, compared to 1965, compared to 1970, compared to 1980? I would urge us to beware of a nostalgia in which we think of "the good old days."

 

      There are many ways in which our college campuses are much better than at any time in American history. You mentioned, for instance, my home university, Harvard University -- and by the way, Harvard University, because it's so well-known because it's so wealthy, gets dinged a lot. I have been at Harvard University now for nearly 40 years. I am very proud of my association with Harvard University. Harvard University is a great institution.

 

      And on the question of this last lawsuit: If one was to ask the question, for instance, about the status—the situation, for instance—of Asian Americans at Harvard University in the last ten years as opposed to 20 years ago, as opposed to 30 years ago, Asian American students, people of Asian descent, much more comfortable, much more a part of Harvard University. And that could be said with a number of students from groups that had been historically marginalized.

 

      So I take what you're saying. I think that there is a problem of pathologies in American universities, which you alluded to. Maybe there is a relationship between that and some of the affirmative action policies, but let us do keep perspective. I think that some of the talk about American universities has gone overboard and that there has been too little attention paid to the strengths of American universities and the way in which, in some ways, they are much better than they have ever been. Thank you.

 

Hon. Stephen Vaden:  Professor Heriot, do you want to have your response regarding that --

 

Hon. Gail Heriot:  I think we should go to the audience.

 

Hon. Stephen Vaden:  All right. Let's see what other people have to ask. Please, tell us your name and your question.

 

Charles Correll (sp):  Charles Correll. West Point has already been sued. And, Devon, I know you mentioned that you thought it was a day pass. I was at a briefing with the head of admissions while the case was percolating and up and asked the question: If the Harvard decision comes out as expected in the Supreme Court and it applied to West Point, what would that do? And the admission officer candidly said there would be very few African Americans at West Point.

 

      So, assuming that is true, how do you think the Court will ultimately resolve the diversity issue as it applies to service academies?

 

Devon Westhill:  Look -- can you hear me? In my view, the analytical framework behind what the Court did in the Harvard and UNC cases applies to the service academies. And, quite frankly, I think it's even more important for the Court to say, once it has an opportunity to look at the service academies squarely—and, again, I think it's just a day pass. It wasn't, "We're doing this carveout for service academies," or anything like that—that it's even more important, in the service academies and in the military, not to allow racial discrimination.

 

      As a veteran myself, someone who served in Swift Boat Combat Squadron after 9/11, what you wanted in the military was someone you could trust going into battle with you, leading you into battle. And what we didn't want to do was to undermine that sort of thing with any concern that the person you were serving with in these very difficult situations was in any way less than the most qualified person for that. I think it's incredibly problematic, especially in a military context, and I expect the Court to eventually say that. I think the only reason why they didn't say it -- well, there are a number of reasons potentially why they didn't say it in the Harvard and UNC cases, but it wasn't before them.

 

Prof. Akhil Reed Amar:  We have a podcast episode on -- an hour and a half on just this issue. And you should listen to it, and I'm not so sure my friend is right.

 

      The rationale in the service academies is not a diversity-based rationale. It's more of a political proportionality rationale. The political rights are four. They go all the way back to the reconstruction era: voting, voting on a jury or serving on a jury, voting in office or being voted for, and military service. In these four areas, there is more focus on bottom-line proportionality having to do with political representativeness.

 

      Ronald Reagan says that his first appointment to the Supreme Court will be a woman, and it was a woman. Joe Biden says his replacement for Justice Breyer will be a black woman. So you do see more open emphasis on bottom-line proportionality in the political rights domain.

 

      I mentioned jury service and voting. Military service is another one. So it's not the same rationale, and I don't know what the Court will do.

 

      Randy did say one really interesting thing, which is that judges, who are state actors, openly take account, many of them, of demographic features in picking their law clerks and the like, and they're state actors. Also there was a reason that those issues were bracketed.

 

      One of the really important influences in the Grutter case was the amicus brief by Colin Powell and other former military officers. So I'm not so sure that they will say it's exactly the same as Students for Fair Admission. We'll see.

 

Devon Westhill:  Well, it's --

 

Hon. Gail Heriot:  I would just like to add one thing, and that is that if I had been in charge of picking what case to go to next, I would not have picked the one that Supreme Court dropped a footnote on and said, "Hey. This may be a different case." There are so much low-hanging fruit. I would have preferred to litigate something else.

 

Devon Westhill:  I was just going to follow up to say that what the Court is going to have to grapple with is the fact that their review of the officer corps actually come from the service academies.

 

      The vast majority of officer corps come from regular colleges and universities where they've already outlawed racial preferences. And the great bulk of the remainder come from enlisted individuals who go on to the officer corps. So I just point that out as something the Court has to grapple with.

 

Prof. Akhil Reed Amar:  Yes.

 

Hon. Stephen Vaden:  Next question.

 

Prof. Akhil Reed Amar:  Good point.

 

Ryan Keane (sp):  Good afternoon. Thank you, guys. My name is Ryan Keane, and this question is directed at Professor Kennedy, but anyone's free to answer.

 

      Professor Kennedy, you -- it seemed like your argument for the benefits of racial consciousness distill down to either the remedial effects that race consciousness will have or the benefits of diversity. My question is—and I think that this was really the thrust of a lot of the argument that happened in SFFA—is at what point do we reach the Promised Land?

 

      If we need to use remediation, if we need to recognize the benefits of diversity, at what point can we say to ourselves honestly, "We have now reached a point where we have achieved those goals?" Because I think one of the troubling parts of the argument on the other side was, they had no answer to that question. And it seems like a blank check that isn't really based on those justifications when there is no endpoint. And Grutter established an endpoint, so I do think that it wasn't necessarily way beyond judicial restraints. So that's my question.

 

Prof. Randall Kennedy:  Yeah. It's a great question because I think that one of the things that bedevils us is an uncertainty, actually, about what we're trying to achieve. At certain points in American life, we've had metaphors that people have embraced.

 

      At this point, we really -- we don't really know what we want. In April 1968, the great Martin Luther King Jr. said that he had been to the mountaintop and had glimpsed the Promised Land. And he said to his audience, mainly black audience, "I might not get there with you, but I've glimpsed the Promised Land." Unfortunately, he didn't tell us very much about the topography of the Promised Land. What does it look like? And that's your question. What does it look like? How do people act there? What are -- you know. And I think we're struggling with that.

 

      So, for instance, one thing that some people say is -- it's a very popular thing to say now is, "We want a campus. We want a faculty. We want things to look like America." That's a metaphor one often hears: "looks like America." In certain ways, that's attractive. On the other hand—again, to get back to the Supreme Court case—if you are an Asian American, you look like America. If you're part of a racial group that has 10 percent or 15 percent, well, okay, your group shows up, 10/15 percent. What happens if you're one percent? Then it's very easy for you to be completely overlooked.

 

      Or to flip it around—just to give one more—people talk about "look like America." Well, I'm a basketball fan. When I turn on the television and watch the NBA All-Star Game, a team doesn't look like America. Is that a problem? I think, "Well, this a great team." But if "looks like America" is your baseline idea, we have a problem. I think we're, in various ways, reaching to try to figure out an answer to your very good question.

 

Prof. Akhil Reed Amar:  Two quick thoughts on endpoint. And this is the dishonesty of the discourse that we've had.

 

      Diversity is forward-looking, and we all benefit from it, and then we should do it forever and expand it and expand it and expand it. And Grutter says diversity, but then it actually says 25 years. That's backward-looking. If it's a remedy, then at a certain point, the remedy ends. And so, you see, actually, the tension in Grutter itself, saying diversity but also having a remedial idea of an endpoint.

 

      Second, in terms of just our national narratives and the way in which we are still broken and divided, white America tells itself that this is the Promised Land. And black America has historically said, "This is the land of Egypt, the land of bondage." Martin King was the Moses of his people, and when he says, hours before his death, that he's seen the Promised Land, it's very prophetic. And that's why Taylor Branch writes these books, Parting the Waters, At Canaan's Edge, Pillar of Fire, that see a black America as kind of an Egypt from which deliverance is sought. That’s very different than the white American vision. We don't yet have, actually, an integrated national narrative.

 

Hon. Gail Heriot:  One of the interesting things that I thought about this endpoint issue is if you look back at Bakke, you look at Fisher, you look at Grutter and Gratz, both sides of the debate on the Court seemed to acknowledge there was some need for there has to be an endpoint. The dissents in the Harvard case don't seem to acknowledge that. And I thought that was very disturbing about the opinion.

 

Devon Westhill:  I just wanted to comment to say that a lot of the discourse around affirmative action, race preference, and so forth is this idea of a black vision or a white vision. Everything's very black and white.

 

      But one of the things that I'm hopeful about, after the decision in June, is that we get away from this idea that America is just black and white. And that really is the tension that we had. America is beautifully and incredibly multiracial and multiethnic, and it's increasingly so.

 

      I'm a biracial black man, and my children are, gosh, white, black, Vietnamese. This country is changing rapidly. And I think our discourse around this really needs to be updated. And the way in which we treat people as individuals is the right way forward. And we should really be thinking about how we do that in a way. We can experiment.

 

      The only thing that the Supreme Court did was to say that, "Well, the Equal Protection Clause says X. That's it. You can't experiment on racial discrimination. You can't discriminate on the basis of race. You can experiment in many other ways if you think there's an issue in terms of diversity, socioeconomic diversity, to get racial minorities up to par academically and competitive with others through K-12 experimentation in poor K-12 schools, intergenerational poverty, family and community cohesion," which is a big thing to me. "You can still experiment. You just cannot," the Supreme Court said, "racially discriminate. That's all."

 

Ilya Somin:   Are you going here or there?

 

Hon. Stephen Vaden:  Oh, to the back.

 

Ilya Somin:  Okay. Sure. So Ilya Somin, George Mason University. Can people hear me, or is there --

 

Hon. Stephen Vaden:  Yes.

 

Ilya Somin:  They can? Great. So, formally, the SFFA case was just about racial preferences in higher education. But in a famous passage in the opinion, Chief Justice Roberts says ending racial discrimination means ending all of it. And if he's serious about that, it seems like that has implications for many other areas of government policy, some of which will be to the taste of conservatives, racial preference as friends in government contracting. But some of which conservatives may be less comfortable with, such as the very largest or most common form of racial discrimination by government that we have in our society is racial profiling in law enforcement, which affects huge numbers of people every day. And it seems like if we are serious about government being colorblind, we can't make an exception for those government agents who carry badges and guns and have the power to arrest people.

 

      So I wonder -- my question, panel, is: In what other areas do you think this decision has implications for, should have implications for, and how far should we go in acting on them?

 

Prof. Akhil Reed Amar:  If I could --

 

Ilya Somin:  Thank you.

 

Prof. Akhil Reed Amar:  Ilya, if I could just give a shoutout to a book that I once reviewed a while ago in the Harvard Law Review, the book is called Race, Crime, and the Law. It's written by Randy Kennedy. I think the title of the book review is "Three Cheers for Professor Kennedy." It's an amazing book. I commend it to you all.

 

Ilya Somin:  That's the book that first made me aware of the significance of this issue when I read it when I was in law school.

 

Hon. Stephen Vaden:  Anyone else have any thoughts?

 

Prof. Randall Kennedy:  Thank you.

 

Hon. Stephen Vaden:  All right. Thank you, guys, very much.

 

 

      Well, this has been a great panel, and I think has been the hallmark of The Federalist Society. We've taken on a tough issue. We've discussed it honestly and collegiately. And I know I learned something today. So would you join me in thanking our panelists?

12:00 p.m. - 1:45 p.m.
Friday General Luncheon

2023 National Lawyers Convention

Cabinet Room, Chinese Room, District Room, East Room, Senate Room, State Room
The Mayflower Hotel
1127 Connecticut Avenue NW
Washington, DC 20006

Share

12:00 p.m. - 1:45 p.m.
Originalism and the Communications Act of 1934

2023 National Lawyers Convention

Topics: Administrative Law & Regulation • Constitution • Telecommunications & Electronic Media
District Room
The Mayflower Hotel
1127 Connecticut Avenue NW
Washington, DC 20006

Share

Event Video

Listen & Download

Description

In recent months, the U.S. Senate confirmed a third Democratic Commissioner at the Federal Communications Commission, putting the agency in full force for the first time since January 2021. This panel will focus on the FCC’s likely agenda as we look to 2024. It will also explore the bounds of the Communications Act of 1934, as updated by the Telecommunications Act of 1996, when applied to modern technology, areas for possible legislative reform, and how the existing regulatory authority provided by Congress impacts the Commission's initiatives in the year ahead.

Featuring:

  • Hon. Jonathan Adelstein, President & CEO, The Wireless Infrastructure Association; Former Commissioner, Federal Communications Commission
  • Hon. Brendan Carr, Commissioner, Federal Communications Commission
  • Hon. Mignon Clyburn, Principal, MLC Strategies, LLC; Former Commissioner, Federal Communications Commission
  • Hon. Nathan Simington, Commissioner, Federal Communications Commission
  • Moderator: Hon. Michael H. Park, United States Court of Appeals, Second Circuit

Speakers

Event Transcript

Bryan Tramont: As today's panel will vividly illustrate, these are exciting times to be working in our space, and we're pleased that you could join us. We would like to extend an invitation to all of you to join the Practice Group. And if you'd like to get more involved, just reach out to Nate Kaczmarek.

 

      If you've already checked in via the QR code, however, there's no need to recheck in. Okay, we got that over. Now onto our panel, and we do have an all-star group today. First, our moderator, Judge Michael Park, was appointed to the U.S. Court of Appeals for the Second Circuit in May of 2019. He earned his undergraduate degree magna cum laude from Princeton University, his JD from Yale Law School, where he served as the managing editor of the Yale Law Journal.

 

      After graduation from law school, Judge Park served as a law clerk to then-judge Sam Alito on the Third Circuit, for whom he also clerked at the Supreme Court during the 2008 term. Judge Park also served as an attorney advisor in the U.S. Department of Justice Office of Legal Counsel and was a partner in the New York office of the Dechert law firm and later joined, as a named partner, the law firm of Consovoy McCarthy & Park. During this time, he also served as an adjunct professor at the Antonin Scalia School of Law at George Mason University.

 

      With that, I will turn it over to Judge Park as our moderator, and thank you again for serving today.

 

Hon. Michael Park: Thank you, Bryan. Thank you, Bryan, for the kind introduction, and thanks, everyone, for being here. Welcome to our discussion on "Originalism and the Communications Act of 1934: The bounds of the FCC's Regulatory Authority in the Modern Era." Just a quick description of what we're going to discuss: The U.S. Senate recently confirmed the third democratic FCC Senate Commissioner, putting the agency at full force for the first time since January 2021.

 

      This panel will focus on the FCC's likely agenda as we look to 2024, and we'll explore the bounds of the Communications Act of 1934, as updated by the Telecommunications Act of 1996, when applied to modern technology; areas for possible legislative reform; and how the existing regulatory authority from Congress impacts the Commission's initiatives in the year ahead.

 

      It's my pleasure to introduce our distinguished panel. First, we have FCC Commissioner Brendan Carr to my left. Commissioner Carr is the senior Republican on the FCC, and he previously served as the agency's General Counsel. Commissioner Carr was nominated to the FCC by President Trump and was confirmed unanimously by the Senate. He's been described as the FCC's 5G crusader.

 

       Commissioner Carr has led the FCC has worked to modernize its infrastructure rules and to accelerate the buildout of high-speed networks. His reforms have got billions of dollars in red tape and enabled the private sector to construct high-speed networks across the country and extended America's global leadership in 5G.

 

      Before joining the agency as a staffer back in 2012, Commissioner Carr worked at Wiley Rein in the firm's appellate, litigation, and telecommunications practices. And before that, he clerked on the U.S. Court of Appeals for the Fourth Circuit for Judge Dennis Shedd. He attended Georgetown University and earned his JD magna cum laude from the Catholic University of America's Columbus School of Law.

 

      To his left is Commissioner Nathan Simington. Commissioner Simington was nominated to the FCC by President Trump and was confirmed by the Senate in 2020. Before joining the FCC, Commissioner Simington served as the Senior Advisor at the National Telecommunications and Information Administration, the NTIA, where he worked on many aspects of telecommunications policy, including spectrum allocation and planning, broadband access, and the U.S. government's role in the internet.

 

      Before joining the FCC, Commissioner Simington was Senior Counsel to Brightstar Corporation, an international mobile device services company, where he led and negotiated telecommunications equipment and services deals with providers in over 20 countries. Before joining Brightstar, he worked in private practice. Commissioner Simington is a graduate of Michigan Law School and also holds degrees from the University of Rochester and Lawrence University.

 

      To his left is Mr. Jonathan Adelstein, a former commissioner of the FCC. Mr. Adelstein is president and CEO of WIA, the Wireless Infrastructure Association, which represents over 200 companies building telecommunication facilities across the world. Mr. Adelstein served as an FCC commissioner from 2002 to 2009, for which was twice nominated by President George W. Bush and confirmed unanimously by the Senate.

 

      At the FCC, he achieved bipartisan progress on issues like broadband expansion, widening access to the internet, and media diversity. In 2009, Commissioner Adelstein was nominated by President Obama to serve as the administrator of the U.S. Department of Agriculture's Rural Utility Service, where he oversaw a $6 billion portfolio of rural electric, water, and telecommunications infrastructure loans.

 

      Previously, Commissioner Adelstein held a number of legislative staff positions, over 15 years in the U.S. Senate, culminating as a senior policy adviser to the Senate majority leader. Commissioner Adelstein received an MA in history and a BA in political science from Stanford and attended the Kennedy School of Government at Harvard.

 

      And last but not least, former FCC Commissioner Mignon Clyburn, who's principal of MLC Strategies. Commissioner Clyburn spent nearly nine years at the FCC, affirming her commitment to closing persistent digital and opportunity divides that challenge rural, native, and low-wealth communities. Commissioner Clyburn served as Commissioner of the FCC from 2009 to 2018 and as Acting FCC Chairwoman from May to November of 2013.

 

      As an FCC commissioner, she pushed for the modernization of the FCC's Lifeline program, which assists low-income consumers in deferring the costs of voice and broadband service. She championed diversity and media ownership, initiated inmate telephone calling services reforms, brokered a technical solution that eliminated longstanding bottlenecks that prevented small rural telecommunications carriers from expanding their network services nationwide, she emphasized diversity and inclusion in the STEM fields, and she fought to preserve a free and open internet.

 

      Commissioner Clyburn's government service began with her election to the South Carolina Public Service Commission in 1998, where she served for 11 years. Before that, Commissioner Clyburn worked in a variety of media and telecommunications positions for over 14 years as publisher and general manager of The Coastal Times, a family-founded, Charleston-based weekly newspaper focusing on issues affecting the African-American community.

 

      It's my pleasure to then introduce all of you. Thank you for joining us today, and we'll begin, in terms of format, with opening statements from each of the panelists, followed by a discussion, and we'll conclude with a Q&A, taking questions from members of the audience. So with that, we'll hear from Commissioner Carr.

 

Hon. Brendan Carr: Thank you so much, Judge. Great to have you on the bench, and it's great to be with all of you here today. I guess for maybe an opening, I'll ask for a show of hands of how many people remember the great net neutrality repeal of 2017. We got a couple of veterans here. Of those people that remember, did you survive? Did you survive? Show of hands if you survived the great net neutrality repeal.

 

      I want to talk really briefly about two FCC proceedings and then explain to you why they aren't isolated pinpricks and why what you're seeing at the FCC in those instances is something you're seeing reflected more broadly across the administrative state right now. The first is what I call Title II, what has been popularly branded as net neutrality.

 

      So if you remember, for the very first time ever, the last two years of President Obama's administration, the FCC reclassified the internet from a Title I information service—a regulated service, but lightly regulated—to a Title II regulated service. Title II was the utility-style, heavy-handed regulations that were first invented to rein in the Ma Bell telephone monopoly, a point in time of New Deal-era legislation where it was really hard to distinguish between government and private sector.

 

      The FCC did that for two years. Then, when the administration changed over, the Trump administration, I was the commissioner, and we reversed that two-year experiment. And if you remember, when we did that, the predictions, if you remember, were quite astonishing. Senator Bernie Sanders had said that this is the end of the internet as we know it. If this passes, the internet and the free exchange of information we've come to know will cease to exist.

 

      CNN ran a banner headline that said "End of the Internet As We Know It." I got a message. Commissioner Clyburn likes this story. I got a message from a high school ex-girlfriend at the time, and she said that repealing net neutrality, I was about to make the second biggest mistake of my life. I can assure you that neither breaking up with her nor repealing Title II was a mistake.

 

Hon. Mignon Clyburn: He says in front of you right now.

 

Hon. Brendan Carr: Right. But what we were told was speeds would slow down. You'd get the internet one word at a time. And what has happened since that 2017 repeal of Title II? Internet speeds in the U.S. are up sixfold. Millions of Americans have been brought across the digital divide because of private sector buildout.

 

      And COVID-19 was the ultimate stress test of global telecom policy. In Europe, they were very worried that their continents' networks were going to break under the sudden strain of internet traffic that surged as people started working from home and schooling their kids remotely. We didn't have that over here because we had heavy investment in our networks.

 

      And so, just recently, as the judge indicated, we're back to 3-2 with the FCC for the first time. Commissioner Simington and I were in the minority. We were 2-2 for a while. 2-2 is my second best thing compared to being in the majority. It was a pretty good run, but now we're the minority. The very first thing the FCC does is now propose to bring back that Title II regulatory regime, which I think is going to be a mistake.

 

      Following right on the heels of that, the FCC has launched what is called a digital equity proceeding, and we're actually going to vote on a final order next Wednesday. President Biden had the congressmen weigh in at the FCC and encourage us to take a very strident interpretation of a one-page section of the 1000-plus-page infrastructure law was passed in 2021. It was a provision called Digital Discrimination that said the FCC should work to identify or eliminate discrimination that takes place in the broadband markets.

 

      The FCC has taken this one-page law and read it as giving us effectively unbounded authority over every single type of internet service and infrastructure in the country. If you just read through the list of the things that the FCC say in this one-page bill, which is not quite prophylactic, but it's mostly hortatory, mostly forward looking, what we're doing there is we're exercising control over where infrastructure can be built, how much profit an ISP can realize, the prices that can be charged, everything down to the length of time that an installation should take.

 

      And we're going to be second-guessing all of those decisions, and we reached the decision that it's somehow resulting in a harm to equity. Then you're potentially liable for unlimited fines from the FCC. And so I think you're seeing, whether it's Title II, whether it's digital equity, or again, some of the actions you see in other agencies, what's going on? And this is where I first started, which is to say, these aren't individual pieces of glass; there's a mosaic going on.

 

      And what's happening right now with the ministry of state, in my view, is that you've got this very progressive wing of the Democrat Party, Bernie Sanders, Elizabeth Warren, that has real outside influence when it comes to the administrative agencies right now in this administration. And we aren't having a reasoned debate right now within the agencies about, okay, a debate between the '40s, this person's a Democrat, they have their perspective, elections have consequences. I get it.

 

      We're not having the type of reasoned debate that you would expect in a divided government right now. What's happening is that wing of the Democrat Party is using the administrative state to really fundamentally alter the relationship between the government and the private sector. And it really goes back to this whole Title II New Deal-era mindset that we haven't really had a debate about in this country, let alone, from an electoral perspective, settled on fundamentally changing our relationship between the government and the private sector, but it's happening right now in the administrative of agencies.

 

      The good news along with this is where the Supreme Court is in terms of looking at some of the excesses of administrative agencies. West Virginia v. EPA effectively took what had been a dissent from the FCC's prior Title II decision by Judge Kavanaugh in the D.C. Circuit and is approximately making it the majority opinion at the Supreme Court.

 

      So while we are engaging in a lot of these regulatory excesses right now with the FCC in other agencies, I'm very confident that these are going to be reined back in eventually by the Supreme Court because, after all, we have not been delegated the authority to make these types of sweeping decisions. So with that, I'll end my filibuster and pass it on.

 

Hon. Michael Park: Thank you. Commissioner Simington.

 

Hon. Nathan Simington: Thanks very much. I'm very pleased to be here and to join my esteemed colleagues here on the panel. So on the subject of regulation, media regulation is very much in the news. There's a maelstrom of congressional and lobbying activity swirling around the question of so-called virtual MVPDs—that is, multichannel video programming distributors like cable and satellite TV—and whether the Commission ought to extend its authority to regulate retransmission consent negotiations—that is, the money that gets passed along for retransmitting broadcast content—over online linear video providers.

 

      I'm going to preview my own position on this one. I have no idea. There's no timely record before me. No member of the Commission can make a decision responsibly without record support, and so it shouldn't surprise anyone that my position is that a record refresh is warranted. It hasn't changed in the previous two years that I've been thinking about this VMVPD docket.

     

      I don't know whether it's possible to extend commission authority over VMVPDs, nor do I know whether it's the appropriate moment to do so as a matter of policy. A record refresh, a public notice inviting new comments on a decade-old proceeding, would merely arm the Commission with the facts on the law.

 

      And I'll soon be sending a reply to a congressional inquiry from a couple of weeks ago saying the same thing; it'll be at greater length. So one point I'm going to make in this letter is one that I'd like to discuss here today. Namely, we should reset our expectations because, without congressional action, I'm not sure that there is such a thing as Commission regulation of the immediate marketplace in the future.

 

      And maybe that's a good thing, but we should be clear that that's a decision that we're taking consciously and not by default. I've never given a partage of contemporary Commission wisdom and media regulation, goodness knows. I'm certainly not going to do so here. It may wind up being a good thing to let Commission authority over the video marketplace lapse.

 

      We may want to engage in a greater deregulatory trend to ensure that there isn't a two-tier system where facilities-based legacy broadcasters are penalized for doing that and over-the-top providers are allowed to exploit a regulatory middle. So peering into my crystal ball, however, I feel that's not what's on tap for the upcoming quadrennial review.

 

      Somehow, I imagine we'll discover or invent new and creative ways to extend Commission authority over even the smallest shade tree broadcasting outfits, rendering profitable operation and small DMAs fully impossible and paving the way towards what we all know is the goal of some groups in society and what they've said explicitly: government takeover of broadcast.

 

      So I guess this is where my discussion of jurisdiction starts to rhyme a little bit with what Commissioner Carr has been saying about government takeover of the internet. At a certain point, if broadcast becomes economically unviable yet we want to continue regulating it, that's the immediate future of broadcast media, having been rendered artificially uncompetitive with over the top.

 

      Depending on who you ask, two-thirds to four-fifths of domestic internet traffic goes to streaming video, and it should not surprise anyone to learn that, whenever new fiber trunk is installed in a rural area, most of the excess capacity is immediately soaked up by streaming video upscaling.

 

      Looking at it through this lens, high costs buildout subsidies, in effect if not in intent -- And I think it would have been pretty hard to sell this to the public in these terms, but it looks like a concerted effort to take and replace the legacy media transmission mode of over-the-air terrestrial broadcast, or even of installed cable and satellite systems, with a government subsidized Netflix pipe. Not to pick on Netflix in particular, but there's no doubt that a lot of this content is Netflix content. Of course, it could be any streaming provider.

 

      So when the future of media is fully streaming and the Commission, together with Congress, is making every effort to deliver on that vision, apparently, what's the statutory predicate of our authority? And here, we turn back again to the question of regulation over-the-top content.

 

      If we look at landmark decisions in terms of the FCC's jurisdiction over broadcast and over speech and broadcast, we're looking at Red Line and Pacific, which stood for the proposition that the Commission could pin back the ears of broadcasters, at least somewhat, as to protected speech because of the literal physical transmission modality of broadcast signals. That is because spectrum is scarce and managed by the FCC and because broadcast signals involuntarily penetrate the home and because the rival risks with one another.

 

      So broadcasting occupies a unique space in comparison to other media of protected speech. So, in other words, we've all lived our lives in a world where it's been a well-settled principle that, because broadcasters do these things, they don't have the full speech protections for protected speech that we would have in other media that are not so restricted, such as print.

 

      So whether those decisions remain good law in the current media marketplace and whether broadcasters ought to be treated in a fashion harmonized with other players—I'm not going to show my own biases here—maybe fully muted over the next decade anyway because, as broadcast falls into secular decline, aided lately by the vigorous efforts of the Commission, Commission authority over broadcast media and how it interacts with the First Amendment increasingly looks like a dead letter. Who cares whether the First Amendment protects a speech against Commission interference when there are simply no more licensed broadcasters for whom it would be an issue?

 

      Okay. So what about non-broadcast programming carried on MVPDs? We don't license them. We can't reach them as to content, and currently, there's no statutory or Court predicate for getting to that point. What about other bases of Commission authority over, say, cable systems? The '92 Cable Act give the Commissioning authority explicitly, and in general, the Commission relies on the facilities basis as the predicate of most of its authority over wireline system.

 

      So we still have cable systems and direct broadcast satellite in the regs because of those physical facilities that are involved. Great, except the cable systems are shedding millions of subscribers per year, as the American consumer chooses, and I use that word advisedly, considering the subsidy and regulatory arbitrage aspects that I've highlighted, but nonetheless chooses to get content on over-the-top channels.

 

      And, of course, we've all seen how well the satellite guys are doing lately. So while traditional MVPDs seem to have a little room left to run, it seems that the writing may start to be on the wall for them as well. And indeed, if you look at many cable operators who have both video business and an ISP business, they'll often tell you that it's the ISP business where they really see the runway.

 

      The future, whether consumers have asked for it or not, or whether it's simply emerged as a confluence of regulatory thumbs on the scale that no one really planned or intended, or whether there were people are arranging this for their benefit or engaging in opportunistic lobbying, the point is, the future is over the top.

 

      And the Commission cannot circumvent First Amendment restrictions on the basis of the physical characteristics of the medium, nor does it have a facilities basis as traditionally understood, undergirding its authority to regulate; therefore, edge providers who are further shielded by Section 230 protections are in a very strong position to say that there's just no such thing as content regulation in over-the-top.

 

      That may be how we expect it to wind out. From all the complaints that I hear from both sides of the aisle, I'm not sure that's a decision that anyone is comfortable with. If it's going to become the new normal, then we'd better start building out private ways to live with it. But in any case, our expectation that there's going to be speech regulation is just going to become falsified very quickly. Our anticipation of a regulated media environment is just not going to prevail.

 

      So it would appear the way things are trending that nothing will happen unless Congress takes this issue of with this degree of clarity, recognizing that the disparity in physical medium between watching a Bonanza rerun over the air and watching it on demand make the rhetoric of the regulatory environment completely different for those two situations.

 

      So Congress has got to consider whether we want to consciously walk into this situation or whether we're sleepwalking into it. They have to consider what their constituents are going to expect from them. They're going to have to ask the question, what does it mean for someone who spent 60, 70 years of their life growing up in a regulated media environment to suddenly be confronted with totally unregulated media at this point in our lives?

 

      What about interference? We hear so much about Russian interference in the elections or some other country's interference in the elections, all this kind of thing. What exactly are we supposed to do about it in an atmosphere of over-the-top where there's no political file? Nothing whatsoever is stopping anyone from buying anything on any show.

 

      So I want to make sure that I'm not calling for anything in particular so much as awareness of the situation and for us to appreciate the distinction between where we've been until now and where we're going to be now and going forward. Now, I guess, if I am going to make a call for action or a recommendation, it would be that the best thing the Commission can do right now in the media marketplace is just to get out of the business of broadcast regulation.

 

      I'm not saying that we need to turn it down to two guys and a dog—I'd settle for three—but there's really an angle to which we have to ask the question, what social good exactly is being served by media regulation that still pretends it's 1972 and that the big three rule the air? I think there's none.

 

      I think, at this point, we should be asking instead, what are we trying to preserve as far as localism and journalism, as far as a profitable, sustainable business model of whatever size in small- and medium-sized communities, in terms of real local relevance to advertising and not just feeding it into gigantic national social media campaigns in terms, I might add, of the maintenance of the emergency alerting systems that have always been funded not just in dollars and cents, but in terms of capacity and personnel and resilience by broadcasters?

 

      So there are a number of social goods that I think could be preserved just fine if we eliminated the regulatory arbitrage here and gave broadcasters a fair shake. So that's something that the Commission could do right away without waiting for congressional action, but otherwise, the ball is in Congress's court.

 

      The inflexible and mechanical application of legacy Commission rules is just going to continue to kill the broadcast sector while leaving the entire question of speech regulation off the field. In other words, we're going to stick by the environment of the '70s to say that we need to regulate broadcast speech and hug it to death and that, at the same time, we've got no reason to reach into anything else. That's just a pure path to dependence, folks. There's no rhyme nor reason to a policy approach like that.

     

      If Congress intends that the Commission should, in fact, regulate media in the future—which I'm not calling for—I just want to point out without intervention it simply will not. And people will have to think hard about finding a predicate that is, in fact, not violative of the First Amendment. Thanks very much. Looking forward to a lively discussion.

 

Hon. Michael Park: Thank you. Commissioner Adelstein.

 

Hon. Jonathan Adelstein: Well, thank you, Judge Park, and thanks for inviting me here today. I really appreciate it. It's nice to be on a panel with sitting Commissioners. We're the has-been commissioners, and the real ones are over there. We rarely get elevated to that level, but interestingly, these are Republican appointees, Democratic appointees on this side, so this room will be happy that the ones in power --

 

Hon. Brendan Carr: The capital also flows that way compared to this side. That's okay.

 

Hon. Jonathan Adelstein: Well, that could change. You know, I think I'm going to focus more since I'm not in the broadcast world now, Commissioner Simington, on Commissioner Carr's comments and really focus today particularly on some of the legal issues surrounding net neutrality and, to a lesser extent, the digital equity ruling.

 

      You know, net neutrality is something I've been involved in since the very outset of it in 2003 back on the Commission when we first looked into this, and it's really an article of faith on both sides, on the Democratic side and Republican side. First, as you pointed out, it's adopted under Obama by Wheeler, repealed under Trump with Ajit, and now proposed to be reinstated in almost the same form by Chairwoman Rosenworcel now that she's gained a majority.

 

      So previous court rulings, as you pointed out, forced the FCC to go into a Title II if they wanted to apply net neutrality, and that means treated, as you said, as common carriers, and these have to be just and reasonable. So it's very heavy-handed regulation. So the question, the basic tenets of net neutrality, which we started with back, and there was bipartisan agreement in the early days, where no blocking, no throttling, and no paid prioritization are largely complied with by ISPs.

 

      So going back, when it was pushed in the early 2000s by large cloud providers, like Google, as the white knight, in those days, they were beloved and seen as fighting for the good of the Internet to preserve free carriage, essentially at the expense of ISPs. And what we've seen since then is that it's inhibited carriers from monetizing their network investments in infrastructure, and it's now so entrenched in practice that the new rule won't change the status quo that gives cloud providers a free ride.

 

      And the cloud providers like Meta, Netflix, Google have captured the lion's share of the revenue, and certainly the profits, from the growth of the interne. And you look at the stock of some of the major carriers, it's exactly where it was in the mid-'90s, believe it or not. And you'd think, if you looked back in the mid-'90s and you say, "All right. Everybody's going to own one or two of these devices. Everybody's gonna use them. Nobody's going to live without them. There'll be more than one per person in the country" probably the major wireless carriers are going to be doing pretty well, right? And 20 years from now, well, their stock is flat or down in that period. It's pretty remarkable.

 

      But the stock of these companies that didn't exist at that time when they first began are in the trillions. So the FCC is going to finalize the new rules probably early to mid-year 2024, leading to another round of litigation. That's what might be of interest to discuss today to this crowd, is how the Supreme Court's major questions doctrine will apply with a two-to-three-year legal saga head.

 

      Now, coming from my perspective, the way that the major questions doctrine is being applied strikes me as judicial activism, attractive to rein in the administrative state as a counter to Chevron. So the question is whether the Courts or the expert agencies interpret congressional intent and statute when it's unclear.

 

      I served in the Senate staff for 15 years, as you pointed out. I was involved in basically writing the law. You know, the staff had a huge role in in writing these laws. And when I was in the minority leader's office, I was basically making the sausage. And it was very hard then to get Congress to get specific. You would think it was hard in the '90s. It's a lot harder now. So it's very difficult for Congress to get specific, which is why they delegate agencies and give them basic direction and to delegate to agencies how to interpret these statutes.

 

      And so the question here for me is, as somebody who's looked at the Constitution and served in two of the three branches, should the Courts or agencies interpret the statute fundamentally? And I say the expert agencies, not the Courts. And look at the way the Constitution is structured. Article I is Congress; Article II, the executive agencies; Article III is—of course, with all due respect to Judge Park—the ideas that law is obviously paramount.

 

      And the executive agencies are the ones to interpret and execute the laws, and the Courts are to hold them accountable to ensure that they do it in an honest way. Now, most issues at the FCC are bipartisan, and it truly performed its role effectively. I think that witness to that is the way that these two outstanding Commissioners handled the 2-2 situation, as you pointed out.

 

      Up until just very recently when the third Commissioner on the Democratic side was approved, the FCC got a lot done. And most of what we do is bipartisan, but some things get politicized. As I pointed out, net neutrality is probably the premier example of that. So the question for those of us who support Chevron deference for agencies is, is the FCC handing the Supreme Court a case that is ripe to overturn it?

 

      What's the justification for flip-flopping on policy every time the administration changes party hands? Is it truly an expert agency if it keeps changing? Well, to me, if it's going to change every time there's a change in control of the administration, there has to be evidence of a change in material circumstances that justify the shift in policy. Here, there's no evidence of a problem, as you pointed out; the internet is still alive and well. Hence, it's more ripe for getting overturned and setting what I think is a bad precedent.

 

      Now, it gets particularly interesting in this case because the irony is that Justice Thomas's opinion in the Brand X case cited Chevron to allow the FCC to decide whether to classify, under Title I or Title II, to deregulate certain ISPs. So in that decision, he said, "Oh, Chevron. This is the deregulatory." He says, "Great. Let's let Chevron rule."

 

      Now the decision has been used to impose a strong regulatory regime, Justice Thomas is questioning his own decision. See, now we're looking at flip-flopping by both the FCC and the Supreme Court. Both sides appear to me to be outcome driven. Which is worse: for a federal agency to be outcome driven or the Courts? I would argue the courts.

 

      We expect the Courts to be neutral arbiters. You expect at least some changes from administration to administration. And certainly looking at the changes in circumstances if they occur, the agency should be in a position to do that, and the Court should be neutral arbiter, so if there's a precedent here, why is it getting overturned?

 

      Well, is it a major questions issue, or is that an excuse? Could that be an excuse by the Courts for deregulation? How can the Supreme Court flip using this doctrine from the Brand X decision, which is so recent and so direct to the point? We expect consistent principle decisions from the Supreme Court, but the new version of the major questions doctrine appears outcome driven, and now they've got this case that could be handed where the agency's flip-flopping without an evidentiary basis.

     

      So you're seeing both agencies in the Supreme Court increasingly politicized, which I think undermines confidence in both as independent arbiters of the law. On the substance of the policy, in our industry, there's a serious concern with how the imposition of Title II impacts 5G in particular, which wireless carriers are clearly having trouble monetizing it, as I've discussed.

 

      And we've discussed this. There's an issue that the draft like the previous Wheeler rule subjects mobile to the same rules as wireline. But among the biggest upsides to 5G is its ability to facilitate private networks and slicing, which are, by nature, discriminatory. People here probably don't know about network slicing unless you're deep into the weeds on this telecom law, but essentially, under 5G, it's the first technology where carriers can take a piece of its spectrum and a piece of its network, basically slice it off, and allow a business to have a private little network of its own, which seems to be, in some ways, violative of the idea of net neutrality.

 

      But at the same time, there's an exemption for specialized services in the draft, but it's vague, so it's difficult for carriers to know if they're going to be able to engage in innovative solutions without further clarification from the FCC. So it could have a chilling effect on already depressed 5G capex.

 

      But to conclude on the major questions doctrine, I'd ask, when I think about that more broadly, why are we distinguishing major and minor issues? Statutory construction should be the same either way. Congress writes major and minor statutes with all kinds of vagaries in them that agencies have to distinguish.

 

      And I understand why the major questions doctrine says, "Well, if it's big, Congress wouldn't really delegate it without thinking about it, without having been more explicit about it," but I think the same applies to minor issues. So really, this seems like a power grab by the Court's judicial aggrandizement to say, "We're going to take over administrative law on the biggest issues in the country because Congress shouldn't be able to delegate on major issues, but they should be able to delegate a minor issues."

 

      But the FCC may be inviting an egregious example of overruling a precedent to apply this newfound major questions doctrine. So interesting situation that we're in from a legal perspective I wanted to talk about. And just to wrap up on the aggressive interpretation of the digital equity rules, I would agree, applying them far beyond I think what Congress intended doesn't make a lot of sense.

 

      For example, I'm at Digital Bridge now, and we invest in a lot of infrastructure. And we essentially follow where our customers want us to go. So if a carrier says, "I want a cell tower here, I want some fiber over there," we'll provide it, but then we're subject to being questioned as to whether we're providing digital equity when we're simply following our customers as to where they want us to place infrastructure.

 

      So applying it to infrastructure seems a step too far and, I think, beyond what Congress intended, which, again, is, I think, going to invite certainly some scrutiny in the courts, but I'd rather see that addressed by the FCC in advance. And I hope that, with the good work of these commissioners sitting here in the chair and the other commissioners, that can get addressed before they adopted it on November 15th, but I'm not overly confident.

 

Hon. Nathan Simington:  Unlikely. Unlikely.

 

Hon. Jonathan Adelstein:  I'm not overly confident.

 

Hon. Nathan Simington:  Magic 8 Ball says, not going to happen.

 

Hon. Jonathan Adelstein:  You heard it here first. Whoops. I guess that's not going to happen. Well, pray on. Thank you very much for the time. I'll wrap it there.

 

Hon. Michael Park: Thank you. Commissioner Clyburn.

 

Hon. Mignon Clyburn: Thank you, Judge Park. It's a pleasure being here. Thank you, Brian Tramont for the invitation. Either you'll get blamed or uplifted. And also please allow this. I'm from South Carolina, and Steve Matthews is here from my old high school, so allow me to say hello in the back from the gentleman who just had a big smile back there. It's good to be here.

 

      Nine years ago, in Hillary Shaub's Brooking Institute commentary commending the Act's 80th anniversary, she described the Communications Act of 1934 as being considered at the time, and I quote, "A minor piece of legislation bundled with the New Deal." And if radioworld.com is right, the standard government printed text version of the '34 Act numbered some 45 pages with six titles.

 

      Fast forward 89 years—a substitute check, as you lawyers like to say—nearly 300 pages later, you have challenged us this afternoon with an intriguing theme -- whatever it is. Originalism. I'm cold, so if you hear things -- and the Communications Act of 1934. Clearly, this is no longer considered a minor piece of legislation.

 

      I find it fascinating, so I'm the one you'll throw darts at today, but I'll just go ahead and accept that. So get ready. I find it fascinating to hear scholars, academicians, jurists, and likely more than a couple of you in this room adhere to the concept that all statements in the United States Constitution should be interpreted strictly according to how it would have been understood or intended at the time of its adoption in 1787.

 

      Now, if I am interpreting this position correctly and were to apply that same standard or concept to the Communications Act of 1934, I would not only have to wrestle with its first major overhaul in 62 years in the form of the '96 Act, but the predecessor laws of 1906, 1910, 1912, and 1927, each responding to a changing landscape to regulate safety frequencies, licensing, and operating guidelines.

 

      In the 1934 Act, as you know, the FCC was created to manage administrative and broadcast issues of the day, as well as to regulate interstate and foreign communications, among many other responsibilities. And if I may continue with my analogy, the 27 amendments enacted between 1791 and 1990 to reflect changing societal values not contemplated, nor enacted in 1787.

 

      The point for me here is that, with every technological advance, every creative development, minute entrance, every policy shift, there has been a corresponding reinterpretation redefining statutory overlay or rewriting of laws regulating, or not, companies in this space. Granted, 62 years is a very long time, given the shifts that had been occurring in the marketplace, and the '96 Act was offered as an answer to our struggle to keep pace with an evolving technologically advancing landscape.

 

      The complexity and difference between policy, competitive, and technological issues today, policy issues from 1934—and yes, even 1996—seem dizzying to me. But what I suspect near-universal agreement on is that we have reached another inflection point where there is friction on how much or how little we do to establish new policy to address the evolving issues at hand.

 

      As a baseline, I suggest, as nirvana is a creation of policy where all stakeholders articulate exactly what the problem is and where all stakeholders are an agreement, but nirvana is a word rarely used, making it difficult to set a successful agenda around an issue with consensus. But the primary objective, in my humble opinion, should always be to prevent any one party from framing an issue in the form of the resolution or outcome they would like to see, not what the times call for.

 

      As an easy example, though I know the FCC is not in the price regulation business, would be if one party proclaims that the issue should be that we should be charged less when the actual issue and question should be, what is the appropriate pricing tool. Fully understanding the issue, consequences, and each option before us and their likely policy outcome is the most intense, informative, reflective, and time-consuming exercise.

 

      Listening to parties' positions and arguments, sifting through subject matter interests with public interest groups, special interest groups, interested parties, and often legislate towards comments and concerns. That's a complex and dynamic process. All of this, of course, precedes the adoption and implementation, then monitoring and assessment of what is ultimately decided.

 

      Congressional legislation, executive orders, judicial interpretation, the agency's decision being upheld again or struck down, and whatever public policy modification, all of these influences decisions or shift triggers. And you have, let's just call it, a very fluid, dynamic set of challenges that will enable us to do good or challenge us to do better.

 

      And then, of course, are the decision-makers on my right, a total of five of them, finally, who no doubt, just like I did before the summer of 2018 where I took my leave, have been asked and challenged more than once when it comes to policymaking, should the goal be to prevent or correct potential market failures or harms before they occur, or rather to rely on enforcement or remedies after a harm/violation has occurred?

 

      I am acutely aware that ex-ante regulation is aggressively proactive while ex-post regulation is not. And while one attempts to anticipate, address, or mitigate what could be irreversible or costly harms as opposed to responding after problems materialize, if you ask me, my answer when challenged with that question would not surprise you: It depends.

 

      It depends on the type of action, market segment, entry barriers, systemic risk, and other factors made on a case-by-case basis depending on the facts in play at the time. And that is why I sometimes arm wrestle with my colleagues because I understand when it comes to the net neutrality re-debate, however many times we are re-ing --

 

Hon. Nathan Simington:  According to [inaudible 00:45:16].

 

Hon. Mignon Clyburn:  You know, I come from the posture, that won't surprise you, that we make decisions and policies and rules and laws, not based on the best of times when everything is swimming, but on those times when the most vulnerable have something to be concerned about, and we are concerned about them and their outcomes.

 

      But what is known and measurable with all of this dynamic, the state of our economy, our priorities, and stated needs were influenced by international domestic trends, political and legal dynamics, and the public expectation. That's the number one priority and the number one influencers, particularly at the community level.

 

      There, and primarily there, will influence and determine where the agency leans, but not always where the agency lands when it comes to advanced services. And the collective successes or failures of the majority of the five will be measured, always, by whichever party, whichever influencers have the ears over the congressional or judicial branches. So today, it's net neutrality. As we've said, I've lost count.

 

Hon. Brendan Carr:  Tomorrow will be neutrality again.

 

Hon. Mignon Clyburn:  Okay. Well, in the global today, we have net neutrality, as was mentioned, the prevention of digital discrimination rules to be debated, spectral policy, including the impact of the lack of authority, that allocation of spectrum efficiently and among -- and fairly among commercial providers, federal agencies, public safety entities, and consumers, while considering all of those technical and economic aspects of spectral management, such as interference sharing and pricing, broadband deployment rules, data and mapping, the harmonization of various programs that have been layered to address the needs, particularly at the pandemic and [inaudible 00:47:44]  age, what survives and what does not?

 

      You know, robocalls, the emergency alert systems, rights-of-way fees, USF for me and its principles, and its future, including, like I said, those legal challenges—and yes, I am going to mention it—the contribution factor. So we're at a very interesting time, and I know everyone says this, but it is particularly interesting because we are wrestling with a number of things.

 

      You've got the calls for access to affordable, reliable, and high-quality digital infrastructure, mobile networks, again cloud computing, e-government that can enable communities to access information, education, healthcare, entertainment, and social services, as well as full participation in civic and economic activities.

 

      You've got calls for inclusion and equity in the design, development, and use of technologies, especially from marginalized and vulnerable groups. Older adults, which I have become; people with disabilities; those who are from low-income and rural communities, they face barriers assessing, and they face barriers benefiting from the technology that many of us in this room take for granted.

 

      Again, you've got calls for empowerment and engagement of communities in shaping this technological landscape, particularly as the money is flowing to state and local governments. There's a need for resilience and the adaptation of rapid and complex changes that technologies bring to social, economic, and environmental aspects of the communities; technologies creating new challenges, opportunities, and, yes, risk in these communities; the tackling and the addressing of the digital divide, cyberattacks, misinformation, automation, displacement, and again, environmental impacts; communities crying, for the capacity to cope and to respond to these challenges as well as leveraging the opportunities that these technologies and the times offer us.

 

      And then there's AI and its implications, particularly those who feel that there are vulnerabilities and unevenness and inequities abound. So I end as I begin. And I often rely on history, being the daughter of a former history teacher and librarian, that I hear you speak about the shifts, the ebbs and flows as if it were something new or unpredictable. It is not.

 

      You have laws, decisions that, in some ways, seem static, but you have interpreters through policymakers and other interested parties that will demand of us that constant reinterpretation and reapplication of what seemingly is static and finite to address the interests and the challenges of today.

 

      So, to me, while I know there are tensions and disappointments among all of us, depending on what decision we do or do not make, none of this is surprising. All of this is quite understandable because the communities that we serve and the people who are on the wrong side of some of these issues will demand that we interpret every law and every rule in a way that will improve their communities. That is a constant that is evolving, and all of that is to be expected. Thank you.

 

Hon. Michael Park:  Thank you, Commissioner, and thanks to all of you for your thoughtful and thought-provoking statements. Let me open up the discussion by just giving all of you a chance to respond to anything that you heard from each other that you want to react to, respond to, expand on.

 

Hon. Brendan Carr:  Thanks so much. I'll pick up a little bit on my good friends' comments on the major questions doctrine. I have some differences of opinion there, I'll say. Fundamentally, I think, in my view, the major question doctrine operates in a very neutral way. It is not an expression of substantive preferences or will.

 

      So if Congress passes a law that is regulatory in nature and an agency uses it to deregulate, you can run afoul of the major questions doctrine. Similarly, if they tell us to deregulate and you regulate, the opposite. You get the same outcome. But I also want to step back in terms of the separation of powers and almost a constitutional question and think about it from a policy perspective.

 

      And you ask, why would it make sense that there'd be a major questions doctrine, but you have to be lesser questions that could be delegated? I think, fundamentally, it goes back to the quip about elephants in mouse holes, meaning you can actually hide mice in mouse holes, that that's sort of okay, but that you cannot hide elephants in mouse holes once it gets sufficiently large.

 

      But I think, more than that, from a policy perspective, if you have this concept of Chevron -- And I understand there's a broader debate about Chevron, but when you have Chevron, there's an incentive structure in Congress for legislators to get together, and they pass a bill. And maybe they can't get it exactly the way they want and still pass it, but they can get it to, what I said earlier, between the 40s. Okay.

 

      We generally agree that the outcome should be somewhere in here, and we're delegating authority to an agency to figure it out from there. And again, you can make arguments to why that is a bad thing, but that creates a dynamic that is the opposite of what happens in the absence of a major questions doctrine.

 

      What happens in the absence of a major questions doctrine is you have legislatures, politicians refusing to come to the middle because they don't have to, and one of the great examples of that is Title II. So there was a lot of people that agree that we'd be better off if Congress passed a law on Title II or net neutrality, whatever the branding is, and there are our bills in Congress, but they all come from the left or from the right with a poison pill. And I'll give one on the left.

 

      On the left, there's a legislation that says we're going to put not the net neutrality rules themselves in place, but the actual agency decision itself from 2015, 2016, which obviously Congress doesn't have to do because they could just legislate anew, but they're refusing to do that. Why? Because they know there's a safety valve, and that safety valve is they can stake out an extreme position in Congress, not work to the middle, towards consensus, because an agency is going to come in and do exactly what it is that they want to do on a 3-2basis.

 

      And so I think, again, putting aside separation of powers, constitutional considerations, there is a policy value in the major questions doctrine of compelling, of forcing, to some extent, elected representatives to do their job. So it's not forcing them to do it; it is removing a safety valve that is harming our politics.

 

      There was op ed recently in The Washington Post, and they said, "We oppose the FCC's decision a couple years ago to do Title II regulation of the internet because we thought it was a mistake. The FCC is doing it again now, and we, The Washington Post editorial board, are slightly flipping our position. Why? Because they say the internet is too important to be left unregulated. And so we think it is time for the FCC to move forward with Title II."

 

      And that's the problem. When you have this safety valve of the agency doing it, people start saying, "This is too important. Someone must do something. An agency must step in." But if we have these abilities of the agencies to do it, it takes that off the table for Congress to have. So this problem probably should be solved permanently, but it's one that Congress can do.

 

      But without major questions doctrine, without a hard look at Chevron, we are making it easy for Congress, and there's lots of incentive structures right now for members of Congress to go to their corner and not compromise. So it is constitutional, it's separation of powers, but I also think it's the right thing that will drive the people's actual elected representatives to the middle to compromise.

 

      Hon. Jonathan Adelstein:  I think I'll respond to the response. You know, having worked in Congress for 15 years, maybe that's why I think the Articles of the Constitution were in order for a reason, but also the history of it says the same thing, that Congress sets the rules. And how difficult is that to do? I, as I said, made the sausage. Working for the majority leader, our job was basically to get consensus, and it's very interesting to think about how that job works.

 

      Basically, a lot of the time, I wasn't worried about so much the policy as I was about getting unanimous consent. This is in the '90s, early 2000s, always trying to get unanimous consent when we're in the majority. We're working with the minority to see if we can get agreement on things. If it's not a major issue in the Senate, anybody can amend anything, anytime. So you want to get something done, you've got to take as many of these amendments as you can.

 

      So it's like open season. If there's something you can't agree on, then you get into a vote, but we want to minimize the number of things that go to a vote. So the job is essentially, one, a building consensus, and the Senate is designed that way, constantly sublimating our own policy concerns as the leader to the broader role of the Senate in coming together. And the way you do that is, often, you got to take off the rough edges.

 

      I don't know how many amendments we said, "Well that's really pissing off Senator So-and-so, so we're got to take that out. Can we adjust this? That gets Senator XYZ mad. Can't we all just agree on this?" Okay. Fine. This is back in the days when Congress functioned well. It still functions the same way; the problem is you just don't get to that compromise for a number of reasons, as it's been politicized.

 

      So the fact that Congress can't write specific statutes is not a new problem. I'm old, so I guess there's no problem going back to me, but I think it goes back further than me. Even looking at the Communications Act of '34, you still have, even in the 19th century and 18th century, difficulty of getting very specific in statutes. So statute by requirement and the design is always going to be a little bit higher level.

 

      You talk about written by a committee. Well, they have committees, lots of committees, and when you're done with the committee, you got the full body. So you're talking about a Frankenstein monster. By the time the statute gets out of there, there's been a lot of hands on it, and it's a consensus document because you also get the president to sign it at the end.

 

      So that was a Herculean effort to get acts of Congress done, and now the Courts are saying, "Well, Congress wasn't specific enough on the major questions, so we're not going to let the agencies interpret it." Well, Congress has the ability to go back if they think an agency overstepped its bounds.

 

      First of all, traditional statutory construction allows the Courts to say, "This is inconsistent with the statute," and there's no reason they need to change how that's done. Whether it's the major questions or not, you don't have to give Chevron deference to agencies that depart from the clear statutory intention, but you have to give them some deference to be able to interpret vague statues in ways that bring their expertise to bear and not have the Court substitute its opinion that this is something Congress has got to go back and do when they know full well Congress is not going to do it.

 

      And further, Congress has the ability to go back if it thinks that agency overstepped or misinterpreted the way that it intended for law to be executed. They can rewrite the law. It's the same issue. They got to go through that whole consensus process, but they can rewrite it. They even put in place a thing called the Congressional Review Act, which means that, in the Senate, it's a privileged motion to basically repeal a regulation, and this was applied to FCC regulations and ready to pass a few times, but ultimately, it was vetoed by the president on FCC regulations.

 

      On broadcast in particular, going back to media ownership rules, I think you could say that -- I think that the major questions doctrine is a way of bringing more power to the Courts to basically second-guess almost what agencies are doing and have them be the final arbiter of what Congress intended rather than the agencies on issues where, clearly, Congress would expect the agencies to act and have some discretion.

Hon. Michael Park:  I'm wondering if you could give us a sense of the textual arguments. How did we get from 1934 Act about radio to this conversation? And the major questions document will obviously be an interesting and important part of whatever cases come out of this unfold, but can you just give, as background, some of the textual arguments in Title I, Title II? What is it that we're talking about, and how did we get from radio to net neutrality?

 

Hon. Jonathan Adelstein:  It's hard to change those. We're stuck in this Title I, Title II environment, which I don't think is -- It's a problem the Congress can't act to change that. So basically, the Court's forced -- If they wanted to regulate net neutrality, the agency was not able to do under it Title I, so it's basically forced to go to Title II, then they end up forbearing from a lot of requirements which they didn't intend. So it's extremely awkward, the fact that Congress has been able to change the fundamental structure since 1934, that the FCC is working under this awkward dynamic.

 

Hon. Nathan Simington:  Right. So, with 1934, we've got two things: We've got the radio regulation, and then we've got the telephone regulation, right? And, of course, with radio regulation, this emerged because radio stations with the limited spectrum that could be sent and received, particularly at that time -- Obviously, we can operate in more frequencies now, but with the limited spectrum on which you can transmit or receive at the time, there was a need for some kind of geographic exclusivity and for some sort of separation by frequency.

 

      And so there's a coordinating function that you need to do. That's our radio authority. As far as the telephone stuff, let's remember, the United States was the only country in the world that had a private telephone system by 1934. The British had one for a while, and it got nationalized. A lot of other places, it was just built by the post office in the first place.

 

      So the whole idea of a private telephone system was a compromise between the facts on the ground of the capabilities that AT&T had brought to the market. I want to point out that it was already in the trust-busting era that AT&T was making its first deals with the Justice Department back in 1913, right? So this long predates the New Deal as such. It was much more of a recognition that the Bell system had won the fights among the many early telephone companies to reach a combination of the most customers with the best service, with the sharpest elbows, with sometimes exclusions of other parties from their long lines and technical standards, from supplying the phones themselves, which, let's remember, you didn't used to be able to buy a phone. You had to lease it from the phone company.

 

      So that's the world where we're coming from, where it was the federal government going, you might say, back to the first Roosevelt presidency—never mind the subsequent ones—that was grappling with the question, how are we going to keep a private phone system working when it's an inherently exclusionary natural monopoly? And that's where all of this Title II stuff comes from.

 

      The reason that we have the whole concept of Title I service is that we used to be able to do all kinds of other stuff over the phone. I don't know if anyone ever use Dial A Joke. Famously, that was Woz's first consumer product back then he was a --

 

Hon. Brendan Carr:  I dialed the time. I could do that.

 

Hon. Nathan Simington:  So what it used to be, if you lived in Berkeley, you could call up Steve Wozniak's phone number that he'd set up specifically with an answering machine that had a different Polish joke every day. So that's a Title I service, right? We're not going to say there's a natural monopoly and polish jokes; in fact, that they seem to be quite widely disseminated.

 

      But the point is, if your service is stock quotes, if your service is voicemail, if your service is Dial A Joke, it makes sense that you're not going to treat that like that's monopoly. You're an AT&T that's the only place that can run a phone line into people's houses and that controls all the switching stations and that manufactures all the phones and all the switchboards and whatnot through subsidiaries.

 

      So we find ourselves, as my colleagues have said, with a law that seems rather poorly adapted to the times. If we're going to say that we need to have the Title II framework, then we're really saying that we need to have the system that was set up as an alternative to nationalizing AT&T back when AT&T was the only game in town, and that we're going to apply it to every internet service provider in the country, including the wireless ones that talk to our phones.

 

      That puts us, again, in an even more convoluted situation because, if we're going to say that you can't discriminate and that there's de facto unlimited settlement-free peering—in other words, the phone has to take wherever it gets pushed down to it—obviously, we want that in a certain sense. We don't want your phone picking and choosing what websites you're allowed to go to, but it also means that the federal government, which constrains the supply of spectrum, is providing the spectral equivalent of an unfunded mandate, right? They're saying, "Your phone has to take whatever gets pushed down, but we won't provide the spectral resources to do it."

 

      It's a very tough question. And I love it when Congress answers these sorts of questions for us because that resolves a degree of ambiguity. As for how do we deal with the statutory language when the social facts have changed this time and the other time and the third time, let's think back to the '96 Act, which, as Commissioner Clyburn pointed out, was the last time that Congress fully wrapped its arms around the question.

 

      At that time, your internet service and your phone company were two different things, more or less. You had dial-up internet service, right? A few fortunate people had T1 lines or DSL, but it was mainly dial-up internet, and there was a natural disconnect between your ISP. ISP used to mean the company that was connecting you to your internet service via your phone line, rather than the company that provided the line. There was a natural split between that.

 

      And so we wound up in this area where it seemed obvious that the phone line was still a natural monopoly, but that your internet service provider was a specialized service that you would get over it. So in other words, it's a Title I service. And again, with the consolidation of those two things, we've been striving to unpick this thing.

 

      Brand X came up. Well, that's where Justice Scalia raised his famous pizzeria arguments, in fact, Title I treatments in favor of Title II treatment. He's saying, "Can you really separate these? If you're getting the line and the service from the same place, isn't this like the pizzeria saying, 'We don't offer delivery. All we do is bake a pizza and send it to your house.' Two different services." But that shows the difficulty of grappling with this. Justice Thomas has repudiated his position in Brand X, but it remains good law. Good law enough to base for the decisions? I say it's a very muddled situation.

 

Hon. Brendan Carr:  I'll just add, this is why, when people talk to Republican commissioners, they say, "Are you referring to the smart one or the other one?" That's an example of why people make that distinction right there. On Brand X, too, I think we have to recognize there's been a sea change with West Virginia v. EPA. What Brand X said was, "We think it is ambiguous as to whether the internet should be treated as a Title I or Title II service."

 

      And now what we know after West Virginia v. EPA, is that that is a decision that cuts against Title II, meaning the presence of mere ambiguity is no longer enough post-West Virginia v. EPA to impose Title II classification. In fact, Donald Verrilli, the former Obama Solicitor General, filed a paper at the FCC saying exactly that, which is, today, post-West Virginia v. EPA to turn the internet from a Title I to a Title II service would run afoul of West Virginia v. EPA.

 

Hon. Michael Park:  We have a few minutes left, so let me open up the floor to see if there's any questions from the audience.

 

Audience Member:  Should we go to the microphones?

 

Hon. Michael Park:  Yeah, I think that's probably better. Yeah. For people who are watching online.

 

Hon. Brendan Carr:  No pressure. There's like eight people watching online, so don't mess this up.

 

Gracia la Pastore:  Hi. My name is Gracia la Pastore. I'm at Jones Day. I have two questions, actually. The digital equity initiative that you were discussing in the beginning, Commissioner Carr, was probably not foreseen by Congress in passing the infrastructure bill. So do you or the other Commissioners foresee the FCC or other agencies continue to needing to have their regulations shut down by the Supreme Court and the major questions doctrine, or do you think that they're now going to reformulate? Because what it sounds like is that they're going to maybe keep pushing, from what you've all discussed, and it's very expensive to overturn every administrative agency decision. So it's kind of two questions in one. That's just the first question.

 

Hon. Brendan Carr:  Yeah. Thanks. My view is yes. We are going to vote next Wednesday. It's going to pass, this digital equity provision. As you noted, it was based on one page of law of the 1000-plus page of the 2021 Infrastructure Act. It did not contemplate, let alone authorize us, to adopt this sweeping, intrusive set of rules. I think this is going to be another instance where West Virginia v. EPA and the harder look that Courts are giving at Chevron is going to result in an overturning of the FCC's decision. Again, it's going to be a waste of resources to get there, but thankfully, for you, being at Jones Day, you can benefit from some of the waste of resources on the way there.

 

Gracia la Pastore:  Yeah. I also have a second question, which is, as current and former commissioners at an administrative agency, can you contemplate a legislative solution to limiting agencies from broadening their powers outside of the Courts, or is it only the Courts? Because, as I just said, it is extremely expensive to continue to have to overturn these agency decisions, and especially when they've gone so off the cuff or they've gone in such a different direction. So is there another solution to limiting their powers?

 

Hon. Jonathan Adelstein:  It could be more specific. Congress can be more specific. I think that's the goal of some of those who are pushing the major questions is for Congress to specify exactly what they mean in terms of what the level of delegation is and what agencies should do. But the way Congress is moving since my days there—and I think everybody sees this—is that it's more difficult to do that, not less, given the polarization and the way that Congress is functioning.

 

      It used to function much more on a bipartisan basis where that was also difficult, but now unless you get one party control of both and 60 votes in the Senate, which only happened for a very brief period under Obama, and then we haven't seen it since, there is a very great difficulty in getting that done.

 

Hon. Nathan Simington:  Let's see. I'll go ahead and defer to you.

 

Gracia la Pastore:  Okay. Thank you very much.

 

Hon. Michael Park:  Thank you. I think we have time for one more.

 

Ben Slifka:  Ben Slifka visiting from Seattle, retired monopolist. I remember the days of 110 baud dial-up modems, but I took a Starlink antenna up to 74 degrees north in Canada in July. I got 140 megabits a second down and 40 megabits a second up. And I think you'll see the prevalence of satellite internet service increase dramatically, and the prices will drop dramatically. How would that change the discussions you've had?

 

Hon. Brendan Carr:  I should defer to you, given the Canadian nature of the question. Simon is from Canada. Well, one thing that's interesting is—and this goes to some of the backwards nature of regulation—is a lot of people at the FCC, not myself, will look at the fact that you have that high-quality service from a low Earth orbit satellite, Starlink, and some people if we say it's great and some people will say, "Well, we're actually going to treat that as if it's zero megabits per second over zero megabits per second because we have a policy preference to build fiber to 100 percent of the locations."

 

      So when you hear people talk about the digital divide in this country, there's all sorts of juicing the numbers. You'll hear this number about 15 or 16 million people, but what you're actually seeing with that is that's some of the people that don't have a fixed, wired internet connection. But if you look at people have access to all sorts of different technologies to get what they want, which is just, I want my phone to work, the number is much lower. So I think we should be looking to those types of technologies to complement what we have, but there's a policy override that's getting in the way. I don't know if you want to add.

 

Hon. Nathan Simington:  You know, I was just about diving forward to eat my microphone when you came because I think the very first speech I ever gave after taking office at the Free State Foundation for Randy May was that we have a wide diversity of mechanisms for delivery at the last mile at this point. And that really undermines the rationale for Title II since the whole point of natural monopoly is that it actually is an exclusionary monopoly.

 

      If you can get fixed wireless service that's just as fast as wired, and if you can get satellite on top of that, then you don't just have three different services; you have three different mediums of service with potential from multiple providers in each one of those. And I think, under those circumstances, it would have been very hard to justify Title II in the first place, and it wouldn't have been justified, and there wouldn't have been a rivalry between, for example, the Bell system and the telephone systems.

 

      If they all could have been delivered wirelessly using a small number of facilities to cover a wide area, then there never would have been telephone monopolies in the first place, and we'd be looking at a very different history of telecommunications. Now what we have, if anything, is a wide diversity of physical media of connection leading up to a relatively small number of upstream services, which are arguably the ones where we should start asking questions about common carriage in this day and age.

 

      So it's a very, very different situation from what we saw before. Personally, I would feel much less upset if I got fired by my wireline ISP to my house because I would turn to the hotspot on my phone and be back online in three or four seconds. I'd feel a lot less upset about that than being barred from one of the big four or five big techs' ecosystems because, my ISP fires me, I can get a new one. When I pick up my phone, I have a new one. I drive down to Starbucks, and I have a new one.

 

      You know, it's really not a big deal compared to what it used to be if, for example, AT&T were to ban you from its system, but if you get demonetized from a site where you've got millions of followers, or what you base your living on and where you've expected that the terms of service were going to sustain you, and then all of a sudden, you get fired off of that, that's a very, very different world.

 

      So if we were writing the ranks under contemporary circumstances, there's no way we would wind up here. There's no way Congress would have brought us here. And increasingly, we're clinging to this last mile. We're like the drunk looking for his keys. You know, everyone knows this joke. The drunk looking for his keys under the streetlight. Right. And he's like, "I lost my keys in the alley." "Well, why are you looking over here?" "Because the light is better here."

 

      You know, we've got a clear regulatory predicate for reaching the last mile ISPs because we always did because that was how monopoly AT&T worked. If that isn't relevant anymore, then there's the question of, if we do have a predicate to act but it's no longer wise to act, to what degree should we still be acting?

 

Hon. Jonathan Adelstein:  Yeah, having been there in the early days, I completely concur with your point, and your point is valid on the on the capacity issue. Going back to the early days, 2003, the concern was there wasn't adequate capacity from ISPs, so they needed to be regulated in order to ensure that they didn't throttle in order to advance their own services, perhaps, or advance their own content to the degree that they acquired it.

 

      Right now, there's so much capacity and so much competition that those arguments are really moot, as you pointed out, and I think that's a good example. Even satellite is an option. If Verizon My Fios was discriminating, I'd go to Comcast in my neighborhood. Now, some places have less options, but ultimately, they do have SpaceX. There generally is competition for basic broadband, that the speeds are so much faster, there's really no incentive or ability for carriers to discriminate in the way that was originally the concern that prompted early calls for going to Title II. So I'd really concur with you on that.

 

Hon. Mignon Clyburn:  And two things I will add to that is there is not evenness, so the absolutes that I think I'm hearing here don't necessarily exist in every hamlet in this nation when it comes to opportunities at my doorstep. And I continue to bring up that there are a lot of economic incentives, a lot of economic capacity that we see flowing through the states from the government.

 

      Again, the traditional and legacy incentives to do some of the harms that you hear people like me speaking about, they're not there today. My issue is always, do we have the proper backstops in terms of ensuring and protecting those when tomorrow comes and the nature of all of this and the conversations we're having and the money and all of the incentives are no longer there? Will these companies and will some of your clients act in the same manner? And if they don't, what type of backstop, regulatory or otherwise, would they have if individuals are harmed?

 

 

Hon. Michael Park:  Okay. Well, we're out of time, but thank you so much to our panelists for this really great discussion. One quick announcement before we adjourn: If you have time, we encourage you to visit the Remnant Trusts Rare Documents Exhibit. It's in the South Carolina Room. It's open throughout the convention, so please stop by. They have, this year, some original pieces of history, including the Life and Times of Frederick Douglass, History of Women's Suffrage, and the Magna Carta. With that, thanks everyone. We're adjourned.

2:00 p.m. - 3:00 p.m.
Insurrection and the 14th Amendment

2023 National Lawyers Convention

Topics: Constitution • Fourteenth Amendment
Grand Ballroom
The Mayflower Hotel
1127 Connecticut Avenue NW
Washington, DC 20006

Share

Event Video

Listen & Download

Description

Updated 12/20/2023: The Colorado Supreme Court recently decided Former President Donald Trump in ineligible to appear on the 2024 ballot. Read that decision here.

Featuring:

  • Prof. William Baude, Professor of Law and Faculty Director, Constitutional Law Institute, University of Chicago Law School
  • Prof. Michael W. McConnell, Richard and Frances Mallery Professor and Director, Constitutional Law Center, Stanford Law School; Senior Fellow, Hoover Institution
  • Moderator: Prof. Julia D. Mahoney, John S. Battle Professor of Law and Joseph C. Carter, Jr. Research Professor of Law, University of Virginia School of Law

Speakers

Event Transcript

Nate Kaczmarek:  Good afternoon. Good afternoon. Please take your seats. Hello, and thank you for joining us. My name is Nate Kaczmarek. I’m Vice President and Director of the practice groups for The Federalist Society. I hope you are enjoying day two of our convention. It’s my pleasure to welcome you to this special session on “Insurrection and the Fourteenth Amendment.” The topic is obviously a big one. We could spend the whole conference exploring the many aspects of this theme, but we only have 60 minutes, and so I will quickly introduce our moderator and look forward to our conversation amongst three great scholars.

 

       I was asked by our moderator to keep her introduction to one sentence, and so I will reluctantly oblige. Professor Julia Mahoney is the John S. Battle Professor of Law and Joseph C. Carter Jr. Research Professor of Law at the University of Virginia School of Law, and we are delighted to have her guide this conversation. With that, please join me in welcoming her and our discussants. 

 

Prof. Julia Mahoney:  Good afternoon. Thank you for being here for our discussion of “Insurrection and the Fourteenth Amendment.” We are very lucky to have two extremely distinguished scholars here who have distinct yet, in some respects, overlapping views. I will introduce them briefly—their full bios are available in your materials—then each will provide an opening statement of approximately 12 minutes, after which I will ask a couple of questions to get our discussion going. Then we will turn this over to all of you and entertain audience questions. We have only one hour for an event that I am confident could last until midnight so keep questions short. Thank you all in advance.

 

       So first, we have William Baude. He is the Harry Calvin Jr. Professor of Law and the Faculty Director of the Constitutional Law Institute at the University of Chicago Law School. And we also have with us, Michael W. McConnell. He is the Richard and Frances Mallery Professor and Director of the Constitutional Law Center at Stanford Law School, as well as a Senior Fellow at the Hoover Institution. From 2002-2009, Professor McConnell served as a circuit judge on the United States Court of Appeals for the Tenth Circuit. So with that -- 

 

Michael McConnell:  Where Will was one of my best law clerks, so I claim everything he knows he learned from me.

 

[Laughter]

 

Prof. Julia Mahoney:  No doubt. So Professor Baude, I turn it over to you.

 

Prof. William Baude:  Thank you. Could we have the first slide with the text on it? The next slide. Thanks. Our topic is Section Three of the Fourteenth Amendment, which says that “No person shall be a senator or representative in Congress, or elector of president and vice president, or hold any office, civil or military, under the United States, or under any state who, having previously taken an oath as a member of Congress, or as an officer of the United States, or as a member of any state legislature, or as an executive or judicial officer of any state to support the Constitution of the United States shall have engaged in insurrection or rebellion against the same or given aid or comfort to the enemies thereof. But Congress may by a vote of two-thirds of each House remove such disability.”

 

      This provision was enacted under the Constitution in the wake of the Civil War to keep people out of office who had previously held federal office, taken constitutional oaths, and then engaged in insurrection or rebellion against the United States or the Constitution. The question is what it means for us today, and I think there are two important topics: one about procedure, one about substance. So let me offer a few words about each.

 

      First, on procedure. How does this work? What needs to happen for this provision to work? The provision is a self-executing qualification for office. “No person shall be” parallels the language for qualifications for office the Constitution already contains that say no person shall be a senator or representative who doesn’t meet various requirements of age, residency, and citizenship, that no person shall be eligible to the office of president if they’re not a natural born citizen, and so on. “No person shall” is the language the Constitution uses to say, “These are the rules for holding office.” The Constitution itself does not allow you to assume office unless you meet the criteria.

 

      Section Three adds to these qualifications one new and important qualification, namely that you can’t have engaged in an insurrection after swearing to support the Constitution. We know that it works this way, for sure, by comparing it with other parts of the reconstruction amendments. For instance, the Thirteenth Amendment—which bans -- which says slavery and involuntary servitude shall not exist—was an immediately self-executing legal rule. When it was enacted, slaves were immediately entitled to their freedom. Other parts of the Fourteenth Amendment—no state shall deny due process, equal protection, and so on—immediately gave people new legal rights against the states.

 

      Section Three works the same way, and we know this for extra sure because Section Three, after the long clause about no person shall, has a clause that refers to Congress and says, “Congress can lift this restriction by a two-thirds vote.” So the one time that Congress needs to act to activate this -- to act under this provision, is to deactivate the provision, not to activate it. That is, immediately upon insurrection or rebellion, anybody who’s covered by this clause cannot hold office. And if Congress wants to change that, they can do so, but they are the ones who have to act.

 

      There is a case by Chief Justice Chase—not a Supreme Court case but a case of no real precedential value now—called Griffin’s Case, that says otherwise and is wrong.

 

[Laughter]

 

Prof. William Baude:  And we’re happy to talk about it more, but I think it’s wrong, and this is pretty straightforward.

 

      The harder question is -- so to say the clause is self-executing doesn’t mean that it’s self-enforcing. The Fourteenth Amendment is not itself walking around the ballroom or the halls of any state secretary of state scrubbing people off the ballot or stopping them from getting into office. So how does this actually work? And the answer, again, is that it works like other provisions of constitutional qualifications.

 

      So there are a whole lot of steps at the holding and seeking of various offices where you have to ask, “Can the person hold this office?” For instance, the Constitution says that on inauguration day, if the president elect shall have failed to qualify, the vice president shall act as president, not the president. So we know explicitly that somebody who’s disqualified cannot take the office of president. Before that, there’s a step of counting the electoral votes, there’s a step of selecting electors during the presidential election, putting people on the ballot, putting people on the primary ballot, and so on. And at any step where the law chooses to ask whether the candidate’s qualified, this is one of the qualifications they have to enforce.

 

      That means, in many states, at either the primary stage or the general election stage, the state will ask, “Is this person qualified to hold office eventually?” States don’t have to do that. Technically, a state could choose to put somebody unqualified on the primary ballot or even to put somebody unqualified on the general ballot. They run a risk in doing so, of course, that the people’s votes from that state will be thrown out or wasted if the candidate turns out not to be qualified. So there are procedures in various states to test qualifications.

 

      The Minnesota Supreme Court issued a decision just this week, saying that when it comes to the primary, Minnesota law allows unqualified candidates to be on the ballot because it’s really just the party’s decision who they want to put up for the general election but that it may well be different when it comes to the general election. And when that happens and the suit is ripe, the Minnesota Supreme Court may well hear that case in its original jurisdiction. There are cases pending now in Colorado District Court, in the Michigan Court of Claims—which apparently has the authority over ballot access questions—in different procedures around the country.

     

      But at each of these steps, the states can choose to ask, “Is the person seeking office entitled to hold office?” It’s a little funny because technically you vote for presidential electors, not for a presidential candidate, but for many, many years, states have chosen -- have recognized that you’re really voting for president. They put the president’s name on the ballot, and we litigate who the electors shall be in the name of the president they’re seeking to elect.

 

      That’s procedure. These procedures are happening now, and they are the forum to ask the question: who is covered by this clause? What is an insurrection? And could we get the last slide? Is that possible? Great.

 

      So in a very long article, written with my co-author Michael Stokes Paulsen, we detail contemporary dictionaries, speeches by President Lincoln, statutes enacted by the Civil War Congress, case law from the Supreme Court—such as the Prize cases—historical precedence leading up to the enactment of the Fourteenth Amendment, especially the use of the Insurrection Act against a series of insurrections throughout American history, ranging from the Whiskey Insurrection to the slave rebellions, and we conclude that an insurrection is best defined as concerted forcible resistance to the authority of government to execute the laws in at least some significant respect—so group resistance by force to the authority of government to execute the laws. 

 

      A rebellion goes further than that. A rebellion is, of course, an effort to overturn or displace the lawful government through unlawful means. An insurrection is not necessarily an attempt to take over the government. So the Whiskey Insurrection—what we now call the Whiskey Rebellion, but what they called, actually, the Whiskey Insurrection—was a paradigm case of insurrection where a group of farmers who didn’t want to pay a federal tax tried to forcibly resist the government’s authority to collect the tax. They weren’t trying to take over the government. They weren’t even trying to take over Pennsylvania. They just didn’t want to pay the tax, and they thought the government didn’t have the authority to tax them. That was one of the classic examples of an insurrection invoked when Section Three was written. That’s the kind of thing Section Three applies to today. It’s the kind of thing Section Three applies to today.

 

      Now the question of the hour. Were the events of January 6 an insurrection? Were they a concerted forcible resistance to the authority of government to execute the laws in at least some significant respect? I think the answer is, yes. There was force. There was a concerted group that entered the Capitol by force, in part, to resist the authority of Congress to count the electoral votes in the way that Congress thought that they should count them. It, in fact, parallels quite closely some of the earlier insurrections in our history, like the Whiskey insurrection and others: Fries’s Rebellion and more. I think it’s hard to see January 6 as anything other than an insurrection.

 

      The harder question is who engaged in that insurrection? And, in particular, did former president Donald Trump engage in the January 6 insurrection that was covered by the Constitution? I think the best answer is he did. It’s not for me, ultimately, to adjudicate this. This, again, is a question that should come up in the Michigan Court of Claims and in the secretary of states’ offices around the country, perhaps later in the halls of Congress. 

 

      But I think the best understanding of the events of the day, so far, is that Donald Trump did engage in the insurrection of January 6 by doing two things: One, by calling the crowd together and inciting them to march on Congress. There’s a famous speech he gave at the ellipse. The speech is somewhat ambiguous. There are times in the speech he tells them that they should go peacefully, which might be telling them to go but not to engage in insurrection. There are parts of the speech that seem to cut the other way. By itself, maybe that would be a little bit ambiguous, whether that’s direct engagement in the insurrection that followed. 

 

      When you combine that with the president’s actions after the insurrection had begun, his failure to take steps to ensure that the laws were faithfully executed for a long period of time, his failure to call out the National Guard and other authorities, his failure, basically, to exercise his constitutional office and that that casts his speech at the ellipse in a different light and also is itself a form of engaging in the insurrection.

 

      So if you take the before and the after together and you look at the insurrection as a whole, I think the best answer is that Donald Trump engaged in that insurrection, and I think that’s what the Constitution tells us, that he cannot hold the office of president in the future. Thanks.

 

Prof. Julia Mahoney:  Thank you. Thank you very much. Professor McConnell, what do you have to say in response to correct your errant former clerk?

 

Prof. Michael McConnell:  [Laughter] Well, thanks very much. Appreciate seeing such a large audience here. I’d like to just begin by suggesting a principle of construction. That is, Will and my also very close, long-standing friend Michael Paulsen wrote this article about the sweeping reach of Section Three. And in it, they call—I guess, my favorite set of adjectives -- they referred to the—and adverbs too—incredibly broad sweep of conduct that is caught up in Section Three. And I would just urge whatever we may think about any of the specific issues, it should not be given an incredibly broad sweep. 

 

      What we are talking about here is giving a large number of officials all over the country, many of them elected—like state secretaries of state—many of them highly partisan -- giving them the authority to disqualify from the ballot their political opponents. Section Three is, of course, there. It must be given its proper application, but let’s not take it any farther than its terms and its history actually require. So that is the, sort of, interpretive mode with which I look at all of these questions. 

 

      There are any number of very interesting issues about the meaning of Section Three. There’s several I’m not going to spend much time on, but I want to flag them because there’s a lot of scholarship about it. The first question I’m not going to spend much time on is does it apply to the presidency at all? And I assume Josh Blackman is out there somewhere. Hi. Hi Josh. So Josh and Seth Barrett Tillman have written a one hundred and -- I think it is thirty, or was it 280 -- it felt like 520 -- 

 

[Laughter]

 

      -- page article, arguing at length that Section Three doesn’t apply to the presidency. They’ve been joined by people like Kurt Lash, Attorney General Mukasey. Steven Calabresi, upon reading this article, was persuaded. And if afterwards you’d like to hear the details, there are actually different, quite substantial arguments about why it doesn’t apply to the presidency. I’m not going to spend much time on that because—especially from my perspective as a former judge—I think it is exceedingly unlikely that any court or authoritative institution will decide a case on this ground. And the reason is it just seems so counterintuitive. 

 

      Why don’t we get the words of Section Three back up here? You read the words that refers to “any office, civil or military, under the United States,” and to say that the presidency is not an office under the United States will just strike most Americans as being really silly. And I believe that any court that is going to be deciding a Section Three case—and I do hope that we’ll get back the language up there. Who’s handling -- there. Thank you. 

 

      I think a court looking at this is going to have to look at it very seriously and soberly, and they’re not just going to be looking at text and history, but they are going to be making arguments that will resonate and make sense with the American public because if they don’t, there will be hell to pay and, I think, on either side of the matter. And I think the argument about the presidency is—although, I actually -- we, who are textualists, should care. And I think, actually, Will’s paper needs to deal with these arguments more seriously than it does. But in the real world, that isn’t going to fly.

 

      Another very interesting question that Will spends a great deal of time on is whether there’s a requirement for enforcement legislation. And as Will points out, the -- Chief Justice Salmon Chase, in 1869—that is the year after the Fourteenth Amendment was ratified—in a written opinion—not for the Supreme Court but in his circuit court duties—held that there must be enforcement legislation in order to carry a Section Three into effect. Now, Will has a number of arguments why he doesn’t find that decision persuasive, but the decision actually does exist. We call these things precedence. 

 

[Laughter]

 

      And Chief Justice Chase -- let me -- something about him. He was one of the leading constitutional abolitionists prior to being named to the Chief Justice by Abraham Lincoln. He knew the people who wrote the Fourteenth Amendment. He was there for the whole thing, and when he tells us that the -- about the meaning in 1869, he may have a little bit more insight into what it meant than those of us here on this stage. And Chief Justice Chase was not alone. 

 

      Thaddeus Stevens—congressman from Pennsylvania—who introduced the Fourteenth Amendment on the floor of the House of Representatives, said the same thing. He said that it requires enforcement legislation, and he went on to say that in the next -- when the Fourteenth Amendment becomes law—and he’s specifically talking here about Section Three—Congress will pass enforcing legislation in our next session. So Thaddeus Stevens certainly counts -- we call him, I think, one of the originals—for those of us who are originalists. 

 

      And Lyman Trumbull, the Chair of the Judiciary Committee at the time, said exactly the same thing. So he says -- so Trumbull says, “Some statute is plainly, plainly necessary to enforce this constitutional provision.” And he wasn’t just talking through his hat. He then proposes enforcement legislation pursuant to Section Five of the Fourteenth Amendment to enforce Section Three. It passed. It was proposed in 1869. It was passed in 1870 in a bill with the official name of “An Act to Enforce the Fourteenth Amendment.” 

 

      Section Fourteen, which is now codified in 5 U.S.C. §14a, is Congress’s mechanism for enforcing Section Three of the Fourteenth Amendment. It provides -- let me read it. It’s pretty short. “Whenever any person holds office, except as a member of Congress or some state legislature, contrary to the provision of the Third Section of the Fourteenth article of Amendment of the Constitution, the district attorney for the district in which such person holds office shall proceed against him by writ of quo warranto”—footnote: quo warranto is an ancient common law writ used to challenge whether a person is entitled to hold a public office -- so he proceeds, “by quo warranto, returnable to the District Court of the United States in such district and prosecute the same to the removal of such person from office.”

 

      So Congress is not left -- did not leave us in doubt about how Section Three should be enforced. They passed a statute. This is the way it is supposed to be enforced. The idea that miscellaneous, partisan state officials are in charge of deciding who can become president of the United States has some real structural federalism problems to it that Congress anticipated and legislated against. So I’m kind of waiting for the quo warranto, but I’m going to wait a long time because quo warranto doesn’t apply and this statute doesn’t apply until a person seeks to hold office. 

 

      It doesn’t take place during the election time, and that’s because—and I really wish we would just keep the language up here. Please, let’s just keep it because I want to point -- I want to gesture at it because the text -- so note what it says. It says, “No person shall hold any office.” It does not say, “No person shall run for any office.” It doesn’t say, “No person shall be elected to any office.” An earlier version did say that. 

 

      This is what we’ve got. It only applies to people holding office. So when the Minnesota Supreme Court two days ago said, “There’s nothing in state law that permits us to knock people off the ballot when they’re not qualified,” they were right, as a matter of state law. And there’s nothing in Section Three that tells anybody anywhere that they have authority to keep somebody from running for office. Wait until Donald Trump is elected and then we can think about this. 

 

      And so, now, I wasn’t very interested in application to the presidency because I think no court is really going to go there. But this is pay dirt. Right? Think about the U.S. Supreme Court. They do not want to decide this case. That is, they do not want to decide whether Donald Trump engaged in an insurrection. What will they be happy to say? They’ll be happy to say, “It’s not ripe because until he’s elected, there’s no -- this constitutional provision doesn’t apply.” I can really imagine Chief Justice Roberts writing a four paragraph opinion to that effect, and I predict he will. And also, I can imagine him saying, “Well, we don’t know. Does it require enforcement legislation or not?” Well, Will Baude makes some pretty persuasive arguments, but there are pretty good arguments the other way too.  

 

      But what we do have is precedent from the Chief Justice in 1869, saying, “We require enforcement legislation.” We have the sponsor of the Fourteenth Amendment in the House of Representatives saying, “We require enforcement legislation.” We have the Senate Judiciary Committee Chair, at the time, saying, “We need enforcement legislation.” And we have Congress in 1870, passing enforcement legislation. Let’s follow the enforcement legislation and not all these, sort of, made up contrivances to bring the case before us prematurely. I can so easily see them saying that because it answers the case without deciding this explosive political question of whether Donald Trump engaged in an insurrection, a question on which 45 percent of the people will be absolutely infuriated whichever way they go. The Court isn’t -- I think the Court is very unlikely to go there.

 

      So now let’s get to -- the first point is the amendment only applies after someone’s already trying to hold an office. It doesn’t apply to elections at all. So let’s talk about what is an insurrection and then talk about what it means to engage in an insurrection. So could we have the next slide up here? So what is an insurrection? Both insurrection and rebellion are quite demanding terms. These are not -- these are not -- it’s not a low bar; it’s a high bar. 

 

      What we know is that the Civil War was an insurrection or a rebellion—probably both because that’s what the whole thing was about. And we know that it was things like -- so members of Congress, at the time, adopting this, describe the reach and the future as being for actions which are essentially the same -- of the same level as the Civil War. So that’s what we’re looking at. To say that January 6 was like the U.S. Civil War is, I think, a pretty tough pill to swallow. 

 

      But note also how broad that definition is. That would apply to every riot we have seen. Think about Seattle. It was a concerted, forcible resistance. They occupied a whole square mile, they prevented the enforcement of the law in part of the city, and riots are unfortunately a common event in American history. According to Will, every time a politician says something to encourage and support these -- a riot, they are going to be subject to being disqualified from running again, again, by their political opponents who happen to be holding office. 

 

      And then did Donald Trump engage? Well, let’s look at the slide before -- and I’m sorry. Give me 30 seconds more.

 

Prof. Julia Mahoney:  Thirty seconds.

 

Prof. Michael McConnell:  And then I’ll yield more time to Will. But note at the text, it applies to two different things. It applies to engaging in the rebellion or the insurrection or giving aid and comfort to the enemies of the United States. Aid and comfort to enemies of the United States comes from the Treason Clause. Enemies of the United States means people who are making war on the United States. That’s what it means. And so, when there’s an actual war, giving aid and comfort counts. 

 

      If it’s only an insurrection, you actually have to have engaged in it. I do not think making a speech, asking your supporters to march to the Congress with no advocacy of violence, constitutes that. And I do not think doing nothing -- reprehensible though President Trump’s behavior may have been that afternoon, wandering around the White House not doing anything is not engaging in an insurrection.

 

Prof. Julia Mahoney:  All right. Thank you very much. First question. This is an attempt - - two great presentations. First question: I am trying very hard to look at what separates these two. As I say, you agree on a lot. And one of the things where I think there is the greatest chasm is to what extent and in what ways courts should take into account prudential considerations. 

 

      Professor Baude, you suggest that Salmon Chase is, well, off the reservation, and I can’t quite figure out how much he can engage in just thinking about some prudential considerations. I understand your criticism to be that he’s putting enormous weight on practical consequences and neglecting other modalities of constitutional interpretation. And I think you make a number of fair points.

 

      Professor McConnell, you suggest perhaps that judges should be extremely attentive to the consequences, practically speaking, of what their actions are. And I would like to hear more from each of you about precisely what is legitimate for judges to take into account when making prudential calls. So first, Professor Baude.

 

Prof. William Baude:  Okay. Sure. I don’t think it’s illegitimate to consider the consequences in interpretation. Even James Madison—the original original—said that where provision is ambiguous, it can be tried by its consequences, but where it’s clear, you should enforce it. So I think one key step is not to overuse prudential arguments when the text is clear but we don’t like it. Maybe the more ambiguous it is, the more it’s okay. But I think the more important thing is not to confuse our view of what is good with what the amendment is trying to achieve. So the reason we care about the consequences is because the people who enacted the Constitution were trying to do things in the world, and we don’t want to read the Constitution in a sort of robotic or artificial fashion. 

 

      But to take the constitutional provision we don’t like and try to sort of whittle it down to size—not a coincidence, by the way, that Chief Justice Chase opposed Section Three of the Fourteenth Amendment; thought it was a bad constitutional provision—to use your own disagreement with the provision as a way to narrow it, I think, is a big mistake. And Section Three was trying to accomplish something big and important and something dangerous, but it was trying to accomplish something.

 

Prof. Julia Mahoney:  Thank you. Professor McConnell.

 

Prof. Michael McConnell:  I pretty much agree with that, but what was Chase doing? I don’t think he was just saying bad consequences. I think he was saying what the drafters of Section Three must have meant because they didn’t intend to throw this country into abysses of conflict over narrow cases, and we know that from people during the debates over Section Three. So here’s a quote. “This house by a very decided expression of opinion determined that it would strictly construe the rule that is in the Section Three.” 

 

      And there were four cases in the two years, during which Section Three was in -- it was in operation before Congress lifted -- and there were four cases of people elected to Congress whose entitlement to serve was challenged on grounds of Section Three. One of them was excluded. He had led troops to battle for the Confederacy. Three others were not excluded. That is to say Congress -- the House of Representatives voted that they had not violated Section Three. All of them had supported secession by voting for it and speaking for it in their states, but they had not themselves taken up arms, and that seems to have been the distinction for them.

 

      So I don’t grasp at just any old prudential considerations. I want to know what were -- what were the -- how did the people at the time envision this to work as a practical matter?

 

Prof. Julia Mahoney:  Thank you.

 

Prof. William Baude:  I just wanted to correct the record, I think, on one thing, which is that when Thaddeus Stevens and the framers of the Fourteenth Amendment were talking about enforcement legislation, a lot of the time they were actually talking about a different draft of Section Three. So Section Three starts out in the House as a bill to strip complete voting rights from all members of the Confederacy, regardless of office holding, and that’s the provision Thaddeus Stevens says is going to need enforcement legislation because he’s envisioning voting rights legislation. And then when Congress does pass legislation, it’s only after Griffin’s Case—after Chief Justice Chase has stopped the amendment from being enforced. Until then, there were state lawsuits in North Carolina and other places, enforcing Section Three. So I’m not sure we should give Chase credit for defining the actual original meaning of Section Three, but if he was, then he’d be entitled to more respect.

 

Prof. Julia Mahoney:  Thank you. Next question. I’d like to focus on the final sentence of Section Three—if we can get the language up—and the one that says, “But Congress may, by a vote of two-thirds of each House, remove such disability.” And in determining their duties under Section Three, how should state and federal election officials and other constitutional actors take into account the possibility that Congress will act to remove a disability?

 

      Professor McConnell emphasized—I think correctly—that the first sentence of Section Three says, “hold any office,” not run for, not be elected to, not be appointed to, but hold any office. So clearly, anyone thinking about removing someone from a ballot, and so on and so forth, might, at least, think about taking into account the fact that when the time comes for an office to be held, Congress might have acted to remove that disability. So this is very much unlike other potential disabilities. It’s not like not being 35. It’s not like not being natural born. So how does the prudent, faithful, constitutional actor deal with this second sentence?

 

Prof. William Baude:  Well, it’s always possible that any constitutional disability could be lifted by constitutional amendment, which also requires two-thirds of Congress but then the states. But I think this is maybe a case for -- there’s a formalist argument and a prudential argument. So a very formalist argument would say, “Until January 20, 2025, we have no idea if the president is disqualified because at any moment, Congress could grant amnesty, therefore, full steam ahead, and we’ll just wait until 11:58 on inauguration day to figure out whether the president’s entitled to hold office.” That is a reason a state might choose to put a disqualified president on the ballot because you never know. They might become qualified later.

 

      On the other hand, that, it seems to me, is courting chaos and civil war. It seems to me, whatever the scope of this provision, better to figure it out sooner rather than later. Better to figure out when it’s not too late for tens of millions of people to take that into account in making their votes. Better to figure out what insurrection means now rather than until we wait for the next insurrection in Seattle or Washington or anywhere else. So I’m not convinced you have to wait until the last minute and trigger a constitutional civil war.

 

Prof. Julia Mahoney:  Yes. But it’s not a fanciful idea because, of course, Congress has acted before to remove disabilities. Professor McConnell.

 

Prof. Michael McConnell:  My answer is not at all. So Congress might lift the disability, but until it does it, it’s there. Give it full speed. I don’t believe that’s sweeping and broad, but the fact that Congress might lift it, I think, is completely irrelevant to what we say today. I would point out—just to pull Will’s leg a little big—that he just made a prudential argument for reading the amendment to say something other than what it does. It says, “hold.” 

 

      If I were writing such an amendment, I think I would agree with Will. It really is not a good thing to wait until somebody’s already been elected. It is not a nice prospect, but the word is there, it’s completely unambiguous, and the fact that Will and I might write the amendment a different way surely doesn’t mean that it means something other than what it obviously says.

 

Prof. Julia Mahoney:  Thank you. My final question, before I turn this over to the audience, concerns the meaning of officer. Professor McConnell, you spoke some about the presidency as an office, but there is—thinking about arguments that are already gaining traction, at least judging from my reading on the internet—this idea that President Trump as an officer of the United States is a very, very important one. And there is plenty of argument—or, at least, one can, at least, get over the plausibility hurdle, and I think many have—that the president is not an officer, that, in effect, officers refer to appointments, appointed officials, not elected ones. We can, of course, look at parts of Article II Section Three, which speak of the president commissioning officers, all that. You know all that. In many, many provisions one could certainly begin to make an argument that President Trump was not an officer. What is your response?

 

Prof. Michael McConnell:  Well, I think as a very strictly textual matter that that’s probably right. There is a lot of evidence that officer always means appointed officer. Note that the other people listed, members of Congress, state legislatures, electors, all are elected officers so -- and then it says, “and officers.” And there’s extremely sparse reference to the presidency during the entire course of the Section Three debates. There is one exchange where Reverdy Johnson says he thought it did not apply to the president. Someone else makes the argument to him the other way and he folds. I think that’s a really good argument that maybe it does apply to the president.

 

      But there’s one further textual point which has to do -- if we could have -- I wish we could just keep the language -- nobody needs to see my face. 

 

[Laughter]

 

Prof. Michael McConnell:  So note that it says, “Anyone who, having previously taken an oath to support the Constitution of the United States,” -- I’m going to make the pickiest legal argument you have ever heard in your life. There are two oaths. There is an Article VI oath, which, by the way, is 5 U.S.C. § 16, right after -- it’s literally right upon the two provisions of enforcement that I was talking about. It prescribes the oath for everybody other than the president, and they have an -- they swear an oath to defend and support the Constitution. 

 

      The president’s oath is specified in Article II. He promises to protect and defend the Constitution. He does not promise to support the Constitution. I told you it was a picky argument. 

 

[Laughter] 

 

Prof. Michael McConnell:  But if you’re trying to exclude the president, you might well frame Section Three this way. It’s an oath to support the Constitution. The president does not make such an oath.

 

Prof. Julia Mahoney:  All right. With that, we have questions from our audience. So again, please keep questions short.

 

Josh Blackman:  Yes. Will, the same question as Michael. Will, same question Julia asked Michael. 

 

Prof. William Baude:  Sorry. I -- 

 

Josh Blackman:  Same question Michael answered. Maybe you can answer that question.

 

Prof. Julia Mahoney:  Oh, I’m sorry. 

 

[CROSSTALK]

 

Prof. Michael McConnell:  This, by the way, if you don’t know him, is Josh Blackman, the only person on the planet who’s written a longer article about Section Three than Will has.

 

[Laughter]

 

Prof. William Baude:  This is the president question? Is that the --

 

Prof. Julia Mahoney:  Yes. Sorry.

 

Prof. William Baude:  Okay. Sorry. Yeah. I do think - -

 

Prof. Julia Mahoney:  I neglected you.

 

Prof. William Baude:  I do think that the president’s oath to preserve and protect the Constitution is an oath to support the Constitution. I think it’s a more detailed oath to support the Constitution, and I think Section Three just parallels the Oath Clause. So everybody who takes an oath that’s covered by the Constitution is covered by Section Three. I think the president’s oath is covered by the Constitution. Article II itself refers to the presidency as an office. 

 

      I actually think there’s no real dispute. The president is an officer who holds an office. The best argument to the contrary is that it’s not an office of the United States or under the United States. It’s an argument from prepositions, which I think is maybe even pickier than Michael’s argument, and it’s the argument that was discussed and refuted when Section Three was drafted. So I don’t know why we think we know better than them.

 

Josh Blackman:  All right.

 

Prof. Julia Mahoney:  Thank you.

 

Josh Blackman:  So my question is actually about this panel in general. You agree a lot on a lot of things, and I think it was a mistake to have someone up there who perhaps disagrees with you. So my question is debate. I challenge both of you to debate. Stanford, Chicago, will you debate me? That’s the question.

 

[Laughter]

 

Prof. William Baude:  I’ll see you in San Diego, Josh.

 

Josh Blackman:  I’ll take that as a no.

 

Prof.  Michael McConnell:  If we can do it in the hometown of your co-author, so I’d like a trip to Ireland.

 

Josh Blackman:  Dublin’s lovely this time of year.

 

Prof. Julia Mahoney:  All right. Next.

 

Michael Rosman:  Michael Rosman with the Center for Individual Rights. I have two quick questions for Will. I believe I have taken oaths to defend or protect or support the Constitution every time I became a member of a bar, and I’m told that I’m an officer of the court. Does that make me a judicial officer of a state? And the second question is let’s say -- I’m not, but let’s say I’m a former DA, left, going into private practice, and now I was asked to defend one of the insurrectionists from January 6, and I give them a little break on the fee because that person is poor. Have I given aid or comfort to the enemies of the Constitution?

 

[Laughter]

 

Prof. Will Baude:  I think the answer to both questions is no. I do think when we call lawyers officers of the court, I think that’s a little bit self-serving. I don’t think we’re -- the real officers of the court are people --  

 

Michael Rosman:  I don’t say it. They tell me that.

 

[Laughter]

 

Prof. William Baude:  It’s very nice of them. [Laughter] We haven’t argued here about whether, technically, aid or comfort extends to all people who commit insurrection or rebellion, whether that’s the definition of enemies or whether enemies itself has a narrower compass. I think either way, doing something like providing constitutionally required legal representation would not qualify as aid or comfort. And I actually agree with Michael that we should be careful not to read aid or comfort too broadly. I think we should read it the way it was when it was enacted.

 

Prof. Michael McConnell:  I do not believe performing your legal function is engaging in an insurrection. And aid and comfort does not apply unless you’re aiding enemies of the United States who are people who are making war against the United States. Now if we’re talking about a Guantanamo situation, we might have more of a problem.

 

Prof. Julia Mahoney:  Next.

 

[CROSSTALK] 

 

Questioner 3:  I was curious as to the textual interpretation of the word ‘hold’ in Professor McConnell’s interpretation of that, whether that textual interpretation supersedes the nature of a quo warranto action as a civil action and the concurrent provisions, so to speak, in Article III of pre-enforcement actions. So if the injuries—for lack of a better term—is that person hold -- the second that person holds office, why wouldn’t Article III pre-enforcement principles apply to a quo warranto action?

 

Prof. William Baude:  I take it a version of the argument is, it’s true, the Constitution says you can’t hold office—that’s its only bar—but it doesn’t tell us when we can adjudicate the holding question in advance. The Constitution says you can’t be killed without due process, but it doesn’t mean you have to wait until you’re dead before you sue and try to get a ‘writ quo resurrectio’ to come back to life. 

 

[Laughter]

 

Prof. William Baude:  Right? We can say this is about to happen, it would be unconstitutional if it were to happen, and we want to stop it. And that’s, I think, the right way to do it, rather than to try to misread the word ‘hold’. I will say I think the quo warranto provision is no longer in the U.S. Code. I think it disappeared in 1948 in the positive law codification. So I don’t think it’s there anymore.

 

Prof. Michael McConnell:  Actually, it’s -- I’ve spent some time trying to figure this -- I don’t know the answer to that. I can’t find the repeal. You say in your article that it was repealed. I can’t find it.

 

Prof. William Baude:  So in 1948, Congress took the entire judicial code and repassed it and then said, “Anything that we left out is hereby excluded by implication.” So I believe that was where they repealed it.

 

Prof. Michael McConnell:  And the Library of Congress issued a list of provisions that it said are permanent provisions and still exist, even though they weren’t recodified. I don’t know what the legal standing is of that. And it is right there in U.S. Code. Look it up.

 

Prof. Julia Mahoney:  Next question.

 

Dan McLoughlin:  Hi. Dan McLoughlin from National Review. I would say that I’ve written at length on this issue but not at law professor length. My question for Professor Baude though -- it seems to me that if you do look at those cases from the 1860s, where Congress and the Supreme Court of North Carolina did or didn’t exclude people from office, there is a pretty clear standard there that it’s -- pre-insurrection incitement is not enough, that there has to be something active. 

 

       I guess my concern, having listened to you today and having read your article, is that it seems to me that you’re arguments for saying that Trump engaged in insurrection are interesting, they’re creative, but I don’t see the originalist basis for any of them in anything that happened or was considered at the time, including Lincoln describing secession itself as, essentially, a form of insurrection. It seems to me that if inaction -- in that face, maybe James Buchanan should also have been ineligible to ever serve again. But I don’t -- that seems to me a big leap, and I’m just wondering what originalist basis there is, really, for any of this extension of the written principles of the amendment.

 

Prof. Julia Mahoney:  Professor Baude.

 

Prof. William Baude:  So it might be the best evidence comes in Hinds’ Precedents, which is where they summarize the exclusion debates, both of the -- after Section Three is passed, the folks that Professor McConnell had just mentioned, but also a series of debates of whether to exclude people under the Ironclad Oath, which they see as largely paralleling Section Three. And that includes some cases of exclusion for speech. 

 

       Now it’s true it’s speech while the war is ongoing, so it’s distinguishable, but I’m not sure that it’s entirely distinguishable. And it includes exclusions of somebody named Philip Thomas who was excluded largely for his inactions, for his failure to stop his son from enlisting with the Confederacy, and for his decision to resign his position in Buchanan’s cabinet. I think those are the best evidence we have. I admit there are gaps between that and the questions we face today.

 

       In an ideal world, we’d also be able to get more evidence. So it could well be that there’s some more benign explanation for President Trump’s behavior than the explanations we’ve so far got in the public record. It could well be that he could testify in a proceeding and explain why he did the things he did. It could well be his testimony would lead us to conclude something else, and I’d be happy to hear more about that. 

 

Prof. Julia Mahoney:  Thank you.

 

Prof. Michael McConnell:  So the problem with that is that the Ironclad Oath went beyond the terms of Section Three, and so it disqualified people -- for example, anyone who held office in the Confederacy would flunk -- at any time, would flunk the Ironclad Oath. And that is plainly inconsistent with the way Section Three was interpreted. So I think to say—as Will just did—that they equated the two, Section Three and the Ironclad Oath, is just not -- I just think that that is a leap that we can’t make. The two are quite different. 

 

       And, by the way, it’s true, we don’t yet know. There could be new evidence about January 6. But it could go the other way too: maybe more benign explanations. I doubt it. But more malign explanations: we could find out that Donald Trump really did call the Proud Boys and tell them to bring arms and do other things. I mean, he might have. And it is true also that a number of the January 6 defendants, as a defense to the action, claimed that they believed that they were there in obedience to a call from the Commander in Chief. So they may not have -- Trump may not have actually issued such a call, but they may have heard it.

 

Prof. Julia Mahoney:  So thank you. Next question.

 

Questioner 5:  I have a question, but I wanted to defer to the folks at a mic in the back of the room as well.

 

Questioner 6:  Hi. I wanted to ask, do we have any concern about allowing anybody, state officials in a conclusory fashion to determine facts as to very serious crimes? So whichever way the legal definition of insurrection or rebellion goes, it’s quite a different determination to make, such as somebody’s residence, their age, and even those things, I think -- if, for example, somebody was disputing their place of residence, they would be able to go and say, “Well, actually, I did live here for the right number of years, and I am a citizen, and I should be able to be on the ballot and qualify.” So is there a specific issue in this being a different kind of qualification because it surrounds a very serious crime without any legal process having occurred necessarily to just have one official say, “Well, we think what you did is an insurrection. You were never charged, you were never convicted, and so we’re keeping you off.”

 

Prof. Julia Mahoney:  Professor Baude.

 

Prof. William Baude:  Let’s just say there’s tons of legal process. Right? The courts are full of legal process with Section Three now, where they’re hearing and adjudicating these claims. There’s a multi-day trial in Colorado. I take the point that figuring out whether somebody engaged in insurrection feels more weighty than figuring out whether they’re lying about living in Maryland. But both of them are constitutional qualifications, so there’s got to be some place to figure it out. And if the states want to take on that role, I think that’s a legitimate thing to do.

 

Prof. Julia Mahoney:  Professor McConnell.

 

Prof. Michael McConnell:  I think it’s a serious problem, and if it’s in court, there can be a taking of evidence and so forth. But what if the state secretary of state simply throws them -- the person off the ballot without any due process at all or maybe with some sort of executive fact finding? Will, in his paper, says that when there’s judicial review of such a decision, that the court should defer to any -- to the secretary of state if it’s within the range of reasonableness. So I think we are actually facing the very problem you describe. Note that when Lyman Trumbull and the Congress passed enforcement legislation, they had the district attorneys go to court and prove the quo warranto proceeding, which will entail all the due process that you would expect and want.

 

Prof. Julia Mahoney:  Thank you. Next question.

 

Trevor Risell (sp):  My name is Trevor Risell. Thank you both for your comments. My question is for Professor Baude. If President Trump can be deemed to have engaged in insurrection by omission—failing to take steps to address what happened at the Capitol—can President Biden be deemed to have engaged in insurrection for failing to address what’s happening on the southern border—concerted group of people acting in open defiance of law, often armed and acting violently?

 

Prof. William Baude:  I don’t think so, but I don’t think that what’s happening at the southern border rises to the level of an insurrection, and I don’t think that the best reading of the facts is that President Biden is engaging in that insurrection. I will say I have received a lot of emails with variations of that question -- 

 

[Laughter]

 

Prof. William Baude:  -- some suggesting that President Biden is, in fact, complicit in smuggling Chinese soldiers through the border as part of an attempt at an inside job to wage Chinese war against the United States. I think if that is true, that would be very serious, and he should not be president.

 

[Laughter]

 

Prof. Julia Mahoney:  Professor McConnell.

 

Prof. Michael McConnell:  I think those folks are sneaking across the border illegally to take advantage of the liberty and prosperity of this great Republic, rather than committing insurrection to try to tear it down. 

 

Prof. Julia Mahoney:  Next question.

 

Jeff Bishop:  Jeff Bishop. A couple of questions, mostly to some points that Professor McConnell had raised: one about the enforcement clause and one about the distinction of holding office versus running for it. As you know, the Fourteenth amendment is one of six or seven—depending on whether you count the repealed ones—amendments that have language that say Congress may enforce this through appropriate legislation or something to that effect. Is there any precedent, though, for saying that any other part of the Constitution, including other sections of the Fourteenth, don’t have effect because Congress didn’t act on this particular thing? For example, Obergefell: they ruled that straight-only marriage violated equal protection. Could they have or should they have ruled, “Oh, well, maybe it does or maybe it doesn’t, but Congress hasn’t acted to enforce this, and so we’re not going to hear the case at all?

 

Prof. Michael McConnell:  So I think the general rule at least until very modern times was that things in the Constitution could be invoked as a defense, but that they did not constitute a cause of action in which you can go to court and sue. That is true of the rest of the Fourteenth Amendment. Don’t forget that the Fourteenth Amendment is, in fact, enforced, for the most part, against states, state officers, under Section 1983. So you don’t just go into court and say -- Obergefell, for example, was a 1983 case, so it was not one brought without any congressional authority. 

 

       The tricky thing is as the Supreme Court has held that the Fourteenth Amendment also applies to the federal government—which they never expected, and it doesn’t, but they can -- the Supreme Court can say whatever they want—they then had to come make up an enforcement scheme through the Bivens doctrine. And, I mean, this is -- I assume everybody in civil procedure debates the illogic of that.

 

Prof. Julia Mahoney:  Professor Baude, anything to add?

 

Prof. William Baude:  I would just add that in these cases, people are using state law causes of action, so nobody’s claiming an implied federal cause of action of the Fourteenth Amendment. And I think there’s no dispute that the state can give you a cause of action to comply with the Fourteenth Amendment.

 

Prof. Julia Mahoney:  Yes.

 

Prof. Michael McConnell:  Well, except the people who are suing to try to compel the state secretaries of state to kick Trump off the ballot. They need a cause of action.

 

Prof. William Baude:  But they’re using state law causes of action.

 

Prof. Julia Mahoney:  Final question.

 

Craig Richardon (sp):  Craig Richardson from Colorado. Most of the qualifications for office in the Constitution are fairly objective: age, citizenship. This requires some subjective judgment, and we do have a mechanism for those subjective determinations: the Impeachment Clause. How does this provision -- how is it properly harmonized, textually and mechanically, with that provision of the Constitution?

 

Prof. William Baude:  There was an impeachment proceeding involving the insurrection on January 6 that members of the Senate concluded was jurisdictionally barred because the president had left office. That seems wrong, I think, to both of us—I think both of us had written about that. And had they decided otherwise and chosen that as the time to adjudicate this, that seems like that would’ve been a very healthy thing to do for the country. It’s a shame it didn’t happen.

 

Prof. Julia Mahoney:  Professor McConnell. Final word.

 

Prof. Michael McConnell:  So I’m not -- I didn’t quite catch all of that but - - so here’s the way I think it basically works. State officers are governed by state law. Congress and Senate are governed by Article I, which is why, by the way, Lyman Trumbull’s bill excludes them from quo warranto proceedings. Each House is the judge of the qualifications of its own members, so House and Senate are governed by that. Appointed officials, including judges, it’s enforced through the advice and consent proceedings of the Senate. And only the president are we bereft of any possible enforcement. 

 

       And it’s a serious problem because at the primary level -- no matter what the states say, the Republican Party convention can nominate whoever they want for president. They’re not governed by that. And then electors are running -- how are we going to say that people running as electors are to be excluded? They’re not insurrectionists. So I don’t see how that’s going to work. I think the only way it really is going to work is that Kamala Harris will be standing there with electoral votes coming in, and she’s going to have a legal opinion from the 24 version of John Eastman telling her that she’s entitled not to recognize electoral votes in favor of Donald Trump. And we’ve seen this movie before.

 

 

Prof. Julia Mahoney:  Thank you all. Thank you both for excellent and substantive comments. Thank you.

3:00 p.m. - 4:30 p.m.
FISA Section 702 Revisited: Originalist Interpretations and Constitutional Constraints

2023 National Lawyers Convention

Topics: International & National Security Law • Civil Rights • Fourth Amendment • Security & Privacy
East Room
The Mayflower Hotel
1127 Connecticut Avenue NW
Washington, DC 20006

Share

Event Video

Listen & Download

Description

Featuring:

  • Hon. Stewart Baker, Of Counsel, Steptoe & Johnson LLP
  • Hon. Beth A. Williams, Board Member, United States Privacy and Civil Liberties Oversight Board
  • Mr. Gene C. Schaerr, Partner, Schaerr Jaffe LLP
  • Prof. John Yoo, Emanuel Heller Professor of Law, University of California Berkeley School of Law
  • Moderator: Hon. Paul Matey, United States Court of Appeals, Third  Circuit

Speakers

Event Transcript

Matthew Heiman:  Good afternoon.  My name is Matthew Heiman. I chair The Federalist Society's International and National Security Law Practice Group. And on behalf of that practice group, we're delighted to present today's panel. I've been given some instructions, which I intend to follow.  So, a couple of housekeeping notes before we begin. If you are interested in obtaining CLE credit for this panel, you are to scan one of the QR codes that are on the back of the program or on the placards, and then you are to scan it again when you leave today. That will give you a fighting chance with your bar of getting CLE credit.

 

      The second thing I want to note is that the practice group does programming like this throughout the year. We, obviously, as the title of our practice group suggests, we're very much focused on international issues, whether it's international law, trade law, and national security issues such as FISA and law of war, and a number of other topics.  So, if you're interested in the work of the practice group, you're interested in getting involved in a substantive way, we'd welcome your engagement.  Please find me today. You can write a note to me or Jack Capizzi at The Federalist Society, and we'll get you plugged into the work that the practice group does.

 

      With that, it's my honor to introduce our moderator for today's panel, Judge Paul Matey.  Judge Matey was appointed to the United States Court of Appeals for the Third Circuit in 2019.  Prior to going onto the bench, Judge Matey was a partner at Lowenstein Sandler in New Jersey, where his practice focused on commercial litigation and criminal defense. Earlier in his career, he was a general counsel. He was a deputy chief counsel to Governor Chris Christy. And before that he was an assistant United States Attorney for the District of New Jersey. And, with that, I will hand it over to Judge Matey.

 

Hon. Paul Matey:  Thank you. Thanks for the kind introduction and the opportunity to join the conversation today. I'm thrilled to be with a panel that really is going to need no introduction. Our topic for the convention, as we know, is originalism on the ground. Originalism, like textualism, is perhaps understood through the classical legal lens of the concepts of delegation and deference. We ask often where the separated powers of the federal government have come to rest by asking where they began, whether they have been appropriately shared, and when we can accept the reassignment of a task from one branch to another.  That, of course, requires a ruler. And ours is well marked.

 

      On one side is history, that rich experience that influenced the founding era's understanding of our first law. And the other is text, words that, when read in the context of their ordinary public meaning when drafted, provide a predictable means of informing our duties and constraining our discretion. A benefit, surely, to the judges, but to the citizens, as well. These traditional tools, well, they are part of the qualities that have always been understood essential to any republic focused on the teleological goal of the blessings of liberty. 

 

Theory, of course, is shaped in the cool, calm, confines of the classroom. Applying it on the ground, now that’s a bit harder. And when that ground is the battlefield, whether physical or virtual, domestic or foreign, challenges are sure to abound. Recall it was Madison who said, "In war, the public treasures are to be unlocked, and it is the executive hand which is to dispense them. In war, the honors and emoluments of office are to be multiplied. In war, finally, the laurels that are to be gathered and the executive brow that they are to encircle.

 

All of these puzzles come to rest for us in the Foreign Intelligence Surveillance Act, particularly the enigmatic Section 702. FISA was reauthorized as recently as January of 2018 and — timely for our discussion today — will sunset at the end of the year, providing an opportunity for an exchange and opportunities for Congress to correct potential abuses, reconsider usefulness, and ask for necessary reforms. We are thrilled to have four experts in the field to lead us in that discussion. 

 

Let me introduce each of them very briefly right now. Their full biographies are, of course, available online. And we would be here all day if I actually tried to read them. So, instead, I will simply introduce Professor John Yoo, who is the Emanual S. Heller Professor of Law at the University of California at Berkeley; Beth Williams, who is a board member of the U.S. Privacy and Civil Liberties Oversight Board; Gene Schaerr, who is a partner at Schaerr Jaffe and general counsel of the Project for Privacy and Surveillance Accountability; and, of course, Stewart Baker, who is counsel at Steptoe and Johnson.

 

Each of our panelists will deliver opening remarks. We will then turn to what I know will be a lively exchange, leaving ample time for your questions at the end. With that, Professor, I turn it over to you.

 

Professor John Yoo:  Thank you, Judge. Not a bad job from someone from New Jersey. I'm from Philadelphia, so --

 

Hon. Paul Matey:  I was not advised of this before I accepted this. 

 

Professor John Yoo:  No one told me I was going to be on a panel with someone from Jersey, but --

 

Hon. Paul Matey:  We're going to make it work.  We're not happy, but we'll make it work.

 

Professor John Yoo:  So, it's wonderful to be here.  Thanks to The Federalist Society for inviting me. I come from the West Coast where, I'm happy to say, for once, Stanford is much more antisemitic than Berkeley right now. We've had these terrible protests all around the country. And, strangely, at Berkeley, we have had relative peace and quiet. And, although I disagree with him on many issues, I think our Dean, Erwin Chemerinsky, has done a good job protecting the right to free speech, but also making clear — and I agree with him on this — that the attacks in Israel were terrible. They were inhumane. And I don't think we should have a moral equivalency between what happened with the attacks in Israel, and then Israel's right to defend itself and how it carries it out. I just wanted to say that. 

 

      I also want to say, it's also my great pleasure to be here when we've welcomed to The Federalist Society our first Italian chapter. And so, I had the pleasure of introducing Eduardo Rafeota (sp) and Lorenzo Violini (sp) here. I hate to say this, Eduardo, but, as you can see, we have to go to Italy now to get Leonard Leo's body doubles. The original source, as it were. But they're soon, I'm sure, to be the most popular chapter in The Federalist Society as we all now move the annual convention to Milan from the Washington Hilton. 

 

Audience Member:  [inaudible 00:07:31].

 

Professor John Yoo:  Yes. But I'm going to get to Malcolm. Don't worry. We've got something for him.  But actually, the reason I was going to mention John Malcolm, my favorite Civil War reenactor down here, is because, actually, this panel is one that I appeared on in November of 2001.  I actually remember distinctly appearing, although, back then, The Federalist Society was not this large and we did not have all the rooms of the Mayflower Hotel filled simultaneously. But we had a panel. And it was about what are we going to do after the 9/11 attacks.

 

And John and I were at the Justice Department in the days of those attacks, and the weeks after.  And I went back and read some of the things that we argued for and argued about back then. And they seemed to me remarkably unchanged, in a way. And so, I still think we have these fundamental differences to resolve about how to conduct foreign intelligence or counter espionage surveillance, and reconcile it with a Fourth Amendment due process approach to normal criminal law. 

 

      I think the problem still, for me, is that if you're in war, and we're in war time, the president is the commander in chief. And part of conducting war successfully is to conduct what's called signals intelligence, is to conduct espionage and intelligence on the communications of the enemy.  This is something that goes on to this day. In fact, I'm sure Beth is going to talk about this. But if you look at the -- she didn't call it dissent. I think of it as a dissenting opinion to the latest report of the Civil Liberties Board about the implementation of Section 702. It goes through a lot of examples. Declassified, but still lots of examples of how this kind of surveillance has protected the national security of the United States in remarkable ways.

 

      I'm sure you can see it's being put to good use in Ukraine. I often ask, actually, my friends who are in favor of the idea that Congress has to declare war, whether they support what Joe Biden is doing in Ukraine, where we give Ukrainians the weapons, we give them the intelligence on what to shoot the weapons at. All we don't do is press the button on the missile. But it's clear that American intelligence is providing the Ukrainians with a lot of the tools for the successes that they've had.

 

      But that's all part of signals intelligence, which I think has traditionally been part of the commander in chief function and part of, if not the core, of the executive power.  The problem is that we tend to view, after 9/11 — it's really after Nixon, but after 9/11 — we tend to view the means that we're using to try to execute that function in a domestic criminal law lens, where we think, "Why can't this kind of surveillance be subject to the same constitutional scheme that we use to conduct, essentially, surveillance to catch people for committing criminal attacks? Why can't we have a warrant requirement, approved by a judge, based on probable cause, and apply that to surveillance we're doing for national security purposes?

 

      The one thing that's different, though, about 9/11 -- and, by the way, that was the fundamental problem we tried to solve in the weeks and months after 9/11 when the program that became Section 702 first started. And I was the lawyer at the Justice Department who participated in standing that program up. So, if anybody wants to ask any questions that I'm not going to answer, go ahead. But I was there. I saw its creation. And I worked on the very first legal opinions about it.

 

      And this is the same problem today that we thought about back then. But I think what's striking to me, thinking about it now, 22 years later, is that the strategic situation for us is far worse. We are not just dealing with Al Qaeda and the attacks on 9/11, terrible as they were. We are dealing with the revival of an axis that really has, as its aim, pulling down the American liberal world order. We're facing these kinds of challenges from China, Russia, and now Iran, simultaneously in Ukraine, of course, and now in the Hamas attacks in Israel, and then China's threats in the South China Sea and, ultimately, to Taiwan. And we're going to argue about minimization procedures, when this kind of threat is rising against the United States?

 

      It reminds me — I hate to say it — of the United States' decision to stop warrantless surveillance in the period before World War I and World War II, where the secretary of war at that time said, "We're going to shut down our interception of potential enemy communications by telegraph and telephone, because gentlemen do not read each other's mail. That was the attitude we had through December 7,, 1941. You look at the kinds of debates we're having now about whether to reauthorize Section 702, when we're in a strategic situation which, to me, is much worse than 9/11. I worry historians are going to look back at us now, the way we look back at our leaders during the interwar period.

 

      So let me just say, briefly, why I think this conflict exists.  I think presidential power, and using intelligence in wartime is fundamentally different than a criminal justice system Fourth Amendment due process warrant approach in this one respect: the reason why the government is collecting this information is to try to stop future attacks. It has to do with what Judge Richard Posner called "finding a needle in a haystack." That means you have to engage in a lot of guesswork. You have to surveille lots of channels of communication, because you don't already know the names of the people who might be spies, might be terrorists, might be enemy officers.

 

      In contrast, the Fourth Amendment process takes place when a crime has already happened, when the harm to the country has already occurred, and you're almost conducting an historical enterprise to find out who's accountable. So, that's why we can have these standards: warrant application to a judge, naming an individual with probable cause they committed a crime because the crime has already happened. The need to do surveillance for national security purposes is future looking. You're not trying to hold anybody responsible or accountable in the legal system. You are just trying to identify threats and prevent them from happening. It involves a very different mindset, a very different kind of power than the kind that police and prosecutors traditionally use.

 

      So, just very briefly, because my time has run out because of all the jokes I tell, which is why I'm usually on most panels. And then, New Jersey, of course, provided a whole wealth of ones I didn't even anticipate. But two points to end. One is, what's the Patriot Act? To me, the Patriot Act was a compromise that we made back in 2001 after the 9/11 attacks. Part of it was a political compromise. But another way to think of it is it created a safe harbor. Because the way we've done national security surveillance before, if it's on the president's authority alone, that meant the president was solely and singularly accountable. 

 

If you think about what the FISA statute and the Patriot Act did, it created this weird mashup off all three branches now involved in national security searches. It almost doesn't hold the president accountable. Now you've got this made-up court that's involved with it that issues things that sound like warrants, but are not Fourth Amendment warrants, authorized by Congress.  It creates, basically, what Congress offers and what the courts offer to the executive branch: "If you do your searches through the Patriot Act method, we're going to give it a kind of safe harbor treatment, and not just rely on you, the president, having to take responsibility alone for the way the searches are done."

 

And then my last point is there are, of course, because of the abuses in the 2016 election with the, oh gosh, Steele Report -- I say it all the time on TV, but I try to forget it, the Steele Report or the abuses by the FBI to investigate President Trump for being an alleged Russian agent, the Russia hoax. I think you see that, of course, in some conservative skepticism of the use of warrantless surveillance. But I would propose this at the end: it seems to me the problem is not conducting searches for national security purposes — which I think, as a country, we just have to do — or really the way we do it. I think the problem is the FBI. I think the real solution is to separate the FBI into two agencies.  

 

We are almost unique in the western industrialized world by combining law enforcement on the one hand and then counterintelligence, espionage, terrorism and then putting it into one agency. And I think some of the abuses are that we've allowed this domestic law enforcement agency, essentially a police agency, to have access to the kind of tools which I think should only be in the hands of the military and the intelligence agencies. So, I'd say, rather than try to figure out ways to reduce the scope of what we're doing to protect the country, to reduce the kinds of searches we're engaged in, I think the real problem is that the FBI has become too powerful, that it would be better to divide the agency into two parts, and they should not meet. And keep foreign intelligence and domestic law enforcement actually separate, rather than combining them into an all-powerful agency. 

 

And, lastly, the proposals you're going to start hearing for, as Judge Matey said, the reauthorization of this, are going to come with conditions like "Let's make the FBI even more powerful before we reauthorize. Let's have more layers of review. Let's have more bureaucracy." I think that's actually going to make the problem worse, not better. So, thank you very much for bearing with me. And I look forward to the comments and questions. 

     

Hon. Beth A. Williams:  Thank you for the introduction, Judge. And thank you to Matthew and the National Security Practice Group and The Federalist Society for the invitation to participate in today's panel. Before I discuss Section 702, just a brief word about the report, which has the fantastic acronym of PCLOB, and the work that we've done. So, we're a small agency created by statute in 2007 in response to a recommendation from the 9/11 Commission. Our statutory duty is to provide oversight of government counterterrorism programs and make recommendations for how to balance the protection of privacy and civil liberties with the needs of national security. 

 

      There are five Senate-confirmed members of the board, currently, three democrats and two republicans. The board spent a year and a half investigating how the U.S. intelligence community uses its authority under Section 702.  And, in the course of the project, we received significant public input and numerous briefings and materials from the agencies that run the program and develop actionable intelligence from it. Although the report is a 3-2 report and member DiZinno and I wrote a separate statement with different analysis and recommendations, two main points emerged from this investigation about which all five members agreed. 

 

      First, the Section 702 program is highly valuable to the national security of the United States and provides irreplaceable intelligence. In 2022, almost 2/3 of the articles in the President's Daily Intelligence Briefing — so, arguably, the most important high-level intelligence the United States has — contained information acquired through Section 702. Congress has to reauthorize this program, or American national security will suffer a disastrous blow. It is not at all an overstatement to say that lives depend on this program. 

 

      The second thing we agreed about: while all five members agreed that Section 702 is not a bulk collection program, we also agreed that reforms to the program are in order to fix some problems with its operation, particularly by the FBI, and to prevent its possible misuse for political or other improper purposes. This can be done without degrading the value of the program. As the board concluded, and as my colleague Rich DiZinno and I emphasize in our separate statement, Section 702 provides critical insights into some of the most urgent threats facing the country, including the proliferation of weapons to hostile nations and militant groups; cyber threats to critical infrastructure; the conflict in Ukraine; hostile state behavior; malicious cyber activity, including from China, Russia, and Iran; the trafficking of fentanyl across our borders; and the resurgence across the globe of hubs of terrorist activity focused against the United States. 

 

      As the president's Intelligence Advisory Board — which is a separate organization from my own — stated earlier this year, not reauthorizing Section 702 would be "one of the worst intelligence failures of our time." So, while Section 702 is solely directed at foreign targets, it's also valuable for finding and stopping terrorists and foreign intelligence activity inside the United States. By collecting communications of foreign targets, it's possible to discover if those targets have associates in the United States or are talking about potential victims in the United States. And this is crucial. And I think it's overlooked.

 

      We learned from the September 11 attacks that all the foreign intelligence collection in the world is not worth much if the intelligence agencies can't connect the dots to find actual specific people who are threatening our national security. And the world, unfortunately, since then, has not gotten safer, as Professor Yoo was saying. The atrocities committed in Israel on October 7 are what a massive failure of intelligence looks like. We should not kid ourselves that we've defeated terrorism. Hence, personnel at the CIA, NSA, FBI and National Counterterrorism Center may perform U.S. person queries of information collected under Section 702, in accordance with procedures reviewed and approved by the Foreign Intelligence Surveillance Court. 

 

      Any assertion that these queries are not valuable is demonstrably false. There are three reasons for that. First, queries are a quick preliminary step that helps analysists to identify leads for further investigation. For example, if our military recovers on the battlefield the cell phone of a terrorist that contains a 212 New York area code, our intelligence community would likely seek to run that phone number in Section 702-acquired information to discover if it belongs to a U.S.-based contact of that terrorist. 

 

      Second, queries allow the intelligence community to identify victims or potential victims. If foreign actors are targeting Americans for harm, it's important to know who they are targeting. With that knowledge, the IC can warn the potential victim and hopefully thwart or mitigate the attack. And this is especially true for cyber-attacks. Finally, U.S. person queries are an efficient way for investigators to rule out inaccurate tips or leads. A U.S. person query that returns no results is still operationally valuable because it may eliminate further or more intrusive means of investigation, such as invasive physical or electronic searches or other electronic surveillance.

 

      There are a few mischaracterizations of U.S. person queries that should be addressed. And U.S. person queries are really what's being discussed in Congress today. I think most people are in agreement that Section 702 should be reauthorized. But a lot of the discussion is about U.S. person queries, so a few mischaracterizations of them. First, the number of queries that are being discussed refer not to actual persons but to query terms or identifiers. What does that mean? Well, for example, an individual may use multiple selectors to communicate with a foreign target, for example, email, phone, etc. 

 

      A single selector may be queried multiple times. Or the U.S. person associated with the query term may not be a person at all, but may be a company or association, not a specific American citizen. Indeed, in many cases involving cyber threats, the U.S. person query term is an inanimate object, such as critical infrastructure physically located in the United States, whose identifier is queried as part of an investigation. The numbers of U.S. person queries, therefore, are almost certainly greater than the number of actual U.S. persons whose identifiers have been searched. 

 

      The second important misunderstanding is that a query does not authorize additional collection of U.S. person information. It does not authorize that. Queries are simply database inquiries of already collected lawful information. And when it comes to the FBI, the database itself is pretty small. The FBI has access to only a small fraction of the total Section 702 information collected, roughly 3.2 percent, and those are the ones that involve predicated national security investigations. Of that amount, U.S. person queries returned content that the FBI personnel reviewed in less than 2 percent of cases. That is to say, in 98 percent of the searches, no U.S. person communications are ever seen by the FBI. 

 

      Having said that, significant reforms to Section 702 are in order, particularly with respect to how the FBI performs queries. In many cases, FBI personnel have not followed their own rules for querying Section 702 information. And there's no excuse for that. The American public deserves and must have confidence that its government follows the rules guarding against improper exercises of its authority.  Even more troubling were the abuses leading to a national security investigation of President Trump and several of his associates. The surveillance in that case was conducted pursuant to court order under Title 1 of FISA, not Section 702.

 

      But it raised concerns about the Bureau's adherence to protocols and safeguards for the protection of privacy and civil liberties. This has to be fixed. And we can discuss, a little bit more, some of the recommendations that we have. But, in closing, I'd like to emphasize that we can and must balance national security with protection of privacy and civil liberties in the operation of Section 702. Existing guardrails should be strengthened, and new limits should be imposed by Congress to prevent the misuse of the authority. At the same time, failure to reauthorize the program, or reauthorizing it in a way that would hobble the use of lawfully collected information would be devastating to our ability to protect the country. Thanks.

 

Gene Schaerr:  Well, I'd like to just follow up on Beth's comment that reforms of Section 702 are needed in order for it to be reauthorized, and maybe illustrate some of the reasons why that's so true.  And let me begin with a question for the group.  How many of us have ever donated to a political campaign, a congressional campaign, specifically?  Probably everybody in the room, multiple times. Well, you may be glad to know, if you've ever done that, that according to a recent disclosure from the intelligence community, your contribution to that Congressperson may well have resulted in the FBI spying on you and 19,000 other contributors without a warrant, using this massive database of information that's been collected pursuant to Section 702, and, as Beth mentioned, is supposed to be focused on foreign threats and foreign persons. 

 

      Recent disclosures also show that this database was used in 2021 to conduct 3.4 million warrantless searches of Americans' communications. And even after an effort by the FBI to shape up for this reauthorization debate, in 2022 the FBI still used that database to conduct more than 200,000 such warrantless searches. And the FBI itself admits that at least 8,000 of those 200,000 searches were non-compliant with the FBI's own stated standards. And those included searches directed at at least one republican House member, a U.S. senator, a state senator, a judge, and a lot of people's girlfriends and a lot of other people.

 

      And through this Section 702 database and through other means, today the executive branch conducts surveillance on our own citizens on a scale that would have been unimaginable to those who wrote and ratified Articles I and II of our Constitution and who wrote and ratified the Fourth Amendment in the years between 1787 and 1791. And in that regard, I think it's important to distinguish between surveillance of foreign persons and surveillance of American citizens, which are on, I believe, a very, very different constitutional footing.  But the challenge that we have is that the modern surveillance state is directed, in substantial part, at American citizens, foreign persons as well, but, in substantial part, against American citizens.

 

      And it's not just the Section 702 database. There are actually four broad categories of surveillance of Americans today in the U.S. Besides 702, a second type of surveillance is conducted under a different provision of FISA, which Beth mentioned earlier, Title 1. That, at least, requires a warrant. And that's the authority that was later found to have been misused in the surveillance of who knows how many members of the Trump transition team in 2016, but including my client, Carter Page. And that provision nominally requires probable cause to believe that an American is acting as an agent of a foreign power. 

 

      But it's been well-established now that in the case of Carter Page, because of the present lack of any real adversarial process in the secret FISA court that was mentioned earlier, the FBI was able to get four warrants against Carter Page based on weak, and, to some extent, even fabricated evidence that never would have passed muster in a normal court. The third mechanism for surveillance of U.S. citizens is Section 2.3 of Executive Order 12333, which is not based on any underlying statute, but it allows the intelligence community to spy on Americans' texts and emails and browsing history and anything else stored in the cloud, again, without a warrant.

 

      And the fourth mechanism, which currently is completely unregulated, is government purchases of our data. And these purchases allow spying on Americans' most sensitive information of all kinds, including our location, our internet activity, and, again, all without a warrant. Well, fortunately, the upcoming expiration of Section 702 provides an opportunity for Congress to reconsider and, I hope, reign in this entire, massive, multipronged system for spying on our fellow citizens.

 

      As you can imagine, the FBI and other elements of the intelligence community are demanding what they call a clean reauthorization with no added guardrails of Section 702 or any of these other three systems of surveillance. But, fortunately, as far as I can tell, just as there is zero support in Beth's agency, PCLOB, for a clean reauthorization of Section 702, as far as I can tell, there is zero support in Congress for a clean reauthorization of that authority.

 

      And so, the real question at this point is this: if Section 702 is reauthorized, what are the conditions or the protections that should accompany that reauthorization? The organization that I represent, and a number of other organizations on the political right and left and center, believe that Section 702 should, in fact, be reauthorized, for many of the reasons that have been discussed already, but that it should be done in a way that respects four specific principles.

 

      Number one, any surveillance of Americans should be undertaken only pursuant to a statute enacted by the people's representatives in the Article I branch, and not through executive orders or any other kind of self-appointed authority by an executive agency. Number two, Congress should recognize that Americans have a legitimate expectation of privacy in any electronic data that they have taken reasonable steps to protect, including password protection. And, absent a genuine emergency, and consistent with the Fourth Amendment, any government-related searches of our data that we've made an effort to protect should be undertaken only under the authority of a probable cause warrant. 

 

      And people in the intelligence community worry about whether that would be too burdensome. But if you take Beth's example of a phone found on a battlefield that has a 212 number in it, if the FBI goes to a court and asks for a warrant to do a search for that 212 number, they're going to get a warrant in an instant. And so, I think the concerns about the difficulty of the warrant requirement are vastly overblown. And, of course, we operate with warrants in many aspects of our legal system anyway. 

 

      Number three is that agencies should not be allowed to buy their way around the Fourth Amendment and other legitimate privacy protections by getting our personal information from data brokers. And, number 4, any surveillance of Americans should be subject to real oversight by Congress and the judiciary, thereby ensuring accountability for the exercise of whatever authorities are granted to the executive branch to surveille our own citizens.

 

      Fortunately, a substantial, bipartisan, bicameral group of senators and congressmen just this week have introduced a bill that, in my view, satisfies all of these four principles. It's called the Government Surveillance Reform Act, and it's co-sponsored in the senate by none other than our own beloved Senator Mike Lee on the republican side, and by Senator Ron Wyden on the democratic side, and several other senators in both parties. 

 

      And, in the House, where the bill has also been introduced, it's co-sponsored by House Judiciary Subcommittee chair Andy Biggs and other prominent members of the House Freedom Caucus, along with several members of the House Progressive Caucus and a number of other, more centrist, House members. In fact, as you all know, it's rare to see such a wide variety of people on all parts of the political spectrum agreeing on something like this.

 

      If it passes, the GSRA will, I think, reign in our ballooning surveillance system in several ways. Number one, it will generally prohibit warrantless searches through any of the four mechanisms that I mentioned earlier of Americans' personal information, including phone information, text and email communications, geolocation, web browsing, and internet search history. Now, the bill has reasonable exceptions for genuine emergencies, such as identifying malicious software and truly serious imminent threats.  

 

      In addition, this bill will fully phase out surveillance under a provision of the Patriot Act that is almost dead. You remember The Princess Bride? It's called Section 215 of the Patriot Act. And it is almost dead, but it's not quite dead. And the GSRA will completely phase it out so that it can't come back to life. And that's a provision that gives the government warrantless access to business records like all of our emails stored at Google or wherever, and any documents that we may have stored in the cloud on our Google Drive or Microsoft OneDrive or anything like that. Section 215 allows warrantless access to those materials in certain circumstances. 

 

      This legislation will also require the appointment of civil liberties experts or amici to assist the secret FISA court in testing warrant requests in sensitive cases like the Carter Page case. And, having gotten deeply into Carter Page's case now, as his appellate counsel, I am virtually certain that the shenanigans that plagued the Carter Page investigation would not have happened if the people at the FBI had realized that there was significant risk that somebody was going to catch them in the FISA court. And having an independent person there, sort of advocating for privacy, generally, I think would have deterred the kind of misconduct that we saw there and that has now been widely recognized.

 

      The legislation will also hold officials in the FBI and other intelligence agencies accountable for negligent or willful violations of the new legislation, or FISA or other authorities, including in egregious cases, firing them and stripping them of their security clearances. And one of the things that I've learned as I've talked to a lot of people about this issue is that, typically, the thing that FBI agents most fear, if they get caught doing something inappropriate, is that they would lose their security clearance, because that means they can no longer go to the private sector and make four or five times what they're making working for the government. And so, in order to have real accountability, you need to put people's security clearances at risk. 

 

      So, just to close, the GSRA already enjoys widespread bipartisan support because, in my view, it's the most balanced and comprehensive surveillance reform in 45 years. And, perhaps most important, given the theme of our conference, if it passes, it will make major strides towards realigning the federal government's surveillance powers with the founders' vision of what our government should be.  Thank you.

 

Hon. Stewart Baker:  One of the things that I learned when I started out working for senior people in my law firm and they started telling me about the evils of the Smoot-Hawley tariff and the like, and I thought, "God, this guy is really old, and he's giving us all this history." And I realized that once you get to a certain age, nobody actually knows what you really remember and what you just heard about from your grandparents. So, I thought I would talk a little bit about the decision to let the Japanese communications go untapped. No, I'm not going to do that. 

 

Audience Member:  But you were there at the time.

 

Hon. Stewart Baker:  There you go. I actually am going to talk a little bit about my history in this, because I think you're going to be there too, sooner or later. And it will tell you why I'm here and why I'm saying the things that I'm saying. I joined the intelligence community in the '90s when I went to work as general counsel of the National Security Agency. And the 90s were a time that was surprisingly similar to the times we face now. That is to say, there were a lot of congressional democrats who were pretty skeptical of the national security state and the national security agencies and surveillance and always up for a little more restriction on them.

 

      And then, by the end of the 90s, there was a growing group of Freedom Caucus republicans who were equally skeptical and enthusiastic about reigning in the law enforcement and national security agencies. And that created a phenomenon that we see now, a sort of ratchet that you could get something that restricted what the intelligence agencies did through Congress. It wasn't always easy, but you could do it. But if it didn't work out, you were never going to repeal it, because the people who were opposed to the national security state were always eager to find a reason to leave in place the restrictions that had been put there before.

 

      And so, we had this slowly ratcheting set of restrictions that was just generated by the political times. And the beneficiary of that ratchet was something called the wall between law enforcement and intelligence, which you may have heard of. The wall came out of an idea that was kind of a good idea, in the abstract. We had all of these really incredible capabilities to do surveillance that we were using against other nation-states that were existential threats to the country. And we were glad to have them. And then, the question was, well, should we use them against criminals in the United States? 

 

      And the thought was, well, that's really overkill. We're going to end up with a police state in which all of these surveillance tools are used against Americans routinely. Let's put a wall between what we do for national security and what we do for law enforcement. And it kind of made sense. I was at NSA. And it made sense to us too, because we were a little afraid that if the Justice Department started using all of these intelligence tools, they would, sooner or later, want to go to court and brag about them in open court, about what they had done. And that, we didn't want to see.

 

      So, we sort of said, "Yeah, let's have a wall. That's a good idea." And what happened, thanks to the ratchet, is, gradually, that wall got higher and higher. And by the end of the '90s and into 2000, 2001, the FISA Court had taken over the enforcement of the wall, had required every agent that came to the court to swear that they were observing the wall, and they would always observe the wall, and they hadn't breached the wall. And, just as today, the notion was, well, we have to make sure that we have enforced these restrictions. And the FISA Court caught an agent who had let some information slide across the wall about national security. 

 

      And the judge said, "This person must never appear in federal court again to testify. He's unreliable. This is the end of his career, for sure. And maybe we should be thinking about a perjury prosecution for having signed this assurance that he was going to be observing the wall." That's where things stood in the summer of 2001. Also in the summer of 2001, we knew that Al Qaeda was planning a big attack on the United States or its allies. We didn't know where. We didn't know when. We just knew it was coming. And, at that point, the CIA discovered that some of Al Qaeda's worst actors were already in the United States. 

 

      They wanted to tell the FBI because the CIA doesn't look for people in the United States. You need the FBI and their law enforcement authorities and their big task force to go looking for those guys. And when they said, "Well, we want to tell them about that," the FBI general counsel said, "Are you kidding?  That's the end of your career too. You can't do that. That's a violation of the wall." And, to their credit, the people who wanted to make that report screamed bloody murder. They said, "This rule is only helping terrorists.  And it's going to kill somebody soon."

 

      They were nonetheless told, "You are not going to provide that information. You can take your intelligence resources in the FBI" — the two men and a dog that worked at the FBI in intelligence at that time — "and see if you can find them." And they were still looking two weeks later when all of them slammed into the World Trade Center.  So, we had weeks to find those guys. And we didn't find them because we had adopted a rule that sounded like a perfectly good rule, good for civil liberties. Why not? They can work around that. But they couldn't.

 

      Finally, the enforcement of that rule drove the FBI to say, "Okay, if that's what you want, that's what you're going to get." And that's what we got. I had to live with the consequence of having said good things about the wall prior to that. I ended up testifying to the 9/11 Commission. And it's deeply, profoundly disturbing to have to say I supported this. This is a question that will come to you too. If the restrictions that are being proposed on 702 work out as badly as I fear they will in the world we live in, we're going to find ourselves cleaning up after a major terrorist event and asking ourselves why did we think this was a good idea? 

 

      So, I'm going to suggest there are plenty of reasons to reform the intelligence community. But there need to be two rules. One, you've got to be responding to an actual abuse that you can identify, and whose cure you can identify. And then, second, the cure has got to be such that it doesn't wreck the intelligence capabilities that we need to protect ourselves in a world that is more dangerous now than it has been in the last 20 years. I don't think that the standards, especially the requirement for getting a warrant to do a search that the FBI today does by going in and typing in a name meets that requirement, it would not kill the program. It would just drown it in paper. It would be ten times the paperwork load that currently is being carried in doing FISA applications. And that load is enormous.

 

      And the purpose of it would be to say, "We want to make it harder to find out whether Americans are talking to terrorism intelligence, terrorism targets outside the United States. We really want to make sure we've made that as hard and as paperwork intensive as possible. I'm just not sure that that makes sense. And I don't know what problem we are solving. We heard a lot about the possibility that the FBI was looking at donations and officials to see whether they were in the database. But many of those were efforts to find out whether they were being watched for an attack or otherwise under surveillance by international figures. 

 

      There is almost no case, despite all the innuendo in this area, where you can say, "Yeah, in those millions of searches, I found 50 of them where the only explanation is malice or partisan bias." It's just very hard to find actual cases where partisan bias occurred. And if you wanted to stop partisan bias, going to the FISA Court is the last place you would go. First, put aside what they did on 9/11. They had four opportunities to review the Carter Page affidavits, which were demonstrably flawed from the start.

 

      And by the fourth one, which was June of 2017, anybody who read the newspapers, even the New York Times, would know that there was a problem with the Steele dossier and the data that was being used to support the Carter Page affidavit. And what did the FISA Court do?  Bupkis. They just sat there and let it happen. So why are we thinking they're going to be a protection against the misuse of this authority? They're just going to be rubber-stamping this stuff. They have a constituency. The constituency more or less inhabits the faculty lounges of the top twenty law schools in America. And that's who they respond to. They're not ever going to stand up for "Trumpistas" who are under investigation. 

 

      So, I don't understand why we think that's a solution. I don't understand why we have hundreds of other ideas. Just kind of "Hey, isn't this a good idea too?" Just like the wall was a good idea. It sounds good. That's not a reason to do it. We have to say, "We saw an abuse, and this is how we're fixing it in the most targeted possible way." There are plenty of abuses that need to be fixed. Many of them we saw in the last five, seven years. But we can fix all of them with targeted solutions, not by saying, "Why don't we think of as many possible ways to make life hard for the people who are doing this intelligence collection as possible."

 

Hon. Paul Matey:  So, let's begin our discussion with a topic that I have a passing interest in, which is the role of the courts. I hear some to say that the answer is Article III judges and that these are warrants like any other warrants. They can be reviewed for probable cause. The burden and inefficiency will be light, and the protection of liberties strong. I hear others to say there is no comparison between the kinds of warrants that would be necessary for predictive crimes, as opposed to retrospective investigations, and the idea that judges are capable of doing this in the time necessary to help an investigation is fanciful.

 

      How do we resolve this tension? And without sort of getting right to the big question, which is, what is the nature of the Article II power to begin with? Because it seems as though, at least as I'm hearing it, where you come out on the nature of executive authority here sort of resolves the question of what kind of process that's needed. And I imagine there are varying viewpoints on that answer. I welcome your thoughts.

 

Gene Schaerr:  I'm happy to start, if you like.

 

Hon. Paul Matey:  Please.

 

Gene Schaerr:  Like, John, I have some experience — and Beth — I have some experience working in the executive branch. I was an associate White House counsel under the first President Bush. And I don't think I take a backseat to anybody with respect to presidential power to conduct military affairs and foreign affairs. But I don't see anything in Article II that gives the president the authority to surveille American citizens. I think that authority is properly lodged in Congress. 

 

      And to the extent that American citizens are going to be subject to surveillance, that's something that Congress needs to decide. And if there's a good case for authorizing the executive branch to engage in that, then they should do that. And they have, in some limited cases. And with respect to the warrant requirement, I've read analyses from a number of ex-members of the intelligence community and the Justice Department who say it would not really be that big a problem to seek a warrant if there's good reason to search the 702 database for information about American citizens, that, in fact, it would not be that big a job to do that. 

 

      We have prosecutors seek warrants all the time. It's typically not a terribly burdensome process. And if we don't think the FISA court is up to the task, then another option is to just have ordinary Article III Courts do that, as appropriate. But if we're going to depart from Fourth Amendment standards, there ought to be a very good, compelling reason to do that. And, otherwise, I think we ought to follow what the Fourth Amendment says.

 

Hon. Beth A. Williams:  Can I respond to that? So, just a few points of information. First, I think it's important to know that no court has actually ever held that it's a Fourth Amendment requirement in order to conduct a U.S. person query. No court has held that. Second, 702 has nothing to do with surveilling Americans. And what the unanimous privacy and civil liberties oversight board said in 2014 — and some of us have reemphasized recently — is that if you wanted to conduct a domestic spying tool, if you wanted to put one together, 702 would be a truly terrible way to do it. Because everybody who's targeted under Section 702 has to be a foreign person overseas.

 

      So, to the extent that American communications get caught up in that, it's if you happen to be emailing with a foreign target. Which means, if they want to surveille you, the only thing that they're getting in the 702 database is one end of your communications with the foreign target. If they then say, "Oh, that guy who's communicating with the foreign target might be a terrorist too," but he's either in the United States or he's a U.S. person, then they have to go and get a warrant. So, it's not surveillance. 

 

      The only people they're allowed to target are foreigners overseas. And the intelligence community has actually had a really, really good compliance rate with regard to collection. They're over 99 percent compliant, which means that they're not inadvertently targeting Americans. Which is actually a great improvement from where it was in 2014, because we had this thing called “abouts” collection, which means the technology wasn't great and more Americans were accidently getting swept in. That's been taken care of. So that's a really good thing. 

 

      The other thing I wanted to just quickly address is Professor Yoo's suggestion about 702 being used for law enforcement. Because, if it were, that would be a big problem. And that's one of the things the board looked at. And what the board found, both in the majority report and then our report states it's not being used for law enforcement. There are zero prosecutions that have come out of Section 702 information. And that's a good thing. That means they're not using this foreign intelligence tool to try to find tax evaders and then using it in tax cases or other things. So, I think that that's another positive. There's no evidence, that we saw at least, that they're misusing it for law enforcement purposes. 

 

Prof. John Yoo:  Do you want to go, Stew?

 

Hon. Stewart Baker:  No.

 

Prof. John Yoo:  So, I think there's two different aspects to your question, Judge. So, one is what should Article III Courts do? And that's, in a way, separate from what should the Article II understanding be? Because I would say judges, of course, they don't have to listen to the executive branch at all. You have the power to reject the use of any evidence that comes out of any of this in any criminal case in your court. And, as you can see, the Article III role is being defensive. You don't have to rely on another branch.

 

      But if, in the course of conducting your own constitutional functions, you interpret the Constitution, and you feel that the evidence that's collected in this way is not done in a constitutional manner, then you can exclude it. I don't know. And this is part of the problem that arose, what Stewart's talking about with the FISA Court. It's just, if you drag the courts into it through FISA and the Patriot Act, you had FISA Courts sort of managing the way we were doing electronic communication surveillance before 9/11 and after. And I think, in a way, that was well outside the judicial function. It almost was like management of the executive branch. That's what some of the criticisms of the 9/11 commission report were. 

 

      But I think that's different than Article II. How do we understand it?  That's just what you, as a judge, could do, I think, with Article II. I don't mean to imply that Gene takes a backseat to anybody on the war power, how far it goes. It does seem to me that the Constitution gives the president, the commander in chief, power. And we have traditionally understood that power to include the authority to collect intelligence, as well as to use force. In a way, ideally, the better intelligence you have, the less force you have to use. The better signals intelligence you have, the less destruction you're going to have to use to get your targets.

 

      I don't think that the Constitution creates a different rule of war based on whether, unfortunately, some of our enemies include U.S. citizens or not, or whether people are acting on U.S. soil or not. I think that's the way we think about it because it's easy to sort of understand what we're doing within the United States, or U.S. persons as being governed by a law enforcement framework. And, again, this is stuff we thought about right after 9/11. In the Civil War, under Abraham Lincoln's theory of the war, everyone we were fighting was still an American citizen, right? Every member of the confederacy was still a citizen. 

 

      Lincoln had to grapple with this problem too. Do the laws of war, the right to use force, signals intelligence, apply in the same way, even thought we were still fighting other Americans? And Lincoln decided, no, that we're going to use the normal methods of war, even though, unfortunately, we were fighting citizens. This also kind of came up in World War II because there were Americans who went back to Japan and Germany and joined the enemy forces. And the Supreme Court had to decide, does being an American citizen mean that you still are treated by the criminal justice system, even if you're fighting against us? 

 

      And the Supreme Court said, no, you're going to use the normal rules of war, that being an American citizen fighting against us doesn’t give you a kind of immunity or right to a different level of treatment once you take that step of joining up or fighting against us.  So, there's some hypotheticals.  And they were, unfortunately, what we were worried about.  Stewart was in the government too. 

 

Hon. Stewart Baker:  Not then.

 

Prof. John Yoo:  You weren't still in there. You had just left. But these were the kind of things we were worried about at the time. And this happened in Mumbai years later. Suppose you had a roving group of terrorists with weapons going through an American City. Are you still going to use the Fourth Amendment to try to gather the intelligence to try to stop them?  What if you thought that there was a nuclear weapon, or some other kind of large explosive device being hidden in an American city? Are you going to still use a warrant requirement and the Fourth Amendment? 

 

      And then, I just say again, I think with the current situation we are in, actually, this problem is magnified. Because now it's possible, because of the internet, because of hacking, because of new technologies, for people to inflict huge amounts of damage on us, on American soil, solely using communications technologies.  So it seems to me it makes the case for actually expanding the authority of the executive branch to try to intercept electronic communications, rather than reduce it.

 

Hon. Stewart Baker:  I will only make this observation. I promised I would tell you about 1941, and now I will. In fact, Congress had passed the Federal Communications Act in the '30s and made it illegal to intercept radio communications. So it was just a flat violation of law to intercept those communications. But, in the run-up to December 7, the Army Chief of Staff, George Marshall, at the time, said, "No, forget that. We're going to do it." And so, he actually authorized intercepts in violation of federal law. 

 

      Then, after 9/11, 702 was adopted directly contrary to all of the requirements of FISA. FISA said, "This is the only way you're going to do this. And you're going to have to go to the FISA Court and collect this information." And the president said, "Nope. We're going to violate that rule." The rule of law, as it applies to intelligence, is kind of 0-for-2, in terms of coming to the right conclusion. 

 

      In both cases, the right decision was the one reached by the executive branch to say, "We're just not going to accept these limitations because they're existential." And maybe we've got one more strike in us. But it does seem to me that the longer we go and the more we pile -- anybody here read Thidwick the Big-Hearted Moose, where the moose just keeps letting more and more animals more into his antlers?

 

Prof. John Yoo:  That was from 1941 too?

 

Hon. Stewart Baker:  Yeah, exactly. My mother read it to me. Anyway, we just load more and more things onto a service and a capability we have to have to survive future conflicts. And, at some point, it just collapses, and we say, "That whole idea was a bad idea." I'm not comfortable saying "We should just violate these laws." But that sure looks like the judgment of history.

 

Hon. Paul Matey:  Gene, I want to pivot back to you and ask this question. Because I've heard this a couple of times now that this is all sort of too much theoretical concern and not enough on-the-ground consideration. And I know you've offered a different perspective on that. So, in addition to other thoughts, if you could sort of touch upon how much of a concrete concern are the intrusions of liberties that you're seeing?

 

Gene Schaerr:  Well, I think what we know from the disclosures from the intelligence community is very significant. The fact that they would do database searches, whether you call that surveillance or not, and I consider it surveillance, but whether you want to call it surveillance or not, reviewing a massive database with lots of information on people, and choosing, as your selector, people who contributed to a congressional campaign, or doing searches for a particular congressman or senator.

 

      There are lots of examples where people have run searches just because they want to get more information about an ex-girlfriend or something like that. It seems to me that's a very concrete example of an intrusion into liberty. We don't know exactly what those communications show. But people have lots of confidential communications with others. And anytime you have government reviewing your communications with somebody else, it seems to me that's a cause for concern. 

 

      And I'd just like to respond briefly to Stewart's point. It seems to me Stewart's whole argument here proves way too much. It seems to me the implication of argument is that Congress just has to take the FBI's word for it.  If the FBI says, "We really need this authority, and we really need it not to have any guardrails on it," that Congress is just supposed to take their word for it. And I think the message of the last several years is can you really trust what the FBI says? And I think, certainly, on Capitol Hill, trust for the FBI is very low in both parties.

 

Hon. Stewart Baker:  So they don't have to just take it. But then, stop lying about it. Let's be candid about this. When they say, "These are searches spying on Americans," 98, 99 percent of those searches were checks that came back, "There's nothing here." That is not spying on people. That's a check to see whether there is a communication here. And, frankly, I kind of would want to know if people who are contributing to campaigns are also in touch with foreign terrorist suspects. That's a valuable piece of information. And I'm glad that the FBI cares about that.

 

      So, to call that spying when all they were really doing was to say "I wonder if this person is tied up in this particular database," I do think you're stretching espionage well beyond what anybody would actually call it. And I would say that more than 99 percent of what the FBI was doing was what the FBI usually does. They have a database. They want to know, is somebody in that database? And then they want to find out, if it is, what’s going on inside that. 

 

      And the idea that that is spying, if 20 people are going to meet with the president and the FBI is not checking to see whether any of them is talking to a foreign terror suspect, the FBI is not doing its job. And yet, Gene's position is they ought to get a warrant before they do that. And they can't get a warrant because they don't have probable cause to believe these people are talking to a foreign terrorist. That's what they want to know. And I think we, frankly, should be a little more careful about calling that illegal espionage, when it is, in fact, a simple vetting of people who are participating in activities that could turn out to be dangerous.

 

Gene Schaerr:  Well, the whole question is what should be legal? And Congress is going to have to decide how far that authority goes. And my understanding of the system is that not every communication in that database is communications of U.S. persons with foreign terrorists or anything like that. And, in fact, if that were true, the FBI could not have admitted recently that of the 200,000 searches it did in 2021, or I guess it was 2022, that 8,000 of them were contrary to the FBI's own guidelines.

 

Hon. Stewart Baker:  And the FBI adopted those guidelines because they were crammed down their throat by the Justice Department. And the Justice Department said, "The standard is you have to have reason to believe that there's foreign intelligence that will be derived from this search." Now you've got 20 people going in to meet the president and you want to know whether any of them have been talking to foreign terrorists. Do you have reason to believe they have? Of course, you don't. Do you have reason to believe that they're going to be in the 702 database? No, you don't. So, you've violated the rule. And the rule is nuts.

 

Gene Schaerr:  Okay.  So, propose to Senators Lee and Wyden that they include an exception for people who are going in to see the president. I'm sure they'll be happy to add that. But the answer is not we just let the FBI do whatever they want.

 

Hon. Paul Matey:  So, only slightly less unpopular than the FBI on this panel, as I take it, is --

 

Gene Schaerr:  New Jersey?

 

Hon. Paul Matey:  -- is the FISA Court.  And I'm sort of wondering, is the FISA Court, then, just irrelevant to future solutions?  Is it something that can be reformed?  Will anyone speak up for it?  Or is it an idea whose time has come to pass?

 

Hon. Beth A Williams:  I'll take that. So, the FISA Court serves an important function. They review Title I orders, and they oversee the whole Section 702 program, including all of the certifications. They review the program every year and annually certify all of the procedures. So, they serve an important role. But I don't think anybody would say, "Let's just let the FBI monitor themselves and that's fine." There are serious problems with the FBI.

 

      And one of the recommendations that my co-member and I suggested is that there actually needs to be more congressional oversight. Because the FISA Court is a poor vehicle for doing the type of oversight of the potential political misuse of intelligence authorities that a lot of people are worried about. If you're worried that the FBI is going to go after political actors or associates of political actors that the FBI agents don't like, that may be a valid worry.

 

      Is the solution to, then, have the FISA Court check it? Or is maybe the solution for the sensitive terms that are used every six months, every quarter, to actually go to Congress, to people who are going to look at it really closely, not necessarily with a legal lens: is this an agent of a foreign power, or does this satisfy whatever legal standard Congress decides upon? But is this misuse of an intelligence authority? There are ways to have effective inter-branch oversight over some of these issues without necessarily going to the FISA Court.

 

Hon. Paul Matey:  Professor, before you respond, I just want to say, we have time for some questions shortly. So, if we do, if you want to take one of the microphones, and we'll get to you right after the Professor's response.

 

Prof. John Yoo:  It's not really a response to Beth. She describes what the FISA Court does quite accurately, which is approve different rules and procedures and different search mechanisms. But I want to repeat a criticism of FISA that Judge Silberman had when he testified against FISA back in the '70s, and who recently passed away. I was a clerk of his, and so I was, of course, required to read everything the guy ever wrote. And I came across his testimony against the constitutionality of FISA. 

 

      I think Robert Bork also testified along these lines, which is, how is this role, no matter how important it might be to give us assurance about what the FBI is doing, how is this consistent with the Article III Court's authority to decide cases or controversies? How is it a case or controversy to approve a search program and the rules and so on? And you go back and read their testimony.  It was actually really interesting.  They predicted this would actually draw the federal courts out of their constitutional role and get them too involved with foreign intelligence searches. And I really think this is what happened. And it will blur the accountability, therefore. 

 

      So, if you think about how the intelligence searches were done before FISA, the executive branch did them, as we've heard.  The president did them on his or her own authority. So, FDR, his administration, decides to breach the Electronic Communications Act, back from '34.  LBJ, JFK, a lot of them did this. And then they're solely accountable for the decisions. They are responsible politically for any mistakes that are made.  They can't blame the FISA Court. They can't blame Congress.

 

      And I think we should ask, is it actually a better system than one we have here, where we have this, again, this weird court, which is not deciding cases or controversies, but reaching outside and to sort of make management decisions, start blessing all of this? And then, when mistakes are made with Carter Page — undeniable, that what happened to Carter Page was a violation — why don't we think about the president, who authorized those, being responsible? Instead, we get into the arguments about FISA Courts, and so on. That's the very blurring of accountability which the separation of powers was designed to defeat.

 

Ed Hearst:  Yeah, thank you. Ed Hearst from out of the San Francisco Bay Area. I wanted to follow up on a comment that Professor Yoo made with respect to separating things out. And I wanted to get the panel's comments on that. Perhaps taking the FBI's counterintelligence division and counterterrorism efforts that relate to overseas and having it report to the DNI. Maybe that has the benefit of taking domestic politics out of it somewhat, and also taking out the fact that they could use these advanced tools, even for domestic law enforcement. And so, I wanted to get people's thoughts on maybe having counterintelligence and antiterrorism report to DNI instead of the FBI overall, and DOJ. Thank you.

 

Hon. Paul Matey:  Anybody?

 

Prof. John Yoo:  It was my idea, so I shouldn't say how great it is again.

 

Hon. Beth A. Williams:  Look, I think Stewart made a great point before, which is that I think the solution should be tailored to the problem. So, if you see that the FBI is using these intelligence tools for law enforcement purposes, that's a problem. That's not something we've seen, at least in our analysis of this. Prosecutions are not coming out of these intelligence tools. If there were, I would agree that that would be a problem, and that might be a consideration.

 

Prof. John Yoo:  So, is it accurate that most of the abuses that the report talks about occur in the FBI, though? It's not the CIA or the NSA that are -- Gene mentioned the 100,000, 200,000, kind of, searches that weren't supposed to happen, happened. So that's my point. It's not that the FBI is actually taking this and using it for prosecution, which would be a serious problem. That would be crossing a red line. 

 

      But it's that the mindset of the FBI is that you've combined the counterintelligence and law enforcement functions. And so, you have people who are thinking in this confused manner. And so, they think, "Oh, I've got this database.  I can just sort of check it".  They're not thinking, like a counterintelligence agency would do, because they are within part of this domestic law enforcement operation.

 

Hon. Beth A. Williams:  Look, the FBI is very decentralized. It's not like the NSA. It's very decentralized. That has its advantages and disadvantages. I think there are mission advantages to the way it is. But one disadvantage is that you've got agents all over in branch offices who don't have necessarily great training, and who I think need to have a better mindset. So, we have a lot of recommendations for how to improve it so that these tools are used properly, so you're not doing an improper search.

 

Hon. Paul Matey:  I'll give myself the final question, then. One of the fascinating things, going back to the topic of our week here, is when you look at this from an originalist lens, I wonder about the panel's thoughts on whether it's appropriate to even ask these seemingly 20th century questions, let alone 19th and 18th century questions in what is now a 21st century problem. We talked about the Patriot Act and the horrors of 9/11.

 

      These all pale against the threats that we now see, given the consolidations of information and the idea that we now live in a digital, as opposed to analog, world. Is that an argument for the status quo? Or is that an argument for greater congressional vigor in this area to examine what has to be — and I welcome your thoughts — an entire shift in the landscape of the kinds of threats that now exist against the United States? 

 

Gene Schaerr:  Could I maybe answer with a thought experiment? Imagine that we could bring James Madison back and let him watch for a year or so what's happening with our intelligence system and explain to him the history and the background and all of that. I think, if he were to see -- and I talked earlier about four different sort of programs, four different ways that the FBI is engaged in surveillance or analysis of Americans’ communications and that sort of thing.  I think he would be horrified by it, both as a matter of his understanding of the Fourth Amendment and of his understanding of the proper allocation of power between the Section 1 and Section 2 branches. 

 

      I think he would say, "Yeah, there are probably some efficiencies in allowing the executive branch to do this on its own, without meaningful oversight from either the judicial branch or from Congress. But we decided, in the way we set up the government, that we were going to accept some inefficiencies as the price of freedom. And we did that in the structure of the Constitution, and we did that in many of the amendments that we passed to the Constitution." And I think his recommendation would be we ought to go back to that model.

 

Hon. Stewart Baker:  So, if I could pick up on what are the threats that we're looking at now, everybody in this room has had their fill of predictions about artificial intelligence and where it's going and what it's going to mean. But the consensus is it's going to empower a lot of people. Even if it doesn't decide to do it on its own, it's going to empower pretty much anybody who wants to develop brand-new, much more toxic poisons, much more infectious diseases, and to do so on their own, without a lot of help. That means that we will all survive, at the suffering of every single other person on the globe. 

 

      It is not possible, most people would say, to build the artificial intelligence so that it won't do that. We've already seen plenty of jailbreaks of artificial intelligence, and that's almost certainly an inherent feature of AI as it's being designed today. So, when you ask people who worry about that, "What do we do about that?" the only answer they have is, "We need to do a better job of surveillance of who is doing what with these tools, and how they are developing the things that are made possible by the tools." It's not a question of can we accept some inefficiencies in doing that. 

 

      The question is, how many deaths do you accept before you say, "We need to do a better job of surveillance." I don't love the world that that implies. But I don't think James Madison would come back and say, "Well, you're just going to have to live in my world and suffer 21st century consequences. It's not a good situation. But the fact is, we are being pushed by increasing capabilities in the hands of irresponsible people towards ever greater surveillance. Because, without that, sooner or later, these weapons of mass destruction are going to be deployed by disgruntled teenagers. 

 

Prof. John Yoo:  Taking Gene's thought experiment, we don't have to make a thought experiment. We can ask, "How did President Madison do in the War of 1812?" He took these attitudes towards it, and we almost lost, right? It was just because General Jackson beat the British that we survived as a country. I'd rather have Alexander Hamilton in charge if we're going to be defending the country. I'm happy to have Madison govern us for domestic policy. But I think it's a different mindset. And that's what I was trying to get at.

 

      Again, because of 9/11 we have to think of this in this way. The Madisonian system of balanced powers, overlapping checks and balances does not work when you're talking about external threats to the country's safety and security. And I think the framers were aware of this. This is why we have those parts of the Federalist Papers that Hamilton wrote that talk about energy in the executive and the ability to act with swiftness and secrecy and speed, because those are things you need, the qualities a president needs to have to defend against external threats.

 

      And there are going to be errors. Part of the way, maybe, to understand this panel is how do you deal with the fact that you know you're going to make mistakes. And so, in the context of new technology, do we feel so confident that we are in command of all the costs and benefits of different rules that we want to impose these preexisting rules rather than using maybe a standard that we use after the fact to think of damages maybe as a remedy, rather than saying, "We're just never going to do this, ever," as kind of a blanket, rule-based system? 

 

      I think in the kind of uncertainty the judge has talked about, we want to have a standard base that's going to say, "Let's use the technologies first. And then, afterwards, if there are abuses and mistakes, we'll figure out some kind of damages remedy for those harmed, like Carter Page, I think, should get a lot of money from the government. But that doesn't mean we shouldn't do foreign surveillance anymore. That's a rule basis I think is unwise in a period of uncertainty.

 

Hon. Beth A. Williams:  I would just say, look, I go back to the Constitution. It doesn't have to be a thought experiment. The Fourth Amendment doesn't say "There shall be no searches and seizures." It says, "There shall be no unreasonable searches and seizures." And I think that was very purposeful. And so, I think Congress should be interpreting that. They should be thinking about what is the appropriate balance. We've tried to do that in our organizations. And I know Professor Yoo and others have tried to do that. But that's the question. It was not a bright line. It was understood that some things will be reasonable. And we need to consider that in the context that we're in.

 

Hon. Paul Matey:  Speaking of technology, this is the last panel of the day. So, if you are pursuing CLEs, please make sure to scan the QR code on the back of the flier.  I want to thank all of the members of this exceptional panel for this discussion today. 

 

 

3:00 p.m. - 4:30 p.m.
Fair Elections in an Era of Partisanship

2023 National Lawyers Convention

Topics: Election Law • Politics
District Room
The Mayflower Hotel
1127 Connecticut Avenue NW
Washington, DC 20006

Share

Event Video

Listen & Download

Description

Recent years have seen unprecedented controversies about election rules, including mail-in ballots and drop boxes, partisan and racial gerrymandering, early voting, ballot harvesting, and methods of vote counting. Because election laws have partisan consequences, the legislators who make election laws, the officials who administer elections, and the judges who decide election cases are often suspected of exercising power so as to increase their own side’s electoral chances. As we look ahead to future elections, this panel will consider what it means to have a fair election process and how much deference judges should pay to the determinations of officials whose actions in formulating and applying election laws may have partisan motivations.

Featuring:

  • Hon. Michael G. Adams, Secretary of State, Commonwealth of Kentucky
  • Prof. Richard Briffault, Joseph P. Chamberlain Professor of Legislation, Columbia Law School
  • Prof. Michael R. Dimino, Professor of Law, Widener University Commonwealth Law School
  • Prof. Richard H. Pildes, Sudler Family Professor of Constitutional Law, New York University School of Law
  • Hon. Bradley A. Smith, Josiah H. Blackmore II/Shirley M. Nault Professor of Law, Capital University Law School; Former Commissioner, Federal Election Commission
  • Moderator: Hon. Thomas M. Hardiman, United States Court of Appeals, Third Circuit

Speakers

Event Transcript

Mr. Erik S. Jaffe:  Prior to his appointment at the district court, he was a litigator in private practice, most recently as a partner at Reed Smith. He is an undergraduate. He has an undergraduate degree from Notre Dame, his law degree from Georgetown Law, and still teaches a one-week course at Georgetown Law involving the First and Second Amendments, which, given my interest, I may have to go audit. But without further ado, I will give you Judge Hardiman. And thank you, and welcome to our panel.

[Applause]

Hon. Thomas M. Hardiman:  Thank you, Eric. We’ve got folks coming from a very good panel that just ended. There are still some seats up front if people don’t want to stand. On this Veterans Day celebration, my thoughts turn to all those who have served, especially those who gave their last full measure of devotion to our country. So I’d like to start by honoring them with a moment of silence. Thank you.

We are fortunate to have five distinguished panelists today. Their numerous accomplishments are listed on the convention website, so I will introduce them only briefly to save us time.

Michael Dimino, to my immediate left, is a Professor of Law at Widener University Commonwealth Law School in Harrisburg, Pennsylvania. He has written extensively on constitutional law and election law. If I need help adjudicating any disputes this afternoon, I may call on Professor Dimino because he has experience as a baseball umpire and a hockey referee.

Michael Adams, next to him, is Secretary of State of the Commonwealth of Kentucky. Before assuming public office, Secretary Adams had a national practice in election law and was general counsel to the Republican Governors Association. My favorite fun fact about Secretary Adams is, like me, he’s first-generation college.

Richard Briffault is the Joseph R. Chambers—Chamberlin, excuse me—Professor of Legislation at Columbia Law School. He’s the law school’s leading authority on state and local government law. Professor Briffault has written or co-authored over 90 publications and has written extensively on preemption and campaign finance issues. He’s also very active with the American Law Institute, where he has served as reporter there.

Next to him is Bradley Smith, the Josiah Blackmore and Shirley Nault Professor of Law at Capital University Law School in Columbus, Ohio. He’s the author of three books on election law and voting rights. For five years during the George W. Bush administration, Professor Smith served as Commissioner of the Federal Election Commission and was its chairman elected in 2004—or perhaps appointed, actually. I stand corrected if that’s the case.

Finally, last but not least, Richard Pildes is the Sudler Family Professor of Constitutional Law at New York University Law School. A specialist in legal issues affecting democracy, he authored a case book called The Law of Democracy: Legal Structure of the Political Process. Professor Pildes has won two cases in the United States Supreme Court and has served as senior legal advisor to both of Barack Obama’s successful presidential campaigns.

Now, we’re going to begin in the usual manner with opening statements from each of our panelists—approximately five to seven minutes—and then I’ll seek reaction and commentary from the panelists on what they’ve heard from others. And, of course, we will conclude at the end with questions from the audience. Without further ado, please welcome Professor Dimino.

[Applause]

Prof. Michael R. Dimino:  Thank you all. Thank you, Judge Hardiman. Thanks to The Federalist Society for hosting the panel and for inviting all of us. It really is an honor to be here, particularly with such esteemed panelists. Before you rely on me to decide cases, though, you might want to ask the opinion of some of the fans and parents who watch the games that I officiate. [Laughter]

When Justice Scalia was defending originalism, he would readily concede that originalism wasn’t perfect. It created all kinds of problems. It required judges to be more or less amateur historians. It required reading into a vague historical record. It produced policy results that might seem unpalatable to modern ears, etc.

But he said the question of what kind of methodology to adopt was not whether originalism was perfect but whether it was better than the others. And as long as, in his view, originalism beat the alternative, well, that was the way to go. And it kind of reminds me of my father’s parenting philosophy, which made quite clear to my brother and me that any kind of complaint about the way things were was likely to result in an outcome that was worse than what we were complaining about.

And so I want to focus your attention on the panel description, which asks what it means to have a fair election process and how much deference judges should pay to the determinations of officials whose actions in formulating and applying election laws may have partisan motivations.

Now, it’s quite clear that deference to political officials who make political decisions seemingly for political reasons presents substantial dangers for the electoral process and for the judicial process as a whole. So it seems like the answer should be intuitively obvious. To what extent should we defer to these people in making political decisions when we’re on the courts? Well, obviously, not at all, right? Well, maybe.

Let me give you some reasons for a pause, that is, before we criticize the actions of the political officials and think that judges can do better, let’s make sure that judges can do better. And if we’re not sure, then as imperfect as it is, maybe having these kinds of decisions made by political officials, maybe that’s the best we can do or at least tolerable.

Now, I want to begin by letting you remember constitutional law in law school. When you learned the rational basis test and you studied cases like Williamson v. Lee Optical or Railway Express v. New York or Carolene Products or whatever, you learned that there’s a very strong principle of deference that courts will apply to certain kinds of political decisions or decisions by political actors.

The reason for that was not always—or maybe even usually—that the political actors would come out with the right decision. Instead, it was a question of institutional competence. It was, “If we, the judges, decide this question instead [inaudible 00:08:11] to do any better. Maybe we’ll do worse.” But even if the quality of the judicial choice is acceptable, the biggest problem with having judges decide these kinds of political questions is that it risks undermining the support for the judiciary by saying the judges are going to make determinations on the basis of their own political philosophies.

It’s one thing for the public to look at members of the legislature, members of the executive branch—even some secretaries of state—and say, “Oh, well, there are political consequences of your decisions. And maybe I’m a little suspicious about the reason why you’re choosing to affect this policy over this other one. Maybe you’re really doing it to advantage the political party that you favor.”

Well, big deal. Who cares if the legislature is -- members of the legislature are believed to be acting for political reasons. We all know that they’re acting for political reasons. That’s not anything that’s going to undermine the American electoral process or our faith in the system. On the other hand, if judges are believed to be acting for political reasons, then that is a substantial threat to the public’s esteem for the judiciary.

Now, I don’t favor deference to political actors for every kind of decision. Justice Frankfurter famously said in his dissent in Baker v. Carr, “There is not under our Constitution a judicial remedy for every political mischief.” And that’s right. But it doesn’t mean that under our Constitution, there is no judicial remedy for any political mischief.

I certainly believe that judges should act strenuously to defend the Constitution, to defend constitutional rights that are explicit in the Constitution. However, the difference between the kinds of situations where judges are likely to get into trouble and those where they are not is the specificity with which the judges are applying rules, the specificity of the rules that the judges are applying.

If the courts can point to specific rules—that is, ones that are judicially discernible in the Constitution and manageable according to the judicial process—if the courts can point to those kinds of standards, then they’re likely to be on solid ground. It is most problematic when the courts can rely on nothing other than their sense of fairness. If the choice in a decision comes down to the judge’s view of political fairness versus the politician’s view of political fairness, then I don’t think that there’s enough justification for the judges to get involved.

And very briefly—I know I don’t have much time left—but I’ll wrap it up with three recent cases by the U.S. Supreme Court that I think demonstrate this potential problem. A few years ago, in Rucho v. Common Cause, the Supreme Court decided that there were no judicially manageable standards for deciding partisan gerrymandering cases. And it seemed like the Supreme Court viewed its entry into election law as governed by that kind of restraint, if you want to call it that. “We won’t get involved unless we have a judicially discoverable and manageable standard for resolving a controversy.”

Yet this past term, the Supreme Court decided two election cases where it not only allowed for a standard that was not judicially manageable, but the Court went out of its way to create an unmanageable standard and not even resolve what it was. The two cases are Moore v. Harper, the independent state legislature theory case, and Allen v. Milligan, a voting rights case out of Alabama. We don’t have enough time to get into the details of what they are—the Milligan case—so I’ll describe them only briefly.

The Milligan case involved the creation of a second majority minority district in Alabama, and the question was when that would be required. The Court said, “Well, you don’t have to give minorities proportional representation, but if you can give them proportional representation without undermining the compactness of districts, then for all intents and purposes, you have to.” Well, the Court gave us no measure of compactness, didn’t tell us how much compactness was necessary or good. It created this standard without giving us much of an indication as to how to apply it in the future.

And in Moore v. Harper, the Court said that, in general, the state supreme courts can exercise judicial review over decisions of state legislatures, that is, the state legislatures don’t have the unreviewable authority to determine the times, places, and manner of congressional elections. But if the state courts go too far, if they go beyond exercising ordinary judicial review, the Court said, then the state courts will have usurped the legislature’s authority and will have violated the U.S. Constitution.

As to what “ordinary judicial review” meant, the Court acknowledged that it was a vague concept, wasn’t resolving what it meant, didn’t even decide on a standard. It sort of suggested, “Here are three possibilities for a standard, but we don’t need to resolve it now.” And so everybody in the academy and elsewhere are left to figure out what it means.

Now, when the Court comes back to that decision, it’s, of course, going to be in the middle of a hotly contested election. Perhaps the outcome is going to determine -- going to depend on which standard the Court applies, and the Court is going to be right back into being attacked for choosing winners, just like it was attacked during Bush v. Gore. If you don’t want the Court to be perceived as a political institution, then don’t make decisions based on your own view of political theory. Thanks very much.

[Applause]

Hon. Michael G. Adams:  Good afternoon. Thank you. Is this on?

Hon. Thomas M. Hardiman: It should be.

Hon. Michael G. Adams:  Good? Oh, good. Thank you. Good afternoon. Thank you, Federalist Society, for this invitation. And thank you, Kentucky voters, for sparing me a statewide recount this week so I could be here today. [Laughter]

I’d like to give you my take on what it’s like to be a state’s chief election official in these times. My assessment is relatively less scholarly, but I’ll try to compensate by giving you a sense of what it’s like to be in this job and some lessons I’ve learned that I’d like others to learn.

When I first ran for secretary of state four years ago, my biggest challenge was explaining to voters what the office even did. I don’t have that problem anymore, nor do I think my colleagues in other states do. Because of 2020 and its wake, this office is far more prominent. I think that’s a good thing. This office is important, and more scrutiny means more voter awareness and more public accountability.

Another difference is now candidates for this office are less likely to be non-ideological bureaucrats, like county clerks, and more likely to be ideologues like me. [Laughter] I’ve practiced election law for Republican candidates and causes for 20 years, and I’m the first secretary of state candidate in my state’s history to have run on a policy platform, photo ID to vote, post-election audits, cleaning up the voter rolls, and so forth.

In Michigan and Colorado, the secretaries of state are young progressive activists who ran ideological campaigns about voting rights. I like the fact that voters now have clear choices in these races, but the cost of that is that there is some tension among us, and the National Association of Secretaries of State risks looking like the U.S. House of Representatives.

Let me turn here to a point about ideology. I’m a red-blooded conservative, and this is not my first FedSoc conference. I was elected on photo ID, and I pushed it through our legislature in the spring of 2020 at the zenith of COVID panic at a time government offices weren’t even open. I did that to keep my campaign promise but also to hold my base together while I innovated with voting methods during the pandemic.

Most of the problems I face of doing my job, though, are practical, not ideological. It’s getting harder to get poll workers, partly because of the mistreatment they now get, but mostly because there’s been a decline in volunteering generally. It’s harder to get voting locations, too, partly because of the controversy around voting, partly because the Biden administration has recklessly stepped up enforcement of the Americans with Disabilities Act against county election officials who are trying in good faith to offer as many voting locations as they can.

Many of the thousands of buildings we use were built before 1990. They don’t have ramps, or they have parking lots across a gravel road, etc. This administration, rather than working with us in good faith to find alternative locations, has compelled that we simply close locations. In my state at least, it is not conservatives who are engaged in voter suppression. To address the appropriate level of deference, courts should give people like me, instinctively, I would say a lot, but I’ll try to be objective.

I get sued every day and twice on Sunday. Outside a presidential election, most of these lawsuits are bona fide challenges over candidate residency, qualifications, use of name on the ballot, and so forth. Presidential years are different. In the Trump and Dobbs era, the left has unlimited cash. They can and do throw teams of expensive lawyers at me and my state, even though we haven’t voted for a Democrat in a statewide federal race in this millennium.

It’s self-serving to say judges should butt out and let me do my job, but I think that’s generally right so long as I’m following the law. One, judges are not subject matter experts in election administration. They’re jacks of all trades and masters of none, as they should be. Two, I’m directly accountable to the electorate for my performance in a way that judges are not. Three, I think it hurts public confidence in the elections to have judges make up election rules on the fly rather than follow the normal process that separation of powers would dictate.

Judges should not hesitate to smack the hands of election officials who stray from their oath to follow the law, but they should hesitate to start making the law themselves. I personally think that judicial activism did more in 2020 to undercut public faith in our elections than dropbox mules or 3:00 a.m. ballot dumps ever did.

A final point. Kentucky has shown—as we’ve expanded voting days from one to four during my tenure but also stepped up voter ID and purged hundreds of thousands of people off our voter rolls who had moved away or passed away or been put away—we’ve proved that you can have access and integrity at the same time. I encourage conservatives to never go wobbly on election integrity, but you can make it easier to vote while you make it harder to cheat. It’s the right thing to do, and you avoid feeding into the left’s fallacious argument that we are trying to rig the results. Thank you.

[Applause]

Prof. Richard Briffault:  Great. Thank you. This is my first visit to The Federalist Society, so I’m not quite Daniel in the lions’ den, but I am interested to see how this goes. But I’m delighted that I have several former students here, starting with Eric, who began and then also goes to Brett. So I’ve got several generations of students here, which has been a pleasant discovery.

I guess you’ve now heard a little bit of perspective about the court's role and administrator’s role. My comments are going to focus mostly on developments in state election law, on the conflicting partisan perspectives they provide on our election system and its problems. Recent years have witnessed frequent changes in state election law. This dates back to the 2000s but accelerated dramatically after the 2020 election. 2021 witnessed more changes in election laws, laws dealing with election administration, voter registration, and the balloting and tabulation processes than any year in recent history, with 2023 being a close second.

Many of these changes reflect what different partisan and ideological groups determined were the lessons of the 2020 and 2022 elections. It’s tempting to say the “tale of two states”—the tale of two sets of states. Our state laws are -- Kentucky, I think, is a counterexample, but are moving in different directions.

In the so-called “blue states,” legislatures have acted to make registration and voting easier. Twenty-four states now offer automatic voter registration. Twenty-two of those states went for Biden in 2020. Twenty-one states now have some form of same-day or election-day registration. The partisan divide is less sharp for these. Only 15 went for Biden, but some of the 6 red states that have same day registration have recently begun to adopt measures making it less available.

Blue states have also liberalized voter ID requirements, enabling more kinds of ID to count. Building on the dramatically increased level of early in-person voting and mail-in voting during the pandemic, blue states have increased the availability of both. More states now authorize no-excuse absentee voting on a permanent basis where it existed only in 2020 on an emergency basis or facilitate it where it previously existed, such as by giving voters more time to request and return mail ballots and expanding the availability of dropboxes.

Similarly, responding to the incidents of harassment, stalking, vandalism, and threats against election workers in the aftermath of the 2020 election and again in 2022, 11 states—10 blue—have adopted new protections for election workers, including the privacy of their personal information.

Red states—and I’m obviously using these as generalizations—as revealed by the laws that they have been adopting see the lessons of 2020 and 2022 and the problems of election administration differently. Red states have been shortening early voting periods, imposing stricter voter ID requirements—both for in-person voting and vote by mail—shortening the period. Not all red states are doing everything, but these are common patterns.

Shortening the period to request mail ballots, barring election workers from sending unsolicited absentee ballot applications or ballots moving up the return date for mail ballots, imposing new requirements and penalties on voter registration organizations, expanding the access and observation rights of poll watchers—it’s obviously important to distinguish between poll workers and poll watchers—and opposing new requirements often backed up with criminal penalties on election workers, including penalties for mistakes, further underscoring the distrust of local election administration. Ten states with Republican trifecta governments have increased the ability of state administrative takeovers of local elections offices.

I think the two clearest differences or directions in which I think red states are going deal with the acceptance of private or philanthropic contributions and the regulation of dropboxes. Maybe the clearest response to 2020 that over the past 3 years, none of these states had rules on this before. Twenty-five states, including only four that voted for Biden—and two of those have Republican trifecta governments—have passed constitutional amendments or laws banning or tightly limiting the solicitation, acceptance, or use of private or philanthropic support for election operations.

This is obviously a reaction to the grants from the Zuckerberg Chan Center for—Center for Tech and Civic Life—which provided tens of thousands of -- millions of dollars, actually, to local elections offices to handle the unanticipated expenses due to COVID-19, for PPE, and cleaning supplies in bigger places and, obviously, handling the surge in mail ballots. Local elections offices are chronically underfunded. Taking away funding without providing funding is a recipe for difficulties on Election Day.

That same COVID-driven surge in vote by mail has triggered a move by many red states to require photocopies of ID, notary signatures with ballot applications. But most strikingly is the move to ban dropboxes. Twelve states now ban them—eleven states require -- eleven states that were carried by Trump—and the twelfth, Wisconsin, was due to a state court decision. And five more states now tightly restrict their use, such as having one dropbox per county regardless of the population of the county.

It’s kind of funny as a matter of ballot security. This is somewhat ironic given that dropboxes can actually be monitored and provided with anti-tampering devices and secure pickups more effectively than ordinary postal boxes. And indeed, voters seem preferred dropboxes to ordinary mailboxes.

Perhaps the most striking development has not come into law but thus is an initiative that’s being pushed by county governments and individual legislatures, which is the call for hand counting of ballots. This has come up. This has triggered direct conflicts between state and local officials in Arizona. In Nevada, there’s been a call for it, in New Hampshire, and very recently currently really in California, where the state just banned hand counting of ballots and elections in any community with more than 1,000 registered voters. Shasta County, which has about 100,000 people, canceled this contract for voting machinery and wants to use the hand count.

Obviously, there’s a deep distrust of the election machinery out there that’s triggering this. But the implausibility, if not the impossibility, of hand counting ballots in any sizable jurisdiction was demonstrated by a test run by Mohave County, Arizona, where it took 7 part-time and 4 full-time election workers 3 8 hour days to count just 850 ballots, and they made 46 errors. So I know they’re interesting. The call for hand counting is really quite strong out there, but it does seem to be an unwise move. What people don’t realize is that most ballots have multiple votes. So the 850 ballots in Mohave County had actually more than 30,000 votes, given the multiple number of offices that are running.

Another area where there’s been a partisan divide seems to me is to have much less of a partisan valence but nonetheless is striking, and that is rules dealing with ranked-choice voting. That, to me, has no inherent partisan valence. It was used statewide in red Alaska and by many local governments in red Utah. But perhaps because it led to the election of a moderate Republican and a Democrat in Alaska, the expansion of ranked-choice voting has occurred only in blue states with five states—all red—adopting laws just in the last two years, 2022 and 2023, prohibiting rank-choice voting in state or local elections. So I think what you do see is obviously these different patterns.

Final thought. Whatever the ideology underlying particular law -- election law changes, the proliferation of new rules and requirements is itself a burden, I think, to our 8,000 or more overworked, underfunded, and frequently embattled local election offices. I think election workers are the essential workers of the political system. I like to think of Secretary Adams as the chief of surgery in the ER of our election system, but we also have to think about the lower level workers as well.

Recent years have witnessed, as he already alluded to, a high level of turnover in local elections offices and the departure through retirement, resignation, or removal of many senior local election officials. That itself is likely to lead to more mistakes and conflicts in the electoral system, which in turn will undermine public faith in the electoral system and will no doubt lead to further election law changes that local officials will have to deal with.

[Applause]

Hon. Bradley A. Smith:  Okay. Well, thank you all for coming. Thank you, Judge Hardiman, and thanks for my fellow panelists and, as always, to The Federalist Society.

So, in recent years, we’ve seen a large and apparently growing percentage of Americans who are simply unwilling to accept that an election lost by their preferred candidates was an honest result. I don’t mean here people who believe that the election wasn’t fair in the sense that the media was one sided or that one candidate was able to spend far more money than the other, but rather -- and agree many people note such facts. But I mean people who specifically believe that the campaign was not merely unfair but that the announced results were fraudulent: the result of fraudulent voting, fraudulent machines, or fraudulent officials in some way.

Because of the widespread belief among Republican voters that the 2020 election was fraudulent and the ongoing high visibility of Donald Trump in making that claim, there’s been a rise in the belief in intellectual and academic circles that this is a uniquely Republican/conservative problem.

In fact, I want to emphasize that this is a bipartisan problem. For example, in 2018, a Gallup poll found that 78 percent of Democrats believe that Trump stole the 2016 election with Russian assistance. And this is a higher total of election deniers than I have ever seen in any poll of Republicans based on the 2020 election.

Even today, 7 years after the 2016 election, without so prominent a figure as Mr. Trump constantly banging the drum of fraud and with the balm of holding presidential power, polls regularly find that over 50 percent of Democrats still believe that Trump did not win the 2016 election. Overall, roughly two-thirds of Americans—possibly as many as three quarters—now seem to believe that in at least one of the last two elections, the winner was cheated out of victory through some type of fraud.

Now, my point here is not to really say who is worse or what is worse or how people reacted or what they’re saying publicly or who had what evidence on their side. It’s simply to emphasize that the issue here is bipartisan. I don’t believe that democracy can continue long if large segments of our population simply do not accept announced election results as honest.

Now, briefly, on the political right, the typical cry has been fraud, while on the left, it’s vote suppression. These beliefs, in my view, are both almost entirely disconnected from the facts. By almost any standard, fraud in American elections is relatively trivial and less common than it has been throughout much of our history. And contrary to claims of suppression, there have never been fewer obstacles to voting in the United States.

I don’t suggest that there’s no fraud. It occurs. It’s a big country. We’ve got a voting age population of about 250 million or more. Roughly 160 million people vote at some 130,000 polling locations staffed by about three quarters of a million of part time and volunteer workers. Of course, there is going to be some fraud. Similarly, it would be surprising if there was not some episodes of suppression—however one defines that term. But both fraud and suppression are extremely rare in modern America.

The Heritage Foundation voter fraud database, for example, contains about 1,500 incidents of proven fraud since 2004. If we assume that for each of these confirmed instances, there are 20,000 incidents that have not been detected or otherwise are not included in the database, then we’re left with a figure suggesting that fraud accounts to somewhere under -- something under one-tenth of 1 percent of all ballots cast in that time.

As to alleged vote suppression, it’s simply obvious that voting has never been easier in the United States. No state had absentee -- no-fault absentee voting until it was adopted by California in the 1970s. Today, 35 states in the district do. The first state to adopt early in person voting was Texas in the 1980s.

Today, 46 states use it. Dropboxes and provisional votings are both post-1990 creations. The Voting Rights Act dates all the way back to -- the Voting Rights Act of 1965 dates all the way back to 1965. The Motor Vehicle Act of 1992, the Help America Vote Act of 2002 both made voter registration easier. Many states have liberalized their laws in other ways, and we don’t even think of other laws that deal with voting because we don’t think of them as voting laws, such as the Americans with Disabilities Act, which included provisions to enable make sure that people with disabilities would be able to vote, and so on.

So why is there this incredible lack of confidence in the electoral process? I think a major problem is the constant tinkering with the process and the regular changes that are made. One reason isolated incidents of fraud are so readily extrapolated by so many voters into believing that fraud is widespread or that on the other side suppression is widespread is that a lack of confidence in the fairness of the process often collapses into a lack of confidence in the honesty of the results determined under that process. And the fairness of the process, in turn, is brought into question when laws are continually in flux or challenged in litigation.

Almost all the changes in the voting laws, even if defensible on their specific merits at that moment, have the potentially partisan political consequences. And these consequences are often known in advance or at least suspected in advance, and such partisanship is rarely out of the mind of legislators, executive officials, and even judges. This is not lost on voters, and late changes to the law in particular breeds suspicion, and I think this makes people ready to assume the worst about election shenanigans.

I see these breaking down in three types, very broadly speaking. One, of course, is -- well, maybe I should say four. One is legislative changes that seem to have a clear partisan edge. But, to me, of greater concern are executive changes that are made late. These can be executive changes made by county election officials who decide to accept ballots that they previously had not accepted or who decide to defy state law and say, “We’re going to send back absentee ballots that aren’t -- don’t seem to have the right information on the outside envelope so that the voters can correct them when there’s no provision in state law to do this.” And so some jurisdictions do it and some don’t. And that can have a partisan effect depending on the jurisdictions doing it.

You have state officials, such as Michigan Secretary of State, taking it upon her to use COVID to flood the place with ballots, to send ballots to people who had not requested them and a number of things that, at a minimum, I would hope all would agree are a stretch to the language of the statute, if not clearly contrary to the statute. But we also see this in what I consider to be rash decisions by judges in 2020, for example. The Pennsylvania Supreme Court just rewrote the statute repeatedly.

And the argument in all of these cases is often made that people are not going to be able to vote if we don’t make these changes. But when you’re just changing the statute at the last minute, it’s naturally going to raise people’s suspicions about things.

A final category I would raise is one that comes a little more deep, but I’ll just touch on it briefly, and that goes to redistricting under the Voting Rights Act and in particular the mixture between party and race. We know that African Americans tend to vote in very overwhelming numbers for Democratic Party candidates. The Supreme Court has for many years interpreted the Voting Rights Act in a way that at least Justice Clarence Thomas and some others on the courts have felt is not at all intuitive to include redistricting and to guarantee that redistricting serves certain seats for majority minority districts. And those districts will almost inherently be there for Democratic districts. But parties are allowed to gerrymander districts for party advantage.

The end result of this is that one party is allowed to make certain types of redistricting changes that the other party is not. The other party is not because if they gerrymander for partisan advantage when they hold control of things, then it has the potential to affect the existence of these majority/minority districts, and thus, you have an asymmetry in what the parties can do in attempting to manipulate the districting process. I don’t think that we can have that go on for very long and have people be content with that.

Generally speaking, I would just close by saying I believe that judges should be extremely careful about viewing voting behavior through the lens of any individual voter considering the minuscule chance that one or a few votes will determine an election. One of the most damning things I have seen to voter confidence is when judges make decisions on Election Day to hold polls open, even though there have been no allegations of fraud or anything. It’s just, “Oh, there’s long lines or something.” This leads people to tremendous amounts of suspicion that I think is problematic. I think judges need to be careful to give adequate weight not just to that right of individual voters but to the societal interest in orderly and easily understood voting processes.

And with that, I guess I would say that I think if we look at voting purely as a matter of individual rights in the same way we look at free speech or the same way we look at the freedom of religion or the right to be armed or a number of things like that, it simply doesn’t add up. Voting takes place only within a government, organized, and regulated system of elections. And I believe that our judges and our elected executive officials need to pay more attention to the idea of voting as a communal activity in which we govern ourselves and that that’s the real impact and the importance of voting in the United States.

[Applause]

Prof. Richard H. Pildes:  Well, I too want to thank The Federalist Society for this invitation. I know you guys like debate and conflict, and I will say I have many things I disagree with in Brad’s recent remarks. But I’m going to go ahead and talk about what I was asked to talk about first, and maybe in the discussion we can have some of that disagreement played out.

So I was asked to talk about my concerns about the 2024 elections, and I want to start by mentioning two background elements about current American political culture that shape the specific concerns I have about the stability and acceptance of the 2024 election process and its outcome.

First, politics has come to be seen as existential by many people on both sides of the divide. And when politics becomes existential, people believe the country will never be the same if the other side wins. And about 70 percent of Republicans and Democrats said that essentially in a recent poll I looked at.

And I’m not here to say they’re wrong, but that perception runs into the democratic kind of basic principle that losers accept their losses because of the idea of rotation in office. “I can accept losing today because I can win next time around. I can change policy down the road.” When politics becomes existential, that idea kind of collapses, or, as I said, comes under tremendous pressure.

I can’t be satisfied by the idea “my side can win next time around” when I believe that victory by the other side will be catastrophic in changing the country in irreversible ways. And once people believe politics has become existential, they become more willing to justify to themselves and in public any means or other means that they would not normally justify that ensure the right outcome.

I find this shocking if it’s true. But again, looking at recent polling data, 25 percent of Americans say they believe, “Political violence may be necessary to save our country”—a much higher number than you saw in previous studies. So that’s the first kind of big idea about the nature of politics now.

The second, which has been alluded to a bit, is that elections now take place in a context of pervasive institutional distrust. All institutions have been pulled into the vortex of this hyperpolarized existential kind of political culture. There’s distrust of state legislatures when they enact voting policies on party line votes, as they almost always do, no matter which policies they’re enacting—more restrictive or more expansive. There’s distrust of high level election administrators, such as secretaries of state, many of whom are elected on partisan tickets. And as Secretary Adam said, “I’m an ideologue, and so are some of my cohorts.”

No other country, by the way, elects its top election administrators. I think this is a bad institutional design in the United States. I think we need independent election administration, but it’s very hard to move in that direction. There’s distrust of state supreme courts—many of them elected in increasingly partisan elections with tremendous amounts of spending. And we know there’s distrust of the Supreme Court, at least among independents and Democrats, who give it the lowest approval ratings that Gallup has ever measured.

So we’re in a context in which there’s really no institution that commands the kind of broad legitimacy that would allow contested election issues to be resolved in a way that would be widely accepted.

So with those broad considerations in mind, let me turn to some of the more specific things I’m worried about for 2024. One is that because of all these changes in laws that have taken place since 2020, election administrators are going to be functioning under much greater legal uncertainty than would have been true about 10 years ago or so. It’s already the case that many, many states—whether 2021, 2023, as Richard mentioned—have changed their laws, some more restrictive, some more expansive. And in the absence of settled practices about what these laws mean, we’re going to be having novel interpretations and litigation about these various laws.

The second is many election officials are going to be running elections for the first time because since 2020, about a quarter to a third of our election officials throughout the country have quit because it has become a very unpleasant task. Some of them are subjected to death threats; their families are threatened, harassment online. Some states have enacted new laws to criminalize aspects of election administration, and it’s become a miserable job in many critical states to do. And mistakes, even good-faith mistakes, are going to be perceived as motivated by partisan considerations.

And in addition, as Secretary of State Adams said, many more partisan activists have run for these lower-level positions than in the past. And we actually do have, not at the highest levels of the system, but at county levels and lower levels, people who have denied the legitimacy of the 2020 election who are now in positions to administer elections at the county and local level.

We’ve already seen local officials in North Carolina, Arizona, Nevada, Pennsylvania, New Mexico in 2022 who refused to certify election results based on groundless speculations of their own about something being wrong with the system. State courts in New Mexico, for example, had a mandamus accounting to certify. Even when they did that, the vote was still only 2-1 to certify. And I worry that we’re going to see more of this from the inside of the system now, not from the outside, but from within in 2024.

Third, the social media environment is going to be much worse in 2024 than it was in 2020. The platforms are going to do far less to address election-related disinformation, like when you vote, what day you vote, conditions on, whether you have to, whether there’ll be immigration officials at the polls and the like. At X—formerly known as Twitter—Elon Musk has basically gotten rid of the people who did election disinformation or other kinds.

[Applause]

Prof. Richard H. Pildes:  Moreover, as that reaction indicates, the whole issue of content moderation itself has become swept into the dynamics of partisan politics, partly due to some real mistakes that platforms made, partly due to perceptions of bias that might or might not be accurate. So you see the laws in Texas and Florida that have been enacted now that the Supreme Court’s going to look at this term.

And as a result of how politicized the whole issue of content moderation has become, you’re going to have a flood of misinformation about the election process that is going to be sort of widely propagated without any kind of moderation. When people are predisposed towards distrust as they are and social media is flooding the information environment with misinformation about what’s happening, how are election officials, like Michael Adams, going to be able to counter that with accurate information that reaches a large audience in real time? And I think this toxic mix is really dangerous for 2024.

Now, I have a few suggestions that might mitigate a bit, but there are no great solutions to this toxic dynamic we’re in. One is we do need clear rules specified in advance for the election. And I think courts have an important role to play here. And in particular, I think federal courts sometimes make a mistake of relying too heavily on doctrines like rightness and mootness and the like to avoid deciding election issues until the very last minute, which is the worst possible time actually to decide the issues.

So I think the U.S. Supreme Court was right in Moore v. Harper to find a way around the mootness of that case, and I think they had to strain some to do it in order to give us a clear resolution about the independent state legislature doctrine, which the system needed well in advance of 2024. So I applaud the Court for finding a way around the mootness issues in that case.

We need to get accurate results more quickly in the election process. It’s, I think, a travesty that there are states that don’t allow their election officials to process absentee ballots before the polls close on election night. Pennsylvania is the worst about this, but there are other states that are pretty bad.

Hon. Thomas M. Hardiman:  Why are you pointing at me?

[Laughter]

Prof. Richard H. Pildes:  I’m trying to respect and honor those of you from Pennsylvania. [Laughter] We knew in advance of 2020 this was going to be a disaster, and it was impossible to get the legislatures in Wisconsin or Michigan or Pennsylvania to make this change. This doesn’t mean counting the ballots. It just means getting them ready so that they can be instantly counted when polls close.

I think we need more consistency and statewide policies on elections. We have, as Richard said, an incredibly decentralized system. Over 8,000 jurisdictions administer elections. We’ve lived with a lot of differences across counties in an age in which there was less distrust. I think where there’s this level of distrust, to the extent secretaries of state or other officials can bring somewhat more consistency to policies across the state, that’s a good thing. Now, there are real local differences, and sometimes, those have to be respected, but I think we need to think harder about which ones to accept.

Finally, I would like to see us encourage people to vote in person. I wrote in the run up to 2020, CNN -- [applause] okay. Let me just say. I wonder why I keep getting invited back to The Federalist. I feel like I must be doing something wrong.

[Laughter]

Prof. Richard H. Pildes:  In the run up to 2020, CNN titled this piece Three Words to Avoid Election an Election Meltdown, which was vote in person. There’s nothing wrong with absentee voting. I support absentee voting. I support no-excuse absentee voting. But we know that voters make many more mistakes on absentee ballots. We know that they are a source of controversy.

We get into these fights about if the date was left off the ballot envelope, should it be counted or not, does the signature match? There’s more complexity and suspicion and distrust and manipulation can prey on that greater complexity, and it can also slow down the counting process.

So I think, in the pandemic, it made perfectly good sense we were going to have this level of absentee voting. It won’t be anywhere near as high as it was in 2020, but it will be higher than it was in the world before 2020. But I do think voting in person reduces a lot of the issues that create potential controversy and problems. Anyway, let me stop there so I can take on Brad in the discussion.

[Applause]

Hon. Thomas M. Hardiman:  Thank you for those terrific presentations. Professor Pildes, there is good news from Allegheny County, Pennsylvania. We had an election on Tuesday, and there were about 100,000 mail-in ballots, and the polls closed at 8:00. And by about 8:15 or so, they were pretty much all counted. So that was quite a different situation from what we saw in the presidential election of 2020.

If you go to the Allegheny County website, you will see what must have been a tortured effort by the poor folks that were laboring in the elections office to report over and over again every day exactly what was happening. But there seems to be improvement at least in one of the 67 counties of Pennsylvania. I can’t speak for Harrisburg. Was it the same there?

Prof. Michael R. Dimino:  I do not have the same level of confidence, to be honest, there.

[Laughter]

Hon. Thomas M. Hardiman:  Okay.

Prof. Richard Briffault:  Luzerne is the one with a lot of issues.

Hon. Thomas M. Hardiman:  Luzerne, yeah. And also, I apologize to Professor Pildes. I should have warned you that you were walking into an audience full of people that have probably spent large portions of their recreational time reading the Twitter files.

[Laughter]

Prof. Richard H. Pildes:  That’s why I come to these events. You learn things about how different people perceive the world.

Hon. Thomas M. Hardiman:  Well, since you said you wanted to give a rejoinder to Professor Smith, why don’t I let you start and then we’ll work backwards. Go ahead, Rick.

Prof. Richard H. Pildes:  Well, at a general level, I mean, I think a lot of Brad’s concerns about changes at the last minute and the like come out of the pandemic election. I mean, this is not a general phenomenon. And I think under the conditions of the pandemic, I know there’s lots of dispute about some of this.

But I think that, actually, the election administrators did a tremendous job under tremendous stress where they had to both be prepared for the level of absentee voting going from like 5 percent to 50 percent, as it did in some states, and also make the in-person polling places safe. And there were a lot of adjustments on the ground. I agree.

Now, none of those led to people who were not eligible to vote voting. It expanded the opportunity, under the conditions of the pandemic, for people who are otherwise eligible to vote. So allowing drive-up voting, for example, keeping polls open later—and that’s just one of the things I wanted to respond to with Brad.

Courts have issued orders keeping polling places open past poll closing time forever. I mean, I’ve been involved in doing election-related work for 30 some years. This is a very standard thing. If there are reasons that, for example, the polls opened an hour and a half late because there’s some sort of problem, you go to court. You get a court order that extends voting for an hour and a half. If people are in line at the time of poll closing, they’re entitled to vote. That’s a clearly established law. So I was really puzzled by Brad’s concern about courts extending polling hours under these circumstances, which is a very common practice.

The Michigan Secretary of State, as I understand it, did not send out absentee ballots to everybody. She sent out absentee ballot applications, which people had to return in order to get an absentee ballot and to vote absentee, for what it’s worth.

On the redistricting, you mentioned Justice Thomas’s view that the Voting Rights Act might not cover redistricting. There are things I like about Justice Thomas, I want to say, so I don’t mean this as -- but this view that the Voting Rights Act doesn’t apply to redistricting is completely, wildly implausible.

The entire reason Congress amended the Voting Rights Act in 1982 was to deal with redistricting. You might dislike what they did, but there’s zero doubt that the 1982 amendments to the Voting Rights Act were meant to apply to redistricting. And I’ve actually argued that there should be limits on both partisan and racial redistricting. So that’s one direction to go from your comments.

But to say one side benefits from the Voting Rights Act because in the face of racially polarized voting, Congress has decided there has to be an equal opportunity to let candidates of choice—and that’s unfair in partisan terms—I mean, it’s not an argument I’ve heard before. I guess I can kind of understand where that’s coming from. But it is to deny the basic reason that the Voting Rights Act was enacted, which is to deal with racially polarized voting in context where minorities, being minorities, are systematically unable to elect their candidates of choice because in a state like Alabama, they will never get elected from or rarely get elected from majority white election districts, despite being 27 some percent of the voting age population. So anyway, I don’t know.

Hon. Thomas M. Hardiman:  Let’s give Brad a chance to respond.

Prof. Richard H. Pildes:  Yeah, sorry.

Hon. Bradley A. Smith:  Well, okay. So let me say first, I’m not sure that there’s some of the disagreements that Richard thinks there are. I mean, he’s quite right that, for example, courts have long held polls open. But as Richard said, if polls don’t open on time, right? And one of the things I mentioned was, sometimes, they’re doing it for no reason other than there are long lines.

But as Richard pointed out, if you’re in line at closing time, you can vote. You may have to wait a while, but you can vote. And I think of other decisions that are made really simply because it’s held that there are long lines and, therefore, maybe people were discouraged, so we’ll hold the polls open.

The extreme example of this was a case from Ohio a few years ago where a judge was out at a dinner much like this—only they were eating—and her clerk informed her that she’d -- they had gotten a call from somebody knowing that there’d been a serious accident on the interstate north of Cincinnati. And this was making it hard for people to get to vote before the polls closed. And so she ordered that the polls be held open from the dinner table, put out an order ordering that the polls be held open longer.

The Court of Appeals did eventually overturn this decision after the election, had some mootness problems. Of course, you don’t get to it after the election, or you don’t get to it on Election Day, right? What’s the law of Election Day? It’s what you can find some judge somewhere to issue a decision on because there ain’t going to be time for no appeal. And that was the case here. So this federal judge orders the polls open.

And when it got to the Court of Appeals, Judge Sutton, in a wonderful opinion, he begins by saying, “I don’t even know what to call this case.” And to be honest, I don’t remember what the name of it is because they did finally call it something like In re 2018 Election or something like that because it was. It was kind of like you can’t -- I mean, again, this is an extreme case. This isn’t going to be the norm, but it’s illustrative of a direction you can go.

You can’t have—you can tell me otherwise—but I don’t think you can have a judge say -- get a call without a complaint, without a plaintiff even, and just say, “Well, gee. People are calling and saying there was a big accident”—which there was—“so we’re going to hold the polls open. And I have seen that kind of thing for my entire life, not that extreme, but pretty bad. As Richard said, “All our lives we’ve seen this,” and I think this all our lives has contributed to decline in confidence in elections.

Similarly, when we talk about the Voting Rights Act -- and I sort of misspoke here, so I’m to blame for this but partly is the incredible time pressure and so on. But, I mean, it is true. The Voting Rights Act pretty clearly was amended in 1982 with an intent to make sure it applied to redistricting. Justice Thomas’s arguments has been that that essentially should be viewed as, I think, unconstitutional, and that it was also erroneous by the Supreme Court prior to that statutory change to have interpreted that way.

However it comes about, whether it’s statute or judicial, I don’t think it is sustainable to have a system in which we say one party can gerrymander, and the other cannot. And the other cannot because when it gerrymanders to boost its electoral prospects, by definition, it is going to lower the electoral prospects of minority voters simply because those minority voters overwhelmingly vote for the opposition party.

And this is done increasingly now when there’s not that sort of evidence of polarized voting, or if the polarized voting is there, it comes much more from the minority groups which are voting overwhelmingly for one party. This is a thorny issue, this mixture of partisanship and race. But I just don’t think it’s sustainable to have that kind of system where one party can justify its gerrymandering and the other party cannot because it’s deemed to be not partisan but racial when, in fact, they’re sort of the same thing. So those would be a couple of key things.

And then, if I can real quickly, I just want to say I want to totally endorse Rick’s endorsement of Election Day voting. I think this would be a marvelous help. I think it’s good for a lot of reasons, that that should be the norm. I don’t want to totally do away with absentee voting. I don’t want to totally do away with early voting. I would like to trim those back and reestablish a norm that people vote on Election Day.

It’s good. It is a good thing to have to stand in line for a few minutes with your neighbors and fellow voters and other people and see that they’re voting too, and they don’t really look like that bad a guy, as Rick says. I think the Armageddon problem is a real one, and it’s good for us to see that and kind of say “yeah” and to realize that the purpose of voting is not to sit in my kitchen table and think, “How can I get the absolute most out of this election?” but rather to sit with our neighbors and stuff and think, “What’s the best way to get good policy for our body politic, for our polity?” And I think in-day voting does that.

It’s also been shown to be one of the few things, as Rick pointed out, absentee ballots are less likely to be counted. They’re more likely to be fraudulent. I don’t think either is a huge problem, but that’s the reality of it. But also, I think we want people to think about voting as sort of something that we do together to govern ourselves, and we’re not just sitting at our kitchen table trying to think of how much we can get from it.

[CROSSTALK]

Hon. Thomas M. Hardiman:  All right. I’ll give Rick a brief rebuttal, then we’re going to turn to our other panelists.

Prof. Richard H. Pildes:  Well, I just want to clarify actually one thing. So I was not saying everyone should vote on Election Day. I talked about voting in person. And the reason I made that --

Hon. Thomas M. Hardiman:  Like Florida. Florida votes in person but over an extended period of time.

Prof. Richard H. Pildes:  Right. One of the things that has changed is we have expanded early voting opportunities in many, many, many states now. And so you can vote in person without having to worry about leaving work on Tuesday. There’s weekend days of early voting. So what I’m talking about is taking advantage of all the opportunities to vote in person, not some idea that we should go back to a world in which the only way you can vote in person is on a single Tuesday, which is not a national holiday.

Hon. Bradley A. Smith:  And a quick hit here is that there are some studies showing that people who vote in person have more confidence in election results than people who do not.

Hon. Thomas M. Hardiman:  Richard?

Prof. Richard Briffault:  Three things. One, just one on Brad, on the partisan aspects of election law change, there’s actually very little evidence that they have partisan consequences. Most of the data on easier voting, easier voter registration, changes in the voting mechanism make it easier, show almost no partisan consequences.

There’s partisan motivation because different parties have different views about who’s going to be benefited or harmed by election law changes. But almost all the academic studies suggest that it could be. Yes, in a particular race where the margin is one or two or five, maybe it made a difference. But whether it’s expansion, dealing with ex-felons, whether it’s making it easier, making it harder, there’s definitely partisan motivation. Certainly there’s partisan valence in terms of who’s passing what. There’s very, very little evidence of partisan consequence.

Second, in terms of the loss of faith, this does go back to the when are -- I was talking about the two incidents in the last election that had the most dramatic fighting, claims of loss of faith, claims that they were -- elections were being ruined: Harris County, Texas, and Maricopa County, Arizona.

In both cases, there were breakdowns in the election administration, problems with the printers, problems with late openings, problems with the machinery, which led to, of course, charges of partisan intent which -- and led to also to lawsuits trying to keep the polls open longer. These were, again, Harris County was run by Democrats. It was Republicans who were suing. Maricopa County actually had a Republican administrator, but it was also Kari Lake who was suing.

And so I do think in terms of what causes the loss of faith, going back to your point, people lose faith when the rules are being changed or when judges are stepping in. People lose faith when it doesn’t work on Election Day, people -- when they are faced with long lines, when there aren’t enough election machines, when there aren’t enough poll workers. That’s when people lose faith.

So if you want people to vote in person, we have to fund the system. And we have to make in particular that large urban and suburban areas with lots of voters, have more machines, have working machines, have an up to date system. So I do think where people lose faith is when voting becomes -- in-person voting becomes difficult. And those were the two biggest fights that came out of 2022, were Harris County—two of the biggest urban counties in the country—and they’re the ones where they had the most breakdowns, the most publicity, the most claims of fraud.

Third, in terms of voting in person, I’m sympathetic otherwise to go with Rick’s amendment, which is we probably would have to make it a national holiday or make it 24 hours because people do work if people do work or have children or have childcare obligations or have other kinds of care obligations and having short hours, as some states do. Not every state goes six to nine. Some states have shorter hours, don’t have longer hours in urban areas.

If we want to actually have everybody have more in-person voting, make it a national holiday, make it 24-hour voting. But even then, I think we’re swimming upstream. COVID, I think, really -- just as COVID changed the way people work, COVID changes the way people vote. And although 2022 has not nearly as much use of absentee voting as 2020, it was well above 2018. And something like 30 percent of all people are now consistently voting early in person.

There’s problems with early because one of the real problems is, of course, last minute changes in the political environment. Candidates have been known to die or have problems. There is a problem with the early period about how long the period should be. But people are voting with their feet or voting with their hands in voting from home, voting by mail, and voting in person.

So I think it’s as much a cultural thing just as like people are basically preferred to do a lot of things out of the convenience of their homes. It may be a mistake, it may be bad for the culture, but you are swimming upstream. I do think that early in-person voting has some advantages. There are the problems with absentee voting or mail voting. But at the very least, if you want to encourage more people to vote in person, make it better; fund it better; make sure there’s better machinery; make sure that the places are better.

Hon. Thomas M. Hardiman:  All right. Richard, before I go to the Michaels, quick question for you. Do you agree with Rick and Brad that in-person voting is preferable to mail-in voting, provided that the in-person voting is not onerous, that it’s relatively easy to do? Or do you still prefer or like mail-in ballot voting?

Prof. Richard Briffault:  Not more preferring or like; I think it’s about giving people choices, and we’re in a system where those choices exist.

Hon. Thomas M. Hardiman:  Well, we don’t give people choices about showing up for jury duty. And Rick made an important point about civic—Brad too, I think—about civic duty, civic obligation. If you have a duty to show up to jury service, it’s not too much to ask to show up to vote, is it?

Prof. Richard Briffault:  Well, then we should have mandatory voting, which we don’t have, as they have in Australia. Why don’t we have mandatory voting and have people penalized for not voting? They do it in Australia.

Hon. Thomas M. Hardiman:  So you would favor mandatory voting?

Prof. Richard Briffault:  Seriously looking at it, maybe it’s -- I haven’t thought about it in any serious way, but I would be interested in finding out what the experience is in Australia where there is mandatory voting.

Hon. Thomas M. Hardiman:  Okay, all right. The Michaels.

Hon. Michael G. Adams:  Well, thank you. A couple of responses. I’m a realist, and I get held responsible for how well this goes off or doesn’t. And I can tell you this. When I was sworn in three years ago I inherited an election code that was written in 1891 at a time that we had a much more robust volunteer effort in Kentucky than we have today. And it wasn’t that hard to find 4,000 people who would volunteer for a day to work the polls.

It’s harder today than it was in 1891 to find people with the free time who are willing to invest their free time and serve their community. And so I’m a big believer in in-person voting. I think that’s the gold standard for some of the reasons that have been stated today. But I also think it’s increasingly unrealistic to crowd millions of people in and out in one day because I just don’t have the infrastructure, at least in my state.

As I was talking about in my remarks, I just don’t have the facilities, and I don’t have the bodies. I don’t have the volunteers. We’ve got about 3,800 precincts, and you do the math. That’s about 15,000 poll workers to open every single one of them. And so that’s why we’re having to consolidate. And other states are doing that, too.

So I’ll confess something. I didn’t push early voting through in my state just because I’m a swell guy. I did it to make my job easier and the job of the county clerks easier because it’s way easier to get people in and out over a four-day period, smooth it out, versus having one really chaotic day—the last day. What if something goes wrong? What do you do? When you’ve got a little bit of lead in, you can smooth out that turnout a little bit. It’s just easier to get folks in and out.

I mean, it’s kind of crazy to have a task of the government that you just do in one day. If the DMV were open one day, we’d be pretty upset about it. I think the election system should be open for more than one day.

Where I digress from a lot of folks in my job in other states is I don’t like election month. I think that distorts the outcome of who wins elections. And I’ll give you my personal example. I ran against a former Miss America who was very well known, very high name, very well-funded, and I was kind of a nobody. And then we had the election, and I won. But if votes had been cast early, a month early, and banked, I never would have had a shot. And I can give you plenty of other examples on the other side where Democrats or Republicans were disserved by those rules.

I don’t like the election month model where you basically have a lot of votes cast before folks are informed, before they’ve seen the debates, before they’ve seen the ads and all of that, before they talked to their neighbors. I think what we found in Kentucky is -- it’s a good—at least for my state—a good approach of having more days but not so many that you begin to distort the outcome of the election.

To segue a little bit about Kentucky again, this won’t work everywhere because, most states, you have one party control the legislature and the governor. So it was somewhat of, I guess, a happy coincidence that in Kentucky, in my term, we didn’t -- we had split control.

But I think the number one way to have public confidence in your elections and not have one side thinking that you’re trying to rig the rules, if you do give the appearance—whether you’re Democrats pushing mail-in voting in Vermont or you’re Republicans in Georgia, I think unfairly called vote suppressors for dialing back. I think seven or eight weeks of early voting to only five or whatever it was—at least in Kentucky when you’ve got the advantage of split control politically, what I tried to do and I think was successful at is trying to find things both sides could agree on, expanding early voting a little bit, cracking down on the security side but doing it in a responsible way that was humane, and giving both sides something.

And so Kentucky, I think, is one of the unique places where we’ve had Democrats and Republicans together passing election laws in a bipartisan fashion, expanding access while also tightening security. And then when folks lose elections, they don’t allege that something was wrong.

In 2020, the Democrats lost the U.S. Senate race despite outspending Senator McConnell, I think, 100 million to 30 million, and they accepted the results; they accepted that they lost. This week, Daniel Cameron for Governor of Kentucky was tied in the polls to the very end. I thought he was going to win, and he didn’t. And he went on stage and conceded. I shouldn’t have to remark that that is an impressive thing, but it is. [Laughter]

Again, I think that’s somewhat unique to Kentucky, that we’ve pushed this off. We haven’t played politics with it. We’ve done it in a bipartisan way, and I think the result is public acceptance.

Hon. Thomas M. Hardiman:  Great. Just a program note. We’re going to go till about 4:40 or 4:45 since we started late, and in about 5 minutes, I’ll invite folks to the mic. Professor Dimino?

Prof. Michael R. Dimino:  Thank you. I guess I’ll start with the early voting point, since everybody else mentioned that. I generally agree with Mike that some small period of early voting is a good idea. We have in Pennsylvania about a month to vote by mail, and one consequence of that in the last cycle was that there was a debate for the U.S. Senate race that was held after thousands of people had voted already.

And at that debate, it became clear that one of the candidates was suffering from a condition that many people might have considered to be an important consideration when casting their votes. But a good number of the votes had been cast already. So I think that there is a substantial interest in not having that early voting period, whether in person or by mail, go on for too long.

But on this question generally of how to structure elections that way, there is a fundamental question of what is it that we want? Should we change a policy to have one kind of rule or another based on what goal? And there is no agreement on that point among the citizens of the country or among any other subset of it.

Do we want to encourage people to vote? Do we want to make it as easy as possible to vote? Well, some people do, and other people don’t. Do we want to try to achieve the results that make sense in some kind of way? Do we want to choose the best leaders? Well, of course we can’t agree on what those are, even if we could agree that that’s a good goal, and so on.

So whether we have with this early voting in particular, I think Richard is absolutely right that there are a ton of people who now want to shop online, want to vote online, want to do everything online, and not have to put on any pair of pants other than pajamas. [Laughter] And that’s a fact of modern life. So if we want to encourage as many people as possible to vote, that’s the kind of thing we’re going to do. But we have to realize that there’s a kind of trade off.

And speaking of tradeoffs, it strikes me in listening to all the very great remarks by everybody else on the panel that there are a couple of different things we could be talking about in terms of this question about public confidence in elections. The first one is how to increase public confidence in elections—again, assuming that’s what we want to do. And I agree that there are some methods for doing that if you’re lucky enough to be in a situation where, as Mike was describing, where you have kind of buy-in by Democratic and Republican leaders. I think that can advance things.

Certainly having election regulations and statutes that are relatively clear rather than very open ended, advances things. The more that you have an open-ended law applied by a potentially partisan motivated election official or judge or whatever, I think that’s asking for more trouble.

But in general, I am a little bit more pessimistic than some others about the prospect of improving public confidence in elections. I think, as another one of my co-panelists was suggesting, that the public distrusts legislatures with justification; the public distrusts election administrators with some justification; the public distrusts judges with some justification. I’m sitting between an elected administrator and a judge, and independent commissions, which are often trotted out as the solution to this. The public distrusts the independence of independent commissions, too. And what’s more, they’re probably right to do so.

So if you’re as pessimistic as I am, you wonder not how are we going to make the public confident in the results of elections, but recognizing that the public isn’t going to be confident in elections, then what do we do? Do we just say, “Here’s how one group avoids taking the blame for problems,” or do we do something else?

Hon. Thomas M. Hardiman:  Great. Well, put me in the category of favoring clear laws. It makes my job easier. Questions, not comments or speeches. Please, sir.

Russell Nobile:  Yeah. Hi. Russ Nobile. I’m one of the election team at Judicial Watch. I very much enjoy the panel. It’s nice to see both friends and our defendants on the panel, so thank you. [Laughter]

One fairness issue that did not come up in the panel was a question in 2020 about candidates standing. For over 100 plus years, candidates had standing to litigate questions about the time, place, and manner regulations of their elections. And in 2020, that window closed, and now, courts are trying to deal with that. I wanted to get anybody on the panel’s thoughts on the new standing rules.

Hon. Thomas M. Hardiman:  Thank you.

Hon. Bradley A. Smith:  Anybody want to take that?

Prof. Richard H. Pildes:  Is that true?

Hon. Bradley A. Smith:  I think we’re at a loss.

Prof. Richard H. Pildes:  Yeah, I’m not sure. I mean, we might have to have more specifics because I’m not sure what you were referring to. There wasn’t any lack of litigation in 2020.

Russell Nobile:  Yeah. Well, several of the campaign -- Trump’s campaign’s litigation questions were dismissed for lack of standing. The Election Day litigation, they litigated the legislature thereof or the independent legislative doctrine. As we all know, that is a question that the Court heard two years later. He was bounced out when he raised that question during the course of litigation.

And so many of the cases were dismissed, not because of Purcell or other things, but because they just said, “You don’t have standing.” And for over a hundred and some odd years, candidates always had standing. In fact, one of the most prominent cases came from the Third Circuit, which was the Biener [(sp) 01:18:37] decision that balanced an entire line of cases on standing questions. It may not be something you all have encountered.

Prof. Richard H. Pildes:  Yeah, no. If you’re referring to -- I’m not sure. If you’re referring to the principle the Supreme Court established earlier on that only legislatures have standing to challenge a violation of their authority to act under the Second Amendment --

Prof. Richard Briffault:  Article Two?

Prof. Richard H. Pildes:  No, I’m not talking -- Article Two, yes. If you’re talking about that, that was Supreme Court doctrine that had been established a while earlier. I’m not sure I agree with the doctrine, but the doctrine had been established that it’s the legislature that this provision protects, and therefore, the legislature is the only entity that has the standing.

W. James Young:  Thank you. Jim Young, National Right to Work Foundation Staff Attorney. In my civilian life, about 10 years back, I served as chairman of a task force in Prince William County—one of our bellwether counties here in Virginia—regarding some difficulties we had with the election. We recommended many of the changes that have been made, including excuse-free early voting.

My question is, hasn’t it gotten away? I believe Professor Dimino touched on this. Haven’t we gotten away and perhaps too far from the notion of elections as a process by which varying candidates make their arguments—a back and forth—and the notion of a final argument made on that first weekend in November? To the degree that with early voting, what we have is either partisans who’ve made up their mind and they won’t be changed under any circumstances or ignorant voters who are going to check whatever the last name they heard is. And I don’t see how that serves the republic at all, let alone the notion of an informed electorate. Anybody want to comment on that?

Prof. Michael R. Dimino:  I’ll say only that the -- I’m always kind of conflicted with questions like that because I do think that there has been some shift—at least in emphasis or the way that we talk about those kinds of things. But I’m less sure that there is a shift in actual practice, that is., if -- has it always been the case that large numbers of people would vote for -- know a year in advance who they’re going to vote for?

My sense is that maybe the numbers have increased as we’ve become more partisan over the last couple of decades. But I am sure that a whole bunch of Democrats knew they were going to vote for Adlai Stevenson, and a whole bunch of Republicans knew they were going to vote for Dwight Eisenhower 70 years ago.

Hon. Bradley A. Smith:  I want to address that just real quickly, more on Michael’s comment there. I mean, one of the reasons -- and by the way, I know -- I did not say we should not have absentee voting or that we should not have early voting. I think we should have them more limited, and it should be expected that the norm is that you vote on Election Day, that that’s the norm that we try to live to. And we can talk more about that. And I think early voting should be cut way back, and I think there’s very strong polling evidence that the public doesn’t think you need more than about two weeks of early voting, max. And many states have much more than that.

But this brings up a point that’s often overlooked, which is in small races in the country, township trustee, village council, the county commissioners in rural areas, you have people -- they start campaigning on October 20. They don’t do anything before then because they’re spending 600 bucks on their campaign and doing a couple of mailers.

And what happens with all -- they go around and start knocking on doors in their little village, and all these people have already voted. And a lot of these elections are nonpartisan, very different from those national elections where people maybe are more certain way in advance how they want to vote. And I think that’s one more reason that I think early voting is ultimately kind of corrosive of our democracy, at least when early voting is extended way out.

I agree with the secretary. A few days helps administratively, and I think, as Rick and Richard point out, it allows people who otherwise might not be able to make it to the polls to get there. But the idea that you need a month or more of early voting strikes me as absurd.

Garret Hoff:  Thank you. Garrett Hoff, Vice President of Speakers for the Duke Law chapter. Do you think ranked-choice voting advantages that are able to take the time to form opinions on an entire field of candidates as opposed to more casual voters. And for this or any other reason, does ranked-choice voting violate your conceptions of fairness in the electoral process?

Prof. Richard Briffault:  No. [Laughter] There’s plenty of evidence in places that have adopted ranked-choice voting that voters very quickly figure it out. Turnout remains high. Depends on how many choices that they’re given. They may not take all the choices.

But I think there’s evidence in San Francisco, in Oakland, in New York, and all -- many places, it takes about one round of education to make sure that people understand what they’re doing. And it really is up to them. I mean, I think in New York, we have too many choices. It’s down to five. But I think three would be -- I mean, I think people can figure it out.

And in some sense, it’s consistent with Judge Hardiman’s concept earlier or the other people on the panel about the duty of people to figure things out. But I think most people do. And certainly, there may be one first election where it takes a little bit of education, but by the second election, the turnout is high and—or certainly not reduced—and there’s no evidence that it changes the composition of the electorate. So I think the short answer is no.

Hon. Thomas M. Hardiman:  Would you add, Richard, that it adds to sort of the civic engagement in the sense that you’re not as likely to focus on tribe or past habit because you have to actually investigate more?

Prof. Richard Briffault:  There’s some of that. I mean you do have to learn a little bit more. I think the major argument—and I think the jury is still out on this, frankly—is that it can affect campaigning, in that candidates may be also campaigning for second votes. And so that it may make campaigns a little less hostile, that, “Vote for me, but I know you’re committed to so and so. Vote for me second.”

And so it also, I think, deals with the spoiler problem. I really, really want to vote for somebody who is on one end of the one extreme. Pick your extreme. Either that person’s not going to win, so I won’t vote for that person, or I will vote for that person. As a result, my second choice loses. With ranked-choice voting, you get to put in both. So again, we’ve only had a few cycles of it in many places. There’s some evidence that it makes voters somewhat happier, which is one of the reasons people drop out.

Prof. Richard H. Pildes:  Can I add one other people drop important thing about ranked-choice voting? In our standard plurality voting system, very factual candidates can get elected if you have a field of a number of candidates. Thirty-five percent of the vote may be enough for you to get elected, particularly in primary elections.

And so one of the major justifications for ranked-choice voting is it makes it more likely that the candidate who a majority of the electorate supports will actually be the candidate who’s chosen because once you go through that vote redistribution process, you have to have a majority of the votes at the end of the day in order to get elected.

I think it is -- Richard mentioned this. I think it’s strange that the Republican Party has become hostile right now to ranked-choice voting—not completely. The Virginia GOP used it in its convention to choose its nominee for governor, who became Glenn Youngkin because they thought it would allow -- it would get them to a more electable candidate.

And since the Republican Party right now is more internally divided, the party actually has, I think, a self-interest, actually—especially in primary elections—in using ranked-choice voting because it’s going to avoid more factional candidates who have less chance of winning the general election getting chosen. But because the Democrats have won the first few of these, it’s --

Prof. Richard Briffault:  Or a moderate Republican.

Prof. Richard. H. Pildes:  Or a moderate Republican, I think, right now, an ideology has settled in among the Republican Party against it. But I think that’s probably not in the interest of the party.

Ben Silska [sp]:  Ben Sliska visiting from Seattle. I’ve got my smartphone here, and I can send $10,000 to any one of you if you give me your mobile number.

Prof. Richard H. Pildes:  Mine is...

Ben Silska:  Okay, very good.

Hon. Thomas M. Hardiman:  Don’t lose that phone.

[Laugher]

Ben Silska:  Right. So this is a technology question, obviously. Dead voters, voter fraud, ballot harvesting, all of these kinds of things, if -- so the question is, “Could you do a technology solution?” Do you think there’s a trustworthy way to do that? I wrote my first software 47 years ago. Warning. Is there a technology solution that might solve a lot of these problems, including increasing voter trust?

Prof. Richard Briffault:  At the moment, there isn’t. There’s been a lot of studies about it. In fact, truly voting from home voting electronically, if you can do your banking from home, why can’t you do your voting? The people at MIT and other people who studied, no one is remotely confident enough that they can have a -- that there’s an unhackable system.

I think if we’re talking about voter distrust of outcomes now because the late Hugo Chavez programmed the Dominion machines before he died, the level of voter lack of confidence—and I think the lack of confidence of people who design these machines, people working on it—is so great where maybe we might get there, but we are not close to getting there now.

And, I mean, the problem of error, there are obviously -- there are errors in the banking system. There are other errors, but these could be irreversible errors and undetectable errors. So right now nobody is confident enough to want to go forward.

Hon. Michael G. Adams:  So just real quick. Believe it or not, we actually have had internet voting in the United States. Washington State had it back in the 2008 election for a governor which I was involved in. It was a nightmare, and they repealed it, and they went to dropboxes because the public trusted dropbox voting more than they trusted the internet.

John Giokaris:  Hi there. John Giokaris from the Chicago Lawyers chapter. Are we all in agreement that election administration is strictly a state responsibility, or does Congress have the constitutional authority to nationalize all electoral law and procedure as the prior Congress attempted to do with the so-called “For the People Act?”

Prof. Richard H. Pildes:  Well, constitutionally there’s no question that Congress has the power to regulate House and Senate elections. The Supreme Court has said, “Congress can write a complete code of elections for federal elections under the Elections Clause. It hasn’t used that power very often. And there are political issues about, “Are we better off with a decentralized system? Should we nationalize certain issues about the process more?” But just as a matter of constitutional power, at least for House and Senate elections, there’s no dispute that Congress could do all of those things.

Questioner 5:  Prefacing the question with a quick State of the Union in Pennsylvania—at least from my understanding from Congressman or State representative now retired Frank Ryan—but in Pennsylvania, the governmental data security practices around elections and election data do not follow sort of private sector standards and do not submit to regular data security auditing practices that are common in the private sector. For example, if you run a bank or a credit card company, the private sector security standards applicable there are much higher than what Pennsylvania will submit itself to.

I wonder what the State of the Union is across the country. If anyone can comment on are there similar problems in other states where private -- where the government run data security for elections is resistant to following the highest standards available in the private sector—and if you see any solution to that problem—to help improve voter confidence in elections?

Hon. Michael G. Adams:  Well, ours is very robust. I’ll leave it there.

[Laughter]

Hon. Thomas M. Hardiman:  You’ve got a good one, and you’re not going to give us the code.

Hon. Michael G. Adams:  Yeah, that’s exactly right.

Hon. Thomas M. Hardiman:  Okay. Yes, sir.

Questioner 6:  Yeah. So when it comes to the idea of fairness and elections, I think that there’s two sorts of ideas that some of you have alluded to so far. I think the first Richard definitely alluded to it when he opened.

And the first idea that I’ve understood is that there’s this procedural fairness, right? And that’s where it’s how the laws on the ground actually operate when people go to vote and how restrictive or not restrictive they are. But then the other type of fairness seems to me to be more substantive—or I’ll call it practical fairness. And that’s kind of like what we haven’t really, I think, dove into yet.

But I think what embodies that is really like the idea that there are things going on in the background of our political atmosphere that kind of influence how people vote. And based off how that influence is carried out, it can be unfair to a particular party if people are being influenced in one way or another, I think, to that substantive or practical form of fairness.

There’s this discussion that’s very lively right now about how fair it is when you have, let’s say, legacy media or you have social media or you have tech companies that are kind of putting a thumb on the scale. And that question is weighing heavy on my mind right now because I’m thinking about the 2022 midterm election when we had a whole bevy of states adopting these voter laws that many—particularly Democratic—politicians kind of weighed in on and said that it was suppressive.

I think the Biden administration even characterized the specific voting laws in Georgia as being Jim Crow 2.0. And I believe that that was pretty much to suggest that it was going to make it harder for African Americans to vote or pose obstacles, whatever the case may be.

What actually turned out being the case once the dust settled and the research came out was that 96.2 percent of black voters reported their voting experience was excellent or good; 91 percent of blacks said voting was easier or no difference than the previous election cycle; 93 percent of blacks said voting was easier of no difference, and 0 percent of blacks reported a poor experience. And this is in relation to equal numbers to whites. So essentially what I’m saying is that there was a great degree of misinformation that was spread about what the election was going to -- how the election was going to turn out.

My question is probably best directed to the FEC or former FEC chair in asking what can be done to balance the fact that we have to rein in misinformation that can influence elections with the imperative to make sure that we’re not undercutting free speech because I think it’s an absolute travesty when you have Democrat politicians or anybody predicting that an election is going to turn out in a way that’s Jim Crow 2.0, and then you see something so far from it? But I also think that there’s, obviously, an imperative to balance free speech rights. So long winded question, but essentially, how can we do that?

Hon. Bradley A. Smith:  Well, it seems that usually what we hear is people complaining about things that are deemed to be misinformation that turn out to be true that would have benefited Republicans. That’s been a big issue lately. One of the most classic, of course, the Hunter Biden laptop.

As I understand your question, you’re sort of suggesting we get all this misinformation about how awful the Georgia code was when they amended it, and there’s really no evidence that it’s that awful. And I guess that goes to show that you can have a lot of misinformation come from all kinds of directions.

We just had an election in Ohio in which, in my view, one side’s campaign was just entirely built on lies from the moment they started. And did they tell the truth once? In my view, no. But can you restrict that? I think the danger comes when you start to have government try to decide that it knows what is the real stuff and not just this misinformation.

They build it off this idea like somebody saying, “Well, the polls are only open in Kentucky until -- or they’re open in Kentucky till 10:00 p.m., so you don’t have to hurry out and vote,” right? And they direct that and fool people into not voting. But that doesn’t really much happen. The problem is just this bigger stuff that we disagree on, whether something’s relevant or not, how likely it is to be true.

And I don’t know if there’s a legal solution for that because I do think -- or I guess I’ll put it this way. I think any effort at most legal solutions is probably more harmful than the disease. You got to let people speak and ask journalists to be more responsible and ask campaigns to be more responsible. But how much you can do? I don’t know.

Questioner 6:  Thank you.

Hon. Thomas M. Hardiman:  All right, a stopwatch. One minute to get a question and answer. Go ahead, sir.

Mike Isaak:  Okay, thank you. Mike Isaak from Tampa, Florida. The paradigm, I think, is changing. Voters are frustrated, and there’s a level of distrust, and we see a greater number changing from partisan registration to independent. In fact, six months ago in Hillsborough County, there were more registered independents than there were republicans. That’s not the case today.

But I’m just wondering. To what extent do you think this change in the paradigm is affecting the outcomes in the primaries which are closed? And perhaps this change in the paradigm, does it require reevaluation as to whether the primaries should be open?

Prof. Richard H. Pildes:  Do you want to go?

Hon. Thomas M. Hardiman:  We got 20 seconds to answer a really complicated and good question.

Hon. Michael G. Adams:  Can I take that? So, in my state, we have closed primaries, so we don’t let independents vote. Independents are the fastest growing voter bloc in our state. We’ve actually had months this year. We had more registered independents register than Republicans and Democrats combined. And there’s no Independent party doing registration drives. That’s huge.

I think it’s good if we were to open those primaries because we have very low turnout on our primaries. It was 14.5 percent in this May. That disenfranchises a lot of people who are taxpayers who ought to get to vote. It also leads to very extreme outcomes where only the most zealous rightwing and leftwing people vote in the primary, and everyone else is left out.

Mike Issak:  That’s exactly the point that I was trying to illustrate.

Hon. Thomas M. Hardiman:  Thank you. All right. Please join me in thanking our experts.

 

[Applause]

3:00 p.m. - 4:30 p.m.
Mere Natural Law

2023 National Lawyers Convention

Topics: Philosophy
Grand Ballroom
The Mayflower Hotel
1127 Connecticut Avenue NW
Washington, DC 20006

Event Video

Listen & Download

Description

The U.S. Supreme Court’s originalist jurisprudence has been on display in its most recent terms – consider the constitutional analysis in major cases like Bruen and Dobbs. But is the Court’s originalism sound? In his newly released book, Mere Natural Law, Professor Hadley Arkes argues that the Court’s ascendant mode of interpretation insufficiently relies upon the natural moral law. Critics assert that such reliance would be difficult, if not impossible, to moor to objectively discernible standards. This panel brings together several of the most formidable constitutional scholars of a generation to discuss natural law and constitutional conservatism alongside Professor Arkes.

Featuring:

  • Prof. Hadley P. Arkes, Founder and Director, James Wilson Institute on Natural Rights and the American Founding & Edward N. Ney Professor in American Institutions Emeritus, Amherst College
  • Prof. Randy E. Barnett, Patrick Hotung Professor of Constitutional Law, Georgetown University Law Center
  • Hon. Edith H. Jones, United States Court of Appeals, Fifth Circuit
  • Moderator: Prof. Robert P. George, McCormick Professor of Jurisprudence & Director, James Madison Program, Princeton University

Overflow: Chinese Room

Speakers

Event Transcript

Prof. Michael Moreland:  All right. We’ll go ahead and get started. Welcome, everyone. My name is Michael Moreland. I am a law professor at Villanova University outside of Philadelphia, and I will say a few brief words of welcome. First, an announcement—I’m sure you’ve heard it a few times already perhaps—about CLE credit. To get credit, you must sign in and out once per day using the QR codes when you come and when you leave during the day.

Secondly, we want to make a quick announcement about our practice groups. The practice groups are the sponsors of this special panel. I’m the incoming chair of the Religious Liberties Practice Group, but we have other practice groups in a whole range of areas. If you’re interested in joining their work, you can look at the webpage and talk to me or members of The Federalist Society staff.

Finally, it’s my honor to turn things over to the moderator of this distinguished panel, my friend and a friend of many of ours, Professor Robert P. George. Professor George is the McCormick Professor of Jurisprudence and Director of the James Madison Program at Princeton University. He is a prominent scholar in the fields of constitutional interpretation, civil liberties, natural law theory, and legal, moral, and political philosophy.

Professor George has served as Chairman of the U.S. Commission on International Religious Freedom, before that on the President’s Council on Bioethics, and as a presidential appointee to the U.S. Commission on Civil Rights. And among his many books and articles, familiar to many of us is the widely acclaimed 1993 book, Making Men Moral. Welcome, Professor George.

[Applause]

Prof. Robert P. George:  Thank you, Professor Moreland, and thank you very much to The Federalist Society for the invitation to moderate this very distinguished panel. I’d like to say a special word of thanks today to anyone here who is a veteran. We owe the world to you. Thank you for your service. I also want to say a special word of greeting to all my former students that I see out there. It’s really great to get to come to a Federalist Society meeting. It’s like a family reunion for me.

When he found himself in a jail in Birmingham, Alabama, Martin Luther King famously wrote a letter to eight fellow clergymen who had criticized his law breaking. It was, after all, lawbreaking that landed him in jail. The eight clergymen were not racists; they were not bad guys. In fact, they were antiracists in the old fashioned sense of that term. They were against racism.

One had taken very courageous steps himself with his own congregation to combat racism. But nevertheless, King found himself under criticism from his fellow clergyman, and so he wanted to respond. They wanted to know, “How can you, Dr. King, break the law -- come down here and break the law when you yourself advocated respect for law, especially when it came to the enforcement of the Brown v. Board of Education’s desegregation decision?”

So King wrote his response. And the central point in that response is that there are two types of law—or what we would today call two types of positive law: just and unjust. And so King then asks, “What’s the difference between the two?” Just law has to be obeyed no matter what, even if you don’t like it, even if you would have made the law differently. If it’s not unjust, you’re under a moral as well as legal obligation to obey it. Unjust law, you’re not under an obligation to obey. In fact, he goes so far as to say, “You’re under an obligation to disobey unjust law.”

Now, how do you tell the difference between the two? King says, “Just law is law that is in line with natural law and the law of God. Just law upholds, elevates, the human personality”—or in other contexts, he calls the human spirit—“while unjust law diminishes it.” King here, in appealing not simply as a clergyman to the law of God but to the natural law, is himself in line with a great tradition going all the way back to antiquity.

The Christian tradition did not invent nor did the Jewish tradition invent the concept of natural law, the moral law, binding as such on all of us insofar as it can be known by reason. The roots of natural law thinking are in figures like Plato and Aristotle, Cicero.

Now, of course, the medievals—especially the great medieval Christian theologian Thomas Aquinas—take the ball from the ancients and run with it, develop the theory of natural law. But Christianity did not invent it, nor is it, strictly speaking, a religious theory. It’s a theory about what can be known by reason. And it’s a theory that’s directly applicable not only to our personal conduct, as King points out, but also to the conduct of institutions, including political institutions.

It’s the obligation of government to make laws that are in line with the natural law. It’s a violation of that obligation when government fails to make law or makes law that violates natural law. And it’s not simply the ancients and the medievals.

The American founders themselves and their great successor, Abraham Lincoln, were clearly people who believed in natural law and in rights that we have, human beings have, not as matters of mere convention, but as matters of natural law—natural rights. Anyone who knows anything about the American Founding understands that the American Founders sought to create a constitutional order and a body of law that was in line with, reflected the natural law.

But we are here to debate a question that has been pressed by Professor Hadley Arkes throughout his distinguished career as a legal and political philosopher and most recently in his book, Mere Natural Law, about the applicability of natural law to contemporary problems, especially as they present themselves in courtrooms, in litigation, and most especially in constitutional litigation.

What follows from the fact—the agreed upon or mainly agreed upon fact—that the American Founders sought in the Constitution and laws to embody principles of natural law? What follows from that for the constitutional interpreter and most especially for the judge doing constitutional interpretation or legal interpretation more broadly? That is the question.

And to discuss it, we have an all-star panel. I will introduce our speakers in reverse order. Professor Randy Barnett is Patrick Hotung Professor of Constitutional Law at Georgetown Law School and Faculty Director of Georgetown’s Center for the Constitution. He is also a prominent and widely admired public intellectual who has helped to shape discussions outside as well as inside the legal academy on questions of civil liberties and the scope and limits of governmental powers. He earned his Bachelor of Arts degree in philosophy from Northwestern University and his JD from Harvard Law School. He’s been a prosecuting attorney as well as an appellate advocate, and he has been a recipient of the Guggenheim Fellowship and a Bradley Prize.

The Honorable Edith Jones has served for 38 years on the U.S. Court of Appeals for the Fifth Circuit, having been nominated by President Reagan. From 2005 to 2011, she was Chief Judge. She earned her Bachelor of Arts degree from Cornell University and her JD from the University of Texas Law School. A native Texan, she was the first female partner at the firm then known as Andrews & Kurth in Houston. She is president of an Inn of Court in Houston and on the board of the Calvin Coolidge Presidential Foundation. She has been married for 50 years to my friend Sherwood “Woody” Jones and is the mother of one surviving son and the self-described proud grandmother of three beautiful granddaughters.

And then the founder of today’s feast, Professor Hadley Arkes. He is the Edward Ney Professor of Jurisprudence Emeritus at Amherst College, where he has been the beloved mentor of generations of students—many of whom are here. He is the author of eight books by my count, including First Things, and most recently, the volume, We Are Here to Consider Mere Natural Law. He’s the founder and co-director of the James Wilson Institute on Natural Rights in the American Founding. Professor Arkes earned his Bachelor of Arts degree from the University of Illinois and his PhD from the University of Chicago, where he studied with Leo Strauss, among other luminaries.

On a personal note, I will say that Hadley is one of my oldest and dearest friends in academic life and was a generous mentor to me when I was an assistant professor at Princeton, trying to make my way as a conservative scholar in what was by then already hostile territory for dissenters from progressive orthodoxy. And so I am eternally grateful to Hadley for that support and counsel, and it’s a great pleasure to turn him over to you. Hadley.

[Applause]

Prof. Hadley P. Arkes:  Thanks, Robbie. As the late Dean Martin used to say, “What are all these people doing in my bedroom?” This is for natural law that they came out? We’re having a raffle or something here today? [Laughter]

I want to thank Gerry Bradley for proposing this panel, for Gene Meyer and Dean Reuter, who made it happen, and for Edith and Randy and Robbie, who are so kind to agree to come here today to join me in this.

Tom Stoppard did a play called Rosencrantz and Guildenstern Are Dead. And a friend said, “What is this about?” I said it’s about to make me a lot of money. [Laughter] Well, I hope this book is about to make Tom Spence a lot of money for having the kindness to grab it after three hours after I showed him a few chapters. But before anything else, I want to move to cut off at the pass one of the most common clichés triggered by the mention of natural law.

My dear friend Russ Hettinger used to say that Abraham Lincoln could not have raised his hand on March 4, 1861, and taken an oath to defend this Constitution if it were thought that the constitutional right articulated in the Dred Scott case was now part of that Constitution as though woven into the text itself. Lincoln had led a national movement to counter and overturn that decision.

Now, since my book, First Things, years ago, I’ve aligned myself with the Lincolnian position here. If the Court declares Dred Scott to be a slave, we will not form a mob to free him. We respect the outcome of the case in regard to those two litigants. But if we’re not persuaded about the rightness of the principle, the political branches are not obliged to act upon that principle for the measures that come under their hands. And the Lincoln administration moved right away to reach decisions that rejected the holding in the Dred Scott case.

They reversed the decisions that blacks could not be citizens of the United States and therefore not carry passports to study abroad or not claim patents under the laws of the United States. And the Lincoln administration and Congress in June 1862 passed a law to bar slavery from the western territories of the United States anything in the Dred Scott decision notwithstanding.

In the mid-’80s, a question arose in the National Institute of Health of whether it was necessary or whether obliged to use tissues and research drawn from elective abortions. I was part of the crew at the time arguing that if Lincoln was right, it was open to the Reagan administrator, saying, “We respect the outcome of the case, but we never accepted the principle articulated in that case. And so in our judgment, those are tissues drawn from wrongful surgeries.”

We said that could be wrong only if Lincoln was wrong. We didn’t see any way, under the logic of this Constitution, that Lincoln could have been wrong. Randy, rolling out quotations from new books, cited my line that the function of securing natural rights was not assigned distinctly to the judicial branch. The dominating purpose or telos of protecting natural rights affected every branch of the government: the executive and the legislature, no less than the judiciary.

My point is that this teaching on natural law is not a doctrine to give unconstrained discretion to an expansive judiciary. The argument, rather, is that the judges who absorb this understanding of natural law will have a sharper understanding of the boundaries that mark the limits to the inventiveness and reach of judges.

I had the chance to voice this argument a while back at the hearings of the Judiciary Committee for our Born Alive Act to protect the children who survive abortions. My old antagonist, Jerry Nadler, started to twit me and say, “Oh, Professor, yeah. We want to try revising another decision. How about that decision of Bush v. Gore?” I said, “Congressman, you really tried to handle that to get practice. But remember, you just have to respect the outcome in regard to those two litigants.”

[Laughter]

Prof. Hadley P. Arkes:  Now, I’ve been doing round-the-clock interviews on the book and podcasts. At times, it’s been rather like Brian Lamb saying, “Would you talk -- remind our audience? Who exactly was Lincoln?” And I’ve had people ask me earnestly, “Could you tell audience what is natural law?” And I say, “Yeah.” I draw on Aquinas and Kant and say, “It’s the law that underlies all the laws. The laws would tell us why we’re justified in having positive laws.”

We see the sign saying 65 mph, 35 mph. But Kant would tell us behind those laws is an underlying natural law that would tell us why we’d be justified in restraining the freedom of people to speed, to speed that has -- a driver has to speeds that put innocent life at hazard. And, of course, as ever, the task is to make a translation between the underlying natural law, to apply it to the circumstances and terrain before us in positive law: 65 in the open highway, 35 in the winding roads.

But at the same time, that natural law also tells -- goes back a step further to tell us who has the authority to make that positive law in the first place. I was at a stage years ago with a professor from Notre Dame, Amy Coney Barrett. And some students asked, “Well, why do you have such reverence for the positive law? Why does the positive law in America stand on a higher plane than the law in Stalin’s Russia?”

She’s a little taken aback by the question, but the answer was really in the key was in the string of three questions from John Locke. He said, “What is the source of the law?” The legislature, which tells us whether we -- who makes what the law is. “Well, then, what is the source of the legislature?” A Constitution that tells us whether we have a legislature, make chambers, what power?

But then Locke asks, “Then what is the source of the Constitution? It must be,” he said, “something holy and precedent to the positive law.” In our case, it sounded like this. No man is by nature the rule of other men the way that men are by nature the rule of horses and cows. Any rightful government over human beings depends on the consent of the governed, to which one of my beloved judicial friends said, “That’s a lovely sentiment, but it’s never been enacted in our laws.” And the response is, “Of course, it couldn’t be enacted. It is the point or the truth that had to be grasped before we knew who had the authority to enact anything in the first place.” And that brings me back to this project.

We’re drawn back to the principles that were there before the Constitution, the principles that the Framers drew upon in devising the Constitution. As Lincoln and my friend George Sutherland reminded us, “The Union is older than the Constitution. The Union was made from a more perfect -- the Constitution was made from a more perfect Union.”

And as the Founders understood, those principles of the Constitution, the principles of the regime were there before the Constitution, and they would be there even if there were no Constitution, just as John Quincy Adams said that -- reminds us that the -- that right to petition the government was simply implicit in the idea of a free society. It’d be there even if it weren’t in the First Amendment. It’d be there even if there were no First Amendment. It’d be there even if there were no Constitution.

Greg Katsas, in the first day of oral argument over the Obamacare case, cited John Marshall in the old Dartmouth College case saying, “To impose upon people a contract they did not wish could be as bad as impairing the obligation of a contract they had willingly made.” And Justice Story would later say, “That would be true even if there were no Constitution,” okay?

So the Constitution matters, of course, though. I do want to know whether a state can make its territory available as a naval and military base for another power. I do want to know that every two or four years, there will be an election in this country in peace and war. They can’t be called off. But I’m offering an originalism that encompasses the Founder’s understanding of the anchoring grounds and what they were doing. And if we respect the Constitution, I’m saying we should come to respect again the furnishings of mind of the men who made it. So I want to go back then to the principles there before the Constitution.

A president of Amherst College once said, “Hadley has a theory of natural law.” I said, “Would you say that you rather suggest you’re standing back at wholesome detachment, watching theories whiz pass, and somewhere, you’re able to form judgment about the strands of those theories that are plausible or implausible, true or false?” I said, “Take me back to the ground in which you’re making those judgments about the things you reliably know, and you back to the ground that some of us take to be the ground of the natural law.”

My dear late friend Dan Robinson—who authored 18 books, spent his last years lecturing at Oxford—said he wanted as a line on his tombstone, “He died without a theory.” [Laughter] He was really calling upon Thomas Reid, the great eighteenth/nineteenth century philosopher, read closely by John Adams and James Wilson. Reid was teaching about those precepts of common sense that the ordinary man not only knows but has to assume in getting on with the business of life.

And so, before the average man would start bantering with David Hume about the meaning of causation, he knew his own active powers to cause his own acts to happen. And that is how Wilson excited Reid in the opening lines, the opening lines of the very first case cited in the Supreme Court reports, Chisholm v. Georgia, 1793, provoking Reid.

The leading fingers among the Founders—men like Wilson, Al Hamilton, Marshall—showed a remarkable knack of tracing their judgments back to those anchoring axioms of common sense that had to be in place for the sake of explaining the grounds of their own judgments. It was Marshall’s elegant opinion in Fletcher v. Peck.

But the clearest and most elegant example was that introduction that Alexander Hamilton struck off to The Federalist 31, the papers on taxation. He reached no conclusion different from what Chuck Schumer or Mitch McConnell would reach. But anyone looking at the text would notice some different furnishings in mind. This is how he put it.

He said, “In dispositions of every kind, there are certain primary truths, our first principles, upon which all subsequent reasonings must depend. These contain,” he said, “an internal evidence which antecedent to all reflection or combination command the ascent of the mind of this nature are those maxims of geometry. The two lines cannot enclose a space. Two things equal a third must be equal to one another. And if, like nature, must be those maxims of ethics and politics, there cannot be an effect without a cause. The means must be commensurate with the end. And there ought to be no limitation placed on a power destined to affect a purpose which is itself incapable of limitation.” Just the way Chuck Schumer would have said it, I think, if he bends his mind to it. We have no glasses, so I have to look like Marco Rubio.

[Laughter]

Prof. Hadley P. Arkes:  Get glasses next time. But what were those critical things that one grasped in this way, as Hamilton said, per se? Well, one was the anchoring axiom of the laws of reason. Two contradictory propositions both cannot be true. The average man knows when he’s hearing conflicting stories. But the other one, running even deeper, is the proposition that Reid and Kant understood as the very first principle of all legal moral judgment.

As Kant had it, it makes no sense to cast moral judgments of praise or blame on people for acts they were powerless to do, or, as Reid said, to call a person to account to approve or disapprove his conduct, has no power to do good or ill, is absurd. No axiom of Euclid appears more evident than this.

Now, we may find ourselves deliberating over the question of whether Jones really was under medication and incapable of performing his acts. These are points that are quite contingent in mantling a variable. But the thing is, the thing to be noticed, the one thing in this mix that is never variable and never contingent is the principle itself. If Jones was incapable of affecting the outcome, he cannot be held blameworthy or responsible.

Now, that proposition, and holding being blameworthy for acts they were powerless to affect, not only explains the insanity of defense, but if we had time, we could draw out from that simple line a string of propositions running through our law. And I think it also works to explain the principle of racial discrimination, as Robert Jackson fell into, when people may fall into the assumption that race exerts a kind of determinist control over conducts. If we know someone’s race, we know that we can reach moral judgments about the goodness or badness of these people we’re encountering as though they were governed by forces outside their control.

If the Court ever really arrived and expect explanation what was in principle wrong with racial discrimination, we wouldn’t be bewildered now wondering whether that principle in the racial preferences case goes beyond colleges to apply to corporations and whether in corporations, it goes about employers to apply to officers. But let me see what I can draw out in one minute from that anchoring point.

We don’t hold people [blameless] for exterior powers to affect. We hold people responsible for their own acts, not for what is known in the aggregate of that racial group in which they happen to be members. But as we judge, we insist that people should be punished. As John Stuart Mill said, they should be punished only for wrongdoing. And if we respect the difference between innocence and guilt, that obliges us.

He used the most demanding methods in assessing guilt rather than having people run over hot coals or be pummeled to shake their memory. But as we take the logic a step further, we arrive at the judgment that anyone accused of a serious crime should have access to the witnesses against him for the sake of rebutting them and rebutting them arriving at a verdict that is substantively accurate, discriminating between innocence and guilt.

In other words, by drawing out the moral logic, we would come to the right of a person to be confronted with the witnesses against him. And my point is, it would be there even if it were not contained in the Sixth Amendment. We remember that the Framers did not think of putting it in the original text in the first place just as they didn’t think of putting in presumed innocent until proven guilty.

As we know, James Wilson think -- they didn’t -- James Wilson didn’t think we should put in ex post facto laws. We all know that. It’s part of the logic of law as we draw out these principles and we see how they bear in a very precise and concrete way, on things like the regulation of speech, the dimensions of religious freedom, and such matters of withholding care from a newborn born with spina bifida and down syndrome.

I was there in the court the day that Chuck Cooper argued that case. This is no mere theory hovering in the sky. It’s not a mere theory that people should not be held [blameless] for acts they were powerless to affect any more than it’s a mere theory that two contradictory propositions both cannot be true. James Wilson understood these were necessary truths, and he thought that any system of law drawn from this cannot merely give us a theory of natural law. It would be giving us the real thing.

Now, this jurisprudence I’ve described finds its ground in real principles—propositions true of necessity. And anyone working with this sense of things knows that the natural law cannot tell us the right price in nature for a pair of pants or a gallon of milk. When judges cultivate this kind of wit, their divide is engaged at once when they encounter policies like wage price controls or rent controls. We think of our dear friend, Janice Rogers Brown, raising the question, “Why was it wrong for the high-end energy company to market milk at 20 cents less a gallon in Southern California? And why does that state of affairs constitute a disorderly market condition that the federal government has any interest in reaching?”

The judges who absorb this understanding of natural law will not presume to tell us just how long of a residence requirement is warranted before a community would be obliged to pay for a publicly funded higher education or for the education of children of illegal immigrants. Those are judgments that depend on the wealth and generosity of the community. They should be made only by politicians who have a closer connection to the condition and sentiments of their own community. The standards for those judgments are not contained, not contained in any toolkit available to judges.

It was said of Socrates that he brought philosophy down out of the clouds to bear on questions of right and wrong that will arise every day. And I’d say what we’re trying to do now is to bring natural law down out of the clouds to show it’s not a theory hovering in the sky but that it supplies the grounds of our most practical judgment at every turn.

I used to say that to ask whether a judge can get through the day without relying at every turn on the reasoning of the natural law was rather like asking the question, “Can I order the coffee without using syntax?” The judge is reasoning with it at every turn, even when he’s unaware that he’s using it.

The statute bars racial discrimination in certain private businesses open to transactions for the public. Why do we assume that that law should be applied universally, equally to anyone who comes with the terms of the statute? That’s not [codified] law. Why do we assume that the term should be applied universally to anyone who comes in the statute? That’s a distinctly moral logic there. It attaches to anything we’ve come to regard as law, and who put it there?

No clause in the Constitution tells us to do it that way. And our experience has been, as we draw out these implications for judges, lawyers, ordinary folk, what clicks in for them now that they not only know them, but they have the sense that they’ve known them all their lives. Mere natural law.

[Applause]

Prof. Robert P. George:  Thank you, Professor Arkes. Judge Jones?

Hon. Edith H. Jones:  I’m sort of the straight man on this panel, the everyman, if you will. I take this from Michael Uhlmann’s reprinted introduction to Mere Natural Law, which says, “I begin with the observation that lawyers in general are an anti-philosophical race.” [Laughter]

And indeed, my son, who majored in philosophy undergrad school and would conduct long arguments with my husband, said to me more than once, “Mom, you’re not philosophical.” And I plead guilty. I am not. I am the everyman who read Mere Natural Law. And it’s like some of the issues that have been clarified recently in our political debate. It’s something that you realize has to be part of what is going on in the law.

And I will try to explain rather briefly three things: Why are we at a moment where we need to think about the natural law in regard to our daily tasks? What is natural law, and how do judges -- how should judges perhaps approach it?

Why should we look at natural law at this point in our history? Well, we seem to be at an inflection point with the recent demonstrations across the country. When I was in college, I was there at the worst of the anti-war era. There were demonstrations. Cornell, where I went to school, was one of the worst. The school was torn apart. But what were the demonstrators looking for?

As Justice Thomas has said, they were looking for peace. Now, it might be peace, meaning that the Viet Cong were going to overrun and commit the rest of Vietnam to communism. But they weren’t asking for the Viet Cong to go set people’s houses afire, to burn them alive, to open up the wombs of women with babies in them and kill both of them, to rape, to behead babies, to leave trails of blood. But that’s what we’ve seen that Hamas did.

We naturally want to draw back from the scenes of this absolute barbarity and brutality that has been unknown since the gas chambers of World War II, but we can’t do it. But here, you’ve got what looks like hundreds of thousands of young people—many of them in college—who can’t seem to see the distinction between political debate on the one hand and approving murderous barbarity on the other. So there is something wrong, some great moral confusion going on.

I would add that the preface to today’s moral confusion was set only three years ago in the Black Lives Matter riots, where arson, assault, vandalism became routine with very little response to maintain civil order. Again, it’s one thing to voice your disagreements with criminal procedure or how that has worked out in particular groups in society. It’s quite another to say it’s okay to burn down the immigrants’ little stores all over Minneapolis and many other places in this country. Moral confusion.

How has the legal community reacted to this? Well, I’m very happy to see that the law firms wrote to a number of famous schools in this country and said, “We’re not going to hire your graduates who signed on to these letters condemning the Hamas violence.” Well, that’s a start. As Hadley said earlier today, that really doesn’t catch the nub of the problem, which is that what they are advocating is terrible violence, and it’s up to the schools who are training these people to give them a moral grounding.

Well, that’s just as true in undergrad as law school because we all know—certainly going back to my era, but for at least 40 or 50 years before that—the trend in the law schools has been to divorce morality, concepts of justice, natural justice, from the law. They thought that was a product of medieval thinking, that the trend of the times was historical, that progress meant that everything trended upward in society if you just had the right government and the right economics and so on.

Obviously, that’s not right, and we are at a very, very serious point in our society when we have one group of people in our society essentially calling for the annihilation of another group. That’s certainly not part of America in the last century. So let’s think about natural law, or I think I should -- we should think about what it is that orders men’s lives, that orders society’s life, to avoid the kinds of crises that we are seeing, and God forbid, that we hope we will not enter into.

What is natural law? Hadley was explaining -- and these gentlemen can explain this in a much more detailed and systematic way than I can. But at least I read the book. [Laughter] And what Michael Ulhmann also points out in the introduction is that lawyers can be trained to think in the way of natural law and justice. It’s just not done at the present time. And, of course, I might add, that was the influence of Holmes, who was great at aphorisms. From the technical standpoint, maybe not so great, but aphorisms win the day. And he was very much opposed to any kind of moral conception in the law. And in fact, Justice Scalia even quoted that occasionally.

But as Hadley writes in his book—and there are a lot of jokes in here. You will laugh when you read great parts of it—he says, “The seven-year-old who gets beat up by bigger boys comes home and says, ‘That was wrong.’” And what would Holmes’ response be to that? Well, I mean, if there is no right and wrong, they had a right to beat him up and to take control over him. Well, what does the Declaration of Independence say? “All men are created equal. No man has a right to rule over the other.” It’s a fundamental of political philosophy that the -- or at least in the Western tradition that the strong do not have the right to govern others just because they’re strong.

That’s a principle of natural law. Holmes was wrong. A seven-year-old boy happens to know that. So let’s think a little more about some of these things. As Mike Ulhmann says, “The best way to train lawyers is sort of by analogy and syllogism.” And I agree with that, and that’s the way I approached a great deal of the book. Take one example.

Hadley goes into many different aspects of con law. He talks a lot about the Dobbs case. He talks a lot about transgenderism. Those are things that are likely to come before our Court, so I can’t discuss those. But let’s talk about speech. We have a series of Supreme Court decisions in free speech. He cites the Terminiello case from the late ‘40s or early ‘50s that have traced an interesting devolution from what the Founders would have recognized as speech.

You went from Terminiello, where this inflammatory speaker in Chicago had a riot going on outside because he was so inflammatory. And then he started throwing rhetorical bricks or flames on the—what do you call it?—cinders on the fire himself. And the police finally arrested and charged him, and his conviction was overturned by the Supreme Court in one of the early decisions that said, “We can’t vouch for the goodness of the speech or the badness of the speech.” They overturned it on jury instructions. And Justice Jackson, recently returned from Nuremberg, was shocked. He was one of the only dissenters.

He said, “The Constitution is not a suicide pact.” Well, other members of the Supreme Court didn’t draw that lesson. So we then have in the early ‘60s Cohen v. California, where the fellow is wearing the jacket that says “F the draft” into the courthouse. The Supreme Court says, “One man’s lyric is another man’s profanity”—something like that. Vulgarity. Really, if you think about it, a very shallow statement to be in a Supreme Court legal opinion.

But I would take the position—and I drew this conclusion even before I read Hadley’s book—that when you become too open ended about the freedom of speech, as we see from this series of Supreme Court decisions, what you end up with is no more civil discourse. I mean, if you can say “F the draft” or “wear it in the courtroom,” the next case they had was a fellow who was spouting the F word in a school board meeting, the Rosenberg case.

It’s systematically gone downhill from that to the Westboro Baptists, where Justice Alito alone, I think, was the dissenter when they were screaming profanities as the family tried to bury their son who had been killed in combat in Iraq. In old days, that would have been considered an assault. It would have been an intentional tort, infliction of emotional distress. And the Supreme Court saw that as protected by the First Amendment.

You go then down to the Stolen Valor case, to the Mattel case, where that was the slant that was refused to trademark. And the Supreme Court, apparently, they all knew that if you can trademark something like that, you can trademark any kind of vulgarity. So again, when you destroy reasoned speech, you destroy the possibility of civil discourse. So you have to ask, “Is the Constitution a suicide pact? Is there a way to limit speech in a reasonable way?”

And one of the hallmarks that the -- one of the grounds that the Supreme Court saw a long time ago to try to curb these tendencies was called fighting words. It is possible—I’m not opining on it—but it is possible that many of the demonstrations that are going on today are fighting words. They’re deliberately inciting anti-Semitic violence in a way that we’ve never seen before.

And, in fact, I would commend to you the president of Tulane University—which has a large Jewish population—where they were demonstrating in support of Israel last week. And the pro-Palestinians came up to disrupt it, and fisticuffs broke out. They arrested the malefactors. The president said, “We’re not through arresting because we haven’t finished looking at the video yet.” And then he said, “Whoever is charged with anything in regard to this by the law is going to be expelled.” So was that an abdication of free speech?

[Applause]

Hon. Edith H. Jones:  One other area I’d mention is defamation, New York Times v. Sullivan. For the sake of time, I’ll just comment. I’ve long wondered whether that was a reasonable opinion. After all, it was Shakespeare that wrote, “He who steals my purse, steals trash. He who”—I wrote it down here somewhere—“robs me of my good name gains nothing, but basically destroys me.”

New York Times v. Sullivan allows the press to utter the most grave falsehoods about anybody with very little recourse. And again, it destroys the possibility of -- it certainly has created incentives against truth telling in the news. So what is natural law? What do you do with this?

Hadley talks about these anchoring principles that underlie all of the thinking that we have, and he’s described a couple of them here. A lot of them were voiced by Lincoln in practically all his writings, famously described in the Lincoln Douglas debates, where the issue was, “Is a slave a man? If a man, what gives anyone the authority to rule over that man?” That’s a principle embedded in our government, embedded in fundamental natural law, and applicable to many subsequent types of positive law through the years.

Natural law is not something that exists in the clouds despite the derision of Oliver Wendell Holmes. It traces its origin back thousands of years, as Professor George noted. It is present in the opinions. And I checked out Hadley’s cites here. I went back to Fletcher v. Peck, Chisholm vs. Georgia. Of course, all American lawyers were trained on Blackstone for well over 100 years who starts off describing natural law and how it is the presupposition of all of our constitutional and positive law.

Justice Story drew from natural law principles for an opinion he wrote on circuit called La Jeune Eugenie—excuse my French pronunciation—where he said that slavery was abhorrent as a matter of natural law, and therefore, the slave trade could be condemned under principles of natural law and principles of the law of nations at that time. And therefore, a vessel engaged in the slave trade was subject to be attached, libeled, and taken away from its owner.

When Hadley is -- some of the precise principles that he refers to—principle of contradiction, which I mentioned already, the idea that no person is responsible for things that he cannot control, that is, the root principle of no discrimination on the basis of skin color. Aristotle’s was do good and avoid evil—in many notions of positive lawmaking and judicial lawmaking, we have to make prudential judgments about doing good and not doing evil. But that’s the fundament from which we operate. I will add one about property that agreements voluntarily entered into must be fulfilled. That’s the root of our contract law.

So there have been criticisms of Hadley’s book. Let me make a few responses to those by very, again, scholars much more learned than I am, but I think they were misapprehending what he is saying. Some couple of scholars have said that he’s trying to take us back to the idea of judge-made law. That is not so. He calls himself an original originalist because he’s trying to recover the sense that was immanent in what the Founders were doing, that there are these principles that exist beyond the Constitution.

Does that mean that we decide cases beyond the Constitution? Not necessarily. In fact, almost never because the Constitution itself—as Scalia and others well know—creates a structure of government that itself is based to reflect the moral and natural law. But there are questions posed under the Constitution—like free speech, like the scope of religious liberty, like the fundamental issues about a child in the womb, and what are male and female—that the Constitution doesn’t answer, but right reason for many of us forms the right answer.

He criticizes opinions that have been issued by a number of members of the Supreme Court who are conservative originalists. Does that make him not an originalist? No, it does not. Conservatives love to disagree with each other, don’t we? [Laughter]

There are many ways to have disagreements and to think about things in a different way. One can realize—again, going back to the speech cases I talked about—“Do you really mean to say that the law in Chicago that was curtailing loitering in order to stop drug dealers from monopolizing all the streets in South Chicago was unconstitutionally vague?” That’s what the Court held in 1999 in Morales v. Chicago. I will say both Justices Scalia and Thomas dissented in that. But what happened?

Well, the drug dealers took over. There was poignant testimony from the local people that they were scared to walk outside for fear of the crossfire. Well, guess what? Chicago hasn’t gotten any better for lack of enforcing that. And in fact, the Ninth Circuit, having condoned camping in public spaces, we see what’s happened to public order and civility in the cities in which that are beleaguered by those kinds of holdings. Are those holdings outside the Constitution, outside the realm of rights? I’ll leave it to the Supreme Court to determine. But the seven-year-old boy probably has an answer to that. [Laughter]

Finally, one of the other arguments, “Does this open the door to substantive due process?” No, it does not because these principles have been known for a long time. They just haven’t been taught. And it used to be that judges -- that lawyers started out their education with several lectures and training in the natural law, much of which is syllogistic reasoning from first principles—as Ulhmann said, natural to lawyers.

Okay. Finally, what are judges supposed to do about this? I’ve just voiced a couple of the areas where I am particularly sensitive to the need to take another look and articulate the underpinnings of our decisions in such a way that they are not morally relativistic. It’s very fine to say the originalist view on -- we’ll be seeing more of this in the Second Amendment arguments in the near future, so I can’t go too far. But if you work your brains a little bit, you will see there’s a lot of questions. And I don’t think it was an accident that Justice Thomas specifically referred to analogical and syllogistic reasoning about what should be the proper scope or limitation on Second Amendment rights.

The problem for judges is, I’m certainly not a young judge, but I was not trained in natural law in the way that the Founders were. I’ve spent some time trying to recover the thinking of the Founders from my own self education, but there is a big educational problem before you can ask judges to incorporate a kind of thinking of right and wrong that used to prevail.

So I would say that the next book Hadley has to write is a version of Scalia’s reading law, where he sets out -- he restored to legal thinking the canons of interpretation. And one of those canons is the necessity for mens rea and criminal law. And Justice Scalia was a big one for saying that he was purely originalist, and he couldn’t go to that law in the sky.

Where did the idea of mens rea come from? Well, it pre-exists the Constitution. In fact, it probably goes back to Genesis. And before that, of course, it would have gone back to Aristotle and Cicero. So even those kinds of principles go back to a way of thinking and a need for stability and moral judgments that we ought to seriously incorporate into the law nowadays. Thank you.

[Applause]

Prof. Robert P. George:  Thank you, Judge Jones. Professor Barnett?

Prof. Randy E. Barnett:  Well, I want to thank the organizers for including me in this wonderful program and thank Hadley for his wonderful book. I’m very impressed by the turnout at this program. I thought that when I agreed to be on a natural law program, we’re going to be 20 people in a room. But this is very nice. So let me start my talk with a hypothetical or what I wish was a hypothetical.

Suppose that the legislature of a hypothetical state—call it California [Laughter]—enacted a statute removing your children from your custody whenever an official of the state determined that it would be in the best interests of your children. I’ll let you fill in the blanks why the state of California might think that it could raise your kids better than you.

Do you have a right to raise your own children? Or more relevantly, under the U.S. Constitution, do you have a constitutional right to raise your own children? After all, while the Constitution protects the rights of speech, press, and assembly, as well as the right to keep and bear arms, it says nothing about a right to raise your own children. So can you assert such a right in court?

As it happens, there’s a Supreme Court precedent on this question. In the 2000 case of Troxel v. Granville, the Court specifically considered whether a mother had a right to raise her own children. And this right superseded -- and did this right superseded -- this right superseded in order by a family court judge supposedly based on the best interest of her children. By a vote of 6-3, the Court upheld the fundamental right of the mother and vacated the family court judge’s order.

Speaking for the majority, Justice O’Connor wrote, “The liberty interests at issue in this case—the interest of parents in the care, custody, and control of their children—is perhaps the oldest of the fundamental liberty interests recognized by this Court.” Now, the earliest of the precedents that she cited were Meyer v. Nebraska and Pierce v. Society of Sisters.

In light of the successive precedent, she concluded, “It cannot now be doubted that the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment protects the fundamental right of parents to make decisions concerning the care, custody, and control of their children.”

Now, Justice Scalia dissented in this case. In his opinion, he conceded that the right to raise one’s own children was one of the unalienable rights to which the Declaration of Independence refers, and he further conceded that it was also among the rights retained by the people to which the Ninth Amendment refers. But he asserted nonetheless that, “The Declaration of Independence is not a legal prescription conferring powers upon the courts. And the Constitution’s refusal to deny or disparage other rights is far removed from affirming any one of them and even further removed from authorizing judges to identify what they might be and to enforce the judges lists against laws duly enacted by the people.”

“For this reason,” he concluded, “I do not believe that the power which the Constitution confers upon me as a judge entitles me to deny legal effect to laws that, in my view, infringe upon what is, in my view, that unenumerated right”—the right to raise your own children, I want to remind you.

Now, Justice Scalia also disparaged the precedents of Meyer v. Nebraska and Pierce v. Society of Sisters, which he said were the first to protect what he called the substantive constitutional right of parents to direct the upbringing of their children. “Both cases,” he said, “came from a -- an era rich in substantive due process holdings that have since been repudiated.” By this, he meant, of course, that they were decided on the same theory as Lochner v. New York.

This ambivalence and even hostility towards the constitutional right of parents to raise their own children reveals what might be called the “positivist pathology” that has always pervaded the conservative legal movement. By this, I mean the insistence that only rights specifically stated in the positive law text of the Constitution can provide the basis of a constitutional challenge to a law and also that the textual references to unenumerated natural rights in the Ninth Amendment and in the Fourteenth Amendment are and ought to be nonoperative dead letters, nor is this problem confined to hypotheticals.

During COVID, the positivist pathology rendered the federal courts completely unavailing to the millions of Americans who were largely confined to their homes, unable to visit their dying loved ones, or even to attend their funerals. Private schools were forbidden from holding classes for young kids who were overwhelmingly unaffected by COVID, lest their example shame the teachers’ unions whose members preferred to teach from home.

Unless you could claim an enumerated right—like the right to freely exercise religion—conservative judges and justices were AWOL. State and federal governments were not held to any burden to present evidence that these restrictions on liberty—these radical, unprecedented restrictions on liberty—were truly necessary and proper.

This positivist pathology is based on a not unrealistic fear of unelected, unaccountable judges making up a panoply of fake rights that legislatures cannot override, thereby denying what conservatives call the right of the people to govern themselves. This is an understandable concern, but it arises from the modern conception of constitutional rights that’s based on a fundamental misreading of our constitutional history.

Under the modern conception, a constitutional right is one that trumps or provides definitive and irrefutable objections to legislation. For this reason, preserving democratic self-governance requires that constitutional rights must be strictly limited. So it is convenient to limit constitutional rights to the positive law rights that are specifically enumerated in the text of the Constitution. But even conservative justices have not gone this far. In McDonald v. City of Chicago, a conservative majority upheld the existence of a constitutional right to keep and bear arms against state governments.

Writing for a for-justice plurality, Justice Alito declined to find that this right was protected by the original meaning of the Privileges or Immunities Clause. Instead, he employed the conservative justices’ substantive due process implementing doctrine that they had articulated in Washington v. Glucksberg, and that is, to be a fundamental constitutional right, a right must be deeply rooted in the nation’s tradition and history. And Justice Alito concluded that the right to keep and bear arms was so rooted.

Now, the good news is that this conservative substantive due process implementing doctrine could pretty easily justify a right of parents to raise their own kids. They could find such a right to be both deeply rooted in the nation’s tradition and history and implicit in the concept of ordered liberty. The bad news is that this conservative implementing doctrine rests solely on stare decisis rather than on the original meaning of either the due process of law -- of the due process of law in the Fifth and Fourteenth Amendments, or, say, the privileges or immunities clause in the Fourteenth Amendment.

There is another way. The solution lies not in abandoning or ignoring the original meaning of the text of the Constitution, but in understanding the natural rights underpinnings of that text. This natural rights underpinnings is acknowledged by the original meaning of the Ninth Amendment and the Privileges or Immunities Clause of the Fourteenth, as well as the Due Process Clauses of both the Fifth and Fourteenth Amendments.

As Evan Bernick and I explain in our book, The Original Meaning of the Fourteenth Amendment: Its Letter in Spirit, the original meaning of due process of law is about ensuring a judicial process before any individual person may be denied their natural rights to life, liberty, or property. This judicial process is required to ensure, first, that a person is actually guilty of violating a validly enacted statute and, second, that the statute or legislative act was within the jurisdiction or just powers of a legislature to enact. In other words, due process of law entitles any accused person to a judicial determination that a legislative act was truly a valid law.

Now, when it comes to the legislative powers of Congress, most conservatives are quite comfortable with the idea that before a person can be deprived of his life, liberty, or property, due process of law entitles that person to a judicial assessment of whether the statute being -- the statute being enforced was a necessary and proper exercise of one of Congress’s enumerated powers.

In this way, in NFIB v. Sebelius, our challenge to Obamacare was both a Commerce Clause challenge and a Fifth Amendment due process of law challenge to a validly enacted statute. The same goes for the states. Under the Fourteenth Amendment’s Due Process Clause, a state legislative act must be within a proper conception of the police power of states. But here, as our COVID experience revealed, conservative judges, along with their progressive colleagues, are wary of enforcing any limits on that power.

Part of this hesitance arises from the assumption that if a natural right retained by the people is found to be fundamental, it requires that any law regulating such a right be strictly scrutinized. But this is not how natural rights were thought to operate before the new deal and the rise of the preferred freedoms approach of footnote four of U.S. v. Carolene Products.

Indeed, it’s inconsistent with how the Court in Carolene Products described due process of law. In the body of his opinion—not the footnote—but the body of his opinion, Justice Stone affirmed that, “A statute would deny due process which precluded the disproof in judicial proceedings of all facts which would show or tend to show that a statute depriving the suitor of his life, liberty, or property had a rational basis.”

Here, the new deal is reaffirming the traditional rationality and an arbitrariness review required by due process of law. What due process of law requires is a realistic or meaningful inquiry into the rational basis of a legislative restriction on liberty, not the unreasonable -- unrealistic, conceivable basis sham review adopted by the Warren court in Williamson v. Lee Optical. I like saying it was a Warren court opinion. It was a Warren court opinion.

Unless the Constitution provides a rule-like prohibition, the due process of law requires an evidence-based showing that a law restricting our natural rights of life, liberty, or property is not irrational or arbitrary. To protect the natural rights of the people, the conservative legal movement simply has to get past its demonization of Lockner v. New York.

Lockner did not find that the liberty of contract was a fundamental right that was protected by strict scrutiny. It was not about requiring any restriction on economic liberty to be narrowly tailored to achieve a compelling state interest. Rather, the majority focused on just one provision of a comprehensive regulation of New York bake shops, the Bake Shop Act, and that was the maximum hours law provision. The majority found the connection between this prohibition and any conceivable health and safety end to be so poorly supported by evidence as to raise the suspicion that the law was a pretext for what the Court called “other motives.”

Now, perhaps the five justice majority was wrong in its fact-based assessment and Justice Harlan was right in his fact-based dissent. But conservatives need to get over their fealty to Justice Holmes’s Lochner dissent, in which he adopts a conceivable basis or fact-free approach to the due process of law. It was noteworthy that in our Rosencrantz debate on Lockner here a few years ago, Akhil Amar declined to defend the reasoning of Holmes’ opinion preferring the much safer route of defending Justice Harlan’s fact-based opinion.

Which brings me at last to Hadley Arkes’ book, Mere Natural Law: Originalism and the Anchoring Truths of the Constitution. In his book, Hadley is rightly scathing about Holmes, who he describes as “a man ever more clever than wise”—a quote I’m going to borrow and maybe make my own. [Laughter] That’s it for you, Hadley. It’s my quote now.

[Laughter]

Prof. Hadley P. Arkes:  That’s it?

Prof. Randy E. Barnett:  As Hadley notes, Holmes has famously observed that the role of a judge was to stand back and let the dominant power have its way. This is “might makes right nihilism.” Whatever the majority says is law is law because it’s the majority. “If we hold back from taking that path,” Hadley responds, “the only alternative is to insist that this exercise of power over other men must take on the discipline of justifying itself.”

Now, Hadley defines “to justify” as “to show why something is rightful or just.” When we override the freedom of moral agents, people who can deliberate about the things that are good or bad for themselves, can we actually show as a ground of our policy a principle that would be valid and rightful for anyone who came under the commands of this law, which is to say, we are asking whether there is a moral ground for justification for that law?

And if we take that path, we open ourselves to the obligation to treat the matter of justification in the most serious manner. “We must insist,” Hadley writes, “on evidence and reasons tested in the most demanding and principled way.” This approach would have come in very handy during COVID to protect the liberties of the American people.

“The natural law comes into play,” Hadley explains, “when we test justifications that are offered for restricting the freedoms of the people, whether freedoms grand or small. To insist that those men and women who govern me need to establish the justification for the policies they are making binding on me is the most natural response to this exercise of power. And in the same way, the men and women who take seriously the obligation to explain that justification to assemble evidence and reasons that are compelling are doing the most natural thing. Without sounding the trumpets or inferring the banners, they are doing the jurisprudence of natural law.”

To this, I would add, these men and women are also adhering to the requirements of due process of law. The subtitle of Hadley’s book, Originalism and the Anchoring Truths of the Constitution, appears to align him with those—like Adrian Vermeule—who have rejected originalism from the right. But Hadley’s criticisms of Justice Scalia are really criticisms of Scalia’s positivism, not his originalism.

I think Hadley would agree that an embrace of natural law does not entail an abandonment of originalism, that is, the moral and legal duty of constitutional actors to adhere to the original meaning of the text, provided that the substance of that text is consistent with natural law and adequately protective of natural rights.

Now, I’m not a late comer to this game. Some 20 years ago, in my book, Restoring the Lost Constitution, I spent the first 45 pages justifying the binding nature of the original meaning of the Constitution on the grounds of what I called “constitutional legitimacy.” I maintained that the reason why the original meaning of the Constitution is binding is at least in part because of the substance of what it says, in particular, whether or not that substance, if followed, provides a lawmaking process that assures that the laws being imposed on we the people are binding in conscience—a phrase I quite consciously borrowed from Thomas Aquinas.

In 2004, when I was still on the faculty of Boston University, the Cato Institute held a book forum much like this one. They invited D.C. Circuit Judge David Sentelle to provide some critical commentary. He began his comments by advising readers “to skip that first 45 pages and jump directly to the meat.” [Laughter]  “The legitimacy of the Constitution,” Judge Sentelle said, “rests upon the consent of the government.” Why? “Because without government, life would be nasty, brutish, and short”—in other words, the same Hobbesean nihilist might makes right approach of Holmes.

When it came to my contention that, to be legitimate, a Constitution needed to provide a lawmaking process that ensured that the laws imposed on we the people are necessary to protect the rights of others and do not violate the preexisting rights of the persons on whom they are being imposed. The good judge dismissed this as “a subjective new standard from a professor from Massachusetts” [Laughter].

By invoking the consent of the governed, Judge Sentelle was, of course, invoking the Declaration of Independence. But he skipped the first part of that phrase, which reads, “Deriving their just powers from the consent of the governed.” And, like other conservative positivists, he omitted how that sentence begins: “To secure these rights, governments are instituted among men.” Which rights are these? They are the unalienable, individual rights to life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness. “These rights are grounded,” said our founders, “in the law of nature and of nature’s God.”

Yes, they were grounded in that mere natural law that Hadley Arkes so impassionately defends in this book as he has in his previous work. The conservative legal movement needs to heed his admonishments. It needs to repudiate Thomas Hobbes, Rousseau, and Nietzsche, and embrace John Locke, Aristotle, and Aquinas, or what the subtitle of Hadley’s wonderful book accurately calls “the anchoring truths of the Constitution.” Thank you.

[Applause]

Prof. Robert P. George:  Thank you, Professor Barnett. I’m afraid that the wonderful presentations have more or less exhausted our time. I had hoped for some questions, and Hadley had asked me to offer a few reflections of my own. Do we have time for -- I’ll skip my own reflections. But can the organizers tell me whether I can have a couple of minutes for a couple of questions? Yeah? Okay. Please.

Prof. Hadley P. Arkes:  Wait, wait, wait.

Prof. Robert P. George:  Hadley?

Prof. Hadley P. Arkes:  I want to explain what Edith was getting at, the remark about the seven-year-olds. The question was posed. Two responses of the seven-year-old who’s beaten up and his money is taken. One, do you think he thinks he was wronged, set upon wrongly, or two, they must have been right? They succeeded? I don’t think anyone would take the second one, which is to say you assume the seven-year-old understood what Rousseau said, that the mere success of people in seizing and holding power over others cannot establish his justification.

If you ask Justice Holmes, “On what ground does the majority rule the minority?” he has the brute power to overpower them. So I was saying that this ordinary seven-year-old knows more than highly learned Justice Holmes. Okay, other questions.

Prof. Robert P. George:  Yes, go ahead.

Brian Bishop:  Brian Bishop from Rhode Island. I want to align myself quickly with Randy’s embrace of bringing Lockner back to a better-viewed decision. But I thought when you said the bad news, I thought you were going to point out that in this same tradition or looking at history and tradition that we might also say there was a tradition of privacy in certain relationships, that this can be kind of played from both sides of the divide on issues. And to me, that is something that, in bringing Lockner back, really questions the part of Roe, of course, that I thought was more dependent on substantive due process.

Prof. Robert P. George:  Okay, Professor Barnett?

Prof. Randy E. Barnett:  I will take that as a comment rather than a question. Thank you.

Prof. Robert P. George:  Yeah, let’s do one more.

Nathaniel Lawson:  Nathaniel Lawson of the Cato Institute. Randy, I definitely know from what I’ve done that rights were -- at the time of the Founding, rights were less absolute than they are today. On the other hand, how does that fit with these rights being inalienable and fundamental things of free speech or in other rights?

Prof. Robert P. George:  Let me hand that one to professor Arkes.

Prof. Hadley P. Arkes:  I didn’t quite get the question.

Prof. Robert P. George:  Oh, you didn’t? Okay, yeah. Randy, do you want to take it?

Prof. Randy E. Barnett:  I mean, it’s a great question. Rights were absolute in the sense that inalienable rights can’t be taken away from you. But the way they function in a constitutional order is simply to put the burden of justification on those who would reasonably regulate it. So the possession of a right bars -- you can prohibit any violations of a right, but you can also regulate the exercise of the right so as to protect the rights of others.

So regulation is permissible in a constitutional order even though these rights remain the possession of the right holder. They can be regulated the way contract law regulates the making of contracts. But then the burden is simply on the government when they are restricting your rights to justify that as necessary and proper, which, if they were actually operating on the empirical facts available to them, they should have no problem showing. Or if they don’t have to show it, they don’t usually do the investigation.

Prof. Robert P. George:  That prompts me to actually to a commercial, which is that for people who are interested in pursuing those sorts of questions more deeply on November 30 and December 1 here in Washington at the American Enterprise Institute, there’s going to be a conference marking the thirtieth anniversary of the publication of my book, Making Men Moral, which addresses many of these basic natural law questions. And I believe that the conference is open to the public. If it’s not, I’m making a big mistake in publicizing it. [Laughter] But we will be exploring very deeply many of these same questions. Hadley, you wanted 30 seconds at the end.

Prof. Hadley P. Arkes:  Yeah, just a quick -- some closing words. I want to pick up one thing of Randy’s. I think to have seemed to assume that the decision in Buck v. Bell was one of our worst decisions. And we said, “Well, what would we use to strike it down?” Bill Pryor used to cite Walter Berns. Walter Berns had a classic case on this, and he came to the --

Well, he cited Corwin [sp] saying, “We’re able to protect this kind of -- we looked at the background. We have no long-anchoring right not to be subjected to eugenic testing or sterilization. It’s a Due Process Clause.” He finds Corwin saying, “Yeah. We’re able to protect these kinds better when we had cases like Lockner,” right?

And so Walter Berns ended by saying this. Buck v. Bill illustrates the need for somebody to perform this function. Holmes recognized, “The correct procedure may be nothing but an empty shell or mask behind which injustice is done. In the end, procedural due process is a substantive right which is denied everyone to whom injustice is done. It seems reasonable to conclude that the extent to which the Court probes the record of the case would depend on the substance of the law.”

Permit me a closing word, a personal word. I’ve lost a number of people close to me over the last year or so. And I began to wonder whether I might see -- be here for the release of the book. And I recall Tom Stoppard’s line in the Invention of Love—what he recalls.

He has the 19 year old A. E. Housman at Oxford doing a riff for his sister on God’s words to Moses as he’s showing him the promised land he will not enter. And he hears God say, “I’m giving you all of Gilead unto Dan. I’m giving you all of the land of Naphtali and Judah and Manasseh to the utmost sea, but not including Wales, which I’m saving for the Methodists. [Laughter]

So I’m saying I’m happy to be alive today, and I’m happy to see so many of the best jurists in the country, Dermot [sp] and Jen [sp] and some others whom I’m blessed to have as friends. Thank you all for coming.

[Applause]

 

Prof. Robert P. George:  Thank you, all, and we are adjourned.

5:00 p.m. - 5:45 p.m.
22nd Annual Barbara K. Olson Memorial Lecture

2023 National Lawyers Convention

Grand Ballroom
The Mayflower Hotel
1127 Connecticut Avenue NW
Washington, DC 20006

Share

Event Video

Listen & Download

Description

(Ticketed event)

On September 11, 2001, at the age of 45 and at the height of her professional and personal life, Barbara K. Olson was murdered in the terrorist attacks against the United States as a passenger on the hijacked American Airlines flight that was flown into the Pentagon. The Federalist Society believes that it is most fitting to dedicate an annual lecture on limited government and the spirit of freedom to the memory of Barbara Olson. She had a deep commitment to the rule of law and understood well the relationship between respecting limits on government power and the preservation of freedom. And, significantly, Barbara Olson was an individual who never took freedom for granted in her own life, even in her final terrifying moments-her inspiring and energetic human spirit is a testament to what one can achieve in a world that places a premium on human freedom. Solicitor General Theodore B. Olson delivered the first lecture in November 2001. The lecture series continued in following years with other notable individuals.

Featuring:

  • Ms. Bari Weiss, Founder & Editor, The Free Press
  • Introduction: Mr. Theodore W. Ullyot, Co-Chairman, Board of Visitors, The Federalist Society

Speakers

Event Transcript

When Gene Meyer gave me a list of the people who had previously given the Barbara Olson lecture, I was sure you guys had made a mistake in inviting me. I am not a lawyer or a legal scholar or a former attorney general. I have, in my time, edited dozens of op-eds about Chevron deference, but I’m still not quite sure what that means.

Nor am I a member of the Federalist Society. My parents, who probably couldn’t afford the local country club, raised us on the Groucho Marx line: I don’t want to belong to any club that would have me as a member.

Then there’s the question of my politics. I hear you guys are conservative. Forgive me, then: I’d like to begin by acknowledging that we are standing on the ancestral, indigenous land of Leonard Leo. ProPublica tells me that Washington is his turf.

Then I googled Barbara Olson.

I had the privilege of editing some op-eds by Ted when I worked at the Wall Street Journal. I knew that his wife was murdered by al-Qaeda on 9/11. But over the past weeks I spent time reading about Barbara herself.

I read about a Texas girl, the daughter of German immigrants, who was ferociously independent. I read about how she, a Catholic, wound up at Cardozo Law School at Yeshiva University. And I read about how, when she was an intern at the Department of Justice, she was apparently the only person with enough chutzpah to personally serve papers to the PLO Mission at the UN telling them they were being expelled from the country because they were terrorists. 

I learned that she was on American Airlines flight 77 because she was headed to L.A. to be on Bill Maher’s show. . . and because she had changed her flight to have a birthday dinner with Ted.

And I learned that she had the composure and clarity and courage to call him not once but twice in those horrifying moments before the plane slammed into the Pentagon. 

There is a phrase Jews say to mourners when a person dies: may their memory be for a blessing. It is an expression of hope. It is so clear in the case of Barbara Olson—the way the force of her life and her character echoes on—that it is very much a blessing fulfilled.

To say that I am honored to give a lecture in the name of this exceptional woman would be an understatement. 

It is also, since the massacre of October 7—a date that will be seared into the memory of civilized peoples, alongside September 11—profoundly fitting. I do not think it is a coincidence that Israel is the only country, outside of America, that is home to a 9/11 memorial bearing all of the victims’ names.

Of course that is what we must talk about tonight. The civilizational war we are in. The war that took the life of Barbara Olson and 3,000 other innocent Americans on that morning in September 2001. The war that came, hideously, across the border from Gaza into Israel on that Shabbat morning a month ago. The war that too many had foolishly thought was over.

The physical war currently raging in the Middle East—with its questions about the way to defeat Hamas and other members of the jihadist death cult; the kind of operation Israel should currently be prosecuting in Gaza; how America should abandon its fatal appeasement of Iran; and a hundred other similar strategic questions—that is a subject for another speech, one for which there are many more qualified people to deliver. 

Tonight, I’d like to talk about the war of ideas and of conviction and of will that faces us as Americans. I want to talk about the stakes of that war. About how we must wage it—fearlessly and relentlessly—if we seek to build a world fit for our children, and if we want to save America itself.

By the time Americans woke up on October 7, 2023, it was clear that what had unfolded while we slept was not like previous wars or battles Israel has fought in its 75-year history. This was a genocidal pogrom. It was a scene out of the many places Jews had fled—a scene from the history of the Nazi Holocaust and of the European pogroms before that and of the Farhud, the 1941 massacre of Jews in Baghdad, a city that, it’s hard to believe now, was 40 percent Jewish at the beginning of the twentieth century—all of which remind us of Israel’s necessity.

The Hamas terrorists came across the border into southern Israel on foot and on motorbike. They came by truck and by car and by paraglider. And they came with a plan. They came to Israel to murder and maim and mutilate anyone they could find. That is what they did.

These Cossacks had smartphones. They called their families to brag that they had murdered Jews. Dad, Dad, I killed 10 Jews! Others filmed the slaughter with GoPros. Some used the cellphones of their victims to upload the footage of their torture and murder to their Facebook pages. In all of this, the terrorists are euphoric. No one who has watched the unedited footage fails to note the glee of the butchers.

Some Israelis were literally disappeared on October 7—burned at such high heat that volunteers are still sifting through the bones and the remnant teeth to identify them. But we know that more than 200 people are currently being held hostage by Hamas and that more than 1,400 were murdered in those terrible hours. Among the dead are some thirty American citizens. There are at least ten Americans among the hostages. 

All of which is why the immediate analogy the world reached for was to 9/11.

As with 9/11, the terrorists caught their victims by surprise on a clear blue morning.

As with 9/11, the spectacle and the savagery were the point. 

As with 9/11, the terrorists notched points on their sadistic scoreboard, taking from us not just precious lives, but our sense of our safety and security. They changed something within us.

The difference between 9/11 and 10/7—two massacres of innocent people, symbols to their killers of Western civilization—was the reaction to the horror.

The difference between 9/11 and 10/7 was that the catastrophe of 10/7 was followed, on October 8, by a different kind of catastrophe. A moral and spiritual catastrophe that was on full display throughout the West before the bodies of those men and women and children had even been identified.

People poured into the streets of our capital cities to celebrate the slaughter.

In Sydney, crowds gathered at the Sydney Opera House cheering “gas the Jews.” People rejoiced on the streets of Berlin and London and Toronto and New York.

Then came BLM Chicago using the paraglider—a symbol of mass death—as a symbol of freedom. Then came posters across our campuses calling for Israel to burn. Then came our own offices in New York City being vandalized with “Fuck Jews” and “Fuck Israel.” Then came Harvard’s task force to create safe spaces for pro-Hamas students.

Then, as thunder follows lightning, more dead Jews. An anti-Israel protester in Los Angeles killed a 69-year-old Jewish man for the apparent sin of waving an Israeli flag, though NBC’s initial headline made it hard to know: “Man dies after hitting head during Israel and Palestinian rallies in California, officials say.” 

In lockstep, the social justice crowd—the crowd who has tried to convince us that words are violence—insisted that actual violence was actually a necessity. That the rape was resistance. That it was liberation.

University presidents—who leapt to issue morally lucid condemnations of George Floyd’s killing or Putin’s war on Ukraine—offered silence or mealy-mouthed pablum about how the situation is tragic and “complex” and how we need to think of “both sides” as if there is some kind of equivalence between innocent civilians and jihadists.

But the most alarming of all were the young people who threw their support not behind the innocent victims of Hamas terrorism, but behind Hamas.

At George Washington University, a few miles from here, students projected the words “Glory to Our Martyrs” and “Free Palestine from the River to the Sea” in giant letters on campus buildings.

At Cooper Union in Manhattan, Jewish students had to hide in the library from a mob pounding on the door.

At Columbia, Professor Joseph Massad called the slaughter “awesome.” At Cornell, Professor Russell Rickford said it was “energizing” and “exhilarating.”

At Harvard, more than 30 student groups signed a petition that found a way to blame Jewish victims for their own deaths—saying that they “​​hold the Israeli regime entirely responsible for all unfolding violence.”

At Princeton, hundreds of students chanted, “globalize the intifada” which can mean only one thing: open season on Jewish worldwide.

At NYU, students held posters that read “keep the world clean” with drawings of Jewish stars in garbage cans.

Hip, young people with pronouns in their bios are not just chanting the slogans of a genocidal death cult. They are tearing down the photographs of women and children who are currently being held hostage in the tunnels that run under the Gaza Strip. They do so with pleasure. They laugh. They mock the 9-month-old baby who was stolen from his parents. 

In doing so, they are tearing down—or at least trying to tear down—-the essence of our common humanity, or even the reality that hostages were taken at all. Or maybe it’s that they are trying to extinguish the memory of the hostages, who to them are not worth saving … or actually had it coming to them. 

Or maybe—and I say this as the mother of a young child whose face I see in the face of every captive—they are trying to tear down the divine image that is at the root of our civilization’s conception of the dignity of every human life. 

What could possibly explain this?

The easy answer is that the human beings who were slaughtered on October 7 were Jews. And that antisemitism is the world’s oldest hatred. And that in every generation someone rises up to kill us. “They tried to wipe us out, they failed, let’s eat” as the old Jewish joke goes.

But that is not the whole answer. Because the proliferation of antisemitism, as always, is a symptom. 

When antisemitism moves from the shameful fringe into the public square, it is not about Jews. It is never about Jews. It is about everyone else. It is about the surrounding society or the culture or the country. It is an early warning system—a sign that the society itself is breaking down. That it is dying. 

It is a symptom of a much deeper crisis—one that explains how, in the span of a little over 20 years since Sept 11, educated people now respond to an act of savagery not with a defense of civilization, but with a defense of barbarism.

It was twenty years ago when I began to encounter the ideology that drives the people who tear down the posters. It was twenty years ago, when I was a college student, that I started writing about a nameless, then-niche worldview that seemed to contradict everything I had been taught since I was a child.

At first, things like postmodernism and postcolonialism and postnationalism seemed like wordplay and intellectual games—little puzzles to see how you could “deconstruct” just about anything. What I came to see over time was that it wasn’t going to remain an academic sideshow. And that it sought nothing less than the deconstruction of our civilization from within. 

It seeks to upend the very ideas of right and wrong.

It replaces basic ideas of good and evil with a new rubric: the powerless (good) and the powerful (bad). It replaced lots of things. Color blindness with race obsession. Ideas with identity. Debate with denunciation. Persuasion with public shaming. The rule of law with the fury of the mob.

People were to be given authority in this new order not in recognition of their gifts, hard work, accomplishments, or contributions to society, but in inverse proportion to the disadvantages their group had suffered, as defined by radical ideologues. 

And so, as an undergraduate, I watched in horror, sounding alarms as loudly as I could. I was told by most adults I knew that yes, it wasn’t great, but not to be so hysterical. Campuses were always hotbeds of radicalism, they said. This ideology, they promised, would surely dissipate as young people made their way in the world.

They were wrong. It did not.

Over the past two decades, I saw this inverted worldview swallow all of the crucial sense-making institutions of American life. It started with the universities. Then it moved beyond the quad to cultural institutions—including some I knew well, like The New York Times—as well as every major museum, philanthropy, and media company. It’s taken root at nearly every major corporation. It’s inside our high schools and our elementary schools. 

And it’s come for the law itself. This is something that will not come as a surprise to the Federalist Society. When you see federal judges shouted down at Stanford, you are seeing this ideology. When you see people screaming outside of the homes of certain Supreme Court justices—causing them to need round-the-clock security—you are seeing its logic.

The takeover of American institutions by this ideology is so comprehensive that it’s now almost hard for many people to notice it—because it is everywhere.

For Jews, there are obvious and glaring dangers in a worldview that measures fairness by equality of outcome rather than opportunity. If underrepresentation is the inevitable outcome of systemic bias, then overrepresentation—and Jews are 2 percent of the American population—suggests not talent or hard work, but unearned privilege. This conspiratorial conclusion is not that far removed from the hateful portrait of a small group of Jews divvying up the ill-gotten spoils of an exploited world.

But it is not only Jews who suffer from the suggestion that merit and excellence are dirty words. It is every single one of us. It is strivers of every race, ethnicity, and class. That is why Asian American success, for example, is suspicious. The percentages are off. The scores are too high. The starting point, as poor immigrants, is too low. From whom did you steal all that success?

The weeks since October 7 have been a mark to market moment. In other words, we can see how deeply these ideas run. We see that they are not just metaphors. 

Decolonization isn’t just a turn of phrase or a new way to read novels. It is a sincerely held political view that serves as a predicate to violence. 

If you want to understand how it could be that the editor of the Harvard Law Review could physically intimidate a Jewish student or how a public defender in Manhattan recently spent her evening tearing down posters of kidnapped children, it is because they believe it is just. 

Their moral calculus is as crude as you can imagine: they see Israelis and Jews as powerful and successful and “colonizers,” so they are bad; Hamas is weak and coded as people of color, so they are good. No, it doesn’t matter that most Israelis are “people of color.”

That baby? He is a colonizer first and a baby second. That woman raped to death? Shame it had to come to that, but she is a white oppressor. 

This is the ideology of vandalism in the true sense of the word—the Vandals sacked Rome. It is the ideology of nihilism. It knows nothing of how to build. It knows only how to tear down and to destroy. 

And it has already torn down so very, very much. The civilization that feels as natural to us as oxygen? That takes thousands of years, thousands of nudges of progress, thousands of risks, thousands of forgotten sacrifices to build up. But vandals can make quick work of all that. 

Reagan used to say that freedom is never more than one generation from extinction. The same can be said of civilization.

If there can be anything good that has come out of this nightmare that began on October 7 it is this: we have been shaken awake. We know the gravity of the stakes. And they are not theoretical. They are real.

So what do we do?

First: look. We must recover our ability to look and to discern accordingly. We must look past the sloganeering and the propaganda and take a hard look at what’s in front of our eyes. 

Look first at what just happened. At the barbarism that Hamas carried out.

Look at the reaction to it. Take stock of how profoundly the lies and the rot have traveled. How badly the forces of civilization are faring in this battle. How it is the most educated, the most pedigreed who have become the most morally confused. The suspect in the killing of Paul Kessler is a college professor. 

To see the world as it is, we must prize the distinctions between good and bad. Better and worse. Pain and not pain. Safety and danger. Just and unjust. Friends and enemies. 

I do not need “context” to know that tying children to their parents and burning them alive is pure evil, just as I do not need a history lesson on the Arab-Israeli conflict to know that the Arab Israelis who saved scores of Jewish Israelis that day are righteous.

Look at your enemies and your allies. 

And I say this more to myself than to you. Many of you have no doubt understood this longer than I have. But for many people, friends and enemies are likely not who they thought they were before October 7. Looking at who your friends and enemies are might mean giving up nice things. Giving up Harvard. Or the club. Or your New York Times subscription. . . wait, wrong crowd.

You get the point. The point is that things—that prestige—aren’t the point of our lives. Harvard and Yale don’t give us our value. We do. And something beyond ourselves. Something visible in those faces so many of our fellow citizens are determined to rip off the wall. And in the faces before me now.

In recognizing allies, I’ll be an example. I am a gay woman who is moderately pro-choice. I know there are some in this room who do not believe my marriage should have been legal. And that’s okay, because we are all Americans who want lower taxes.

But seriously: I am here because I know that in the fight for the West, I know who my allies are. And my allies are not the people who, looking at facile, external markers of my identity, one might imagine them to be. My allies are people who believe that America is good. That the West is good. That human beings—not cultures—are created equal and that saying so is essential to knowing what we are fighting for. America and our values are worth fighting for—and that is the priority of the day. 

The other thing to look for is the good. Look hard for the good and don’t lose sight of it.

New York coffee shop owner Aaron Dahan had all of his baristas quit when he placed an Israeli flag in the window and began fundraising for Magen David Adom—the Israeli Red Cross.

But his café didn’t close—quite the opposite. Suppliers sent him free shipments of beans and cups. Community members picked up shifts for free. There were lines around the block to buy a cup of coffee. The cafe made $25,000 in a single day.

Just this week, American cowboys from the Great Plains and the Rockies traveled to Israel to tend to the fields and animals of Israeli farmers who were killed in the past month. This is the opposite of the cheap solidarity of standing with Hamas that we see across our campuses and city centers. This is the essence of the West—of the idea that free societies must stand together.

It is not just, as I believe James Woolsey said, that we are all Jews now. The reverse is also true. Israel is a mirror for the West, and for the United States—whose founders saw a version of themselves in the biblical nation that also inspired modern Zionists whose grieving descendants today are looking toward America with gratitude, but also with alarm, sensing a shared struggle ahead. 

Second: we—you—must enforce the law.

The wave of elected so-called “progressive prosecutors” has proven to be an immensely terrible thing for law and order in cities across America. It turns out that choosing not to enforce the law doesn’t reduce crime. It promotes it.

It is no coincidence that many of the same activists who have pushed to “defund the police” are also now publicly harassing Jews. Everyone needs equal protection, not only of the law but from the forces of chaos and violence. In Brooklyn, there have been an unconscionable number of violent attacks against Orthodox Jews over the past decade, correctly identified as hate crimes. But they are also simply crimes that, if the law were upheld, would be far less likely to happen—whatever their motivation. 

Masking at a protest is illegal in many states so that it does not become an attempt at mass-intimidation, à la the KKK. Now maybe that’s a good idea—maybe it’s a bad one. But in nearby Virginia, it happens to be the law. And yet, as David Bernstein recently pointed out in Eugene Volokh’s blog, at George Mason University’s Fairfax campus nearly all the protesters at a recent Students for Justice in Palestine rally were masked and covered. Were they punished for breaking the law? I suspect if they had we would have read about it. 

The rallies would likely be less susceptible to erupting in violence if the attendants weren’t hiding their faces. So don’t allow selective enforcement of this law, or any others. If white supremacists can’t do it, then neither can antifa or Hamas sympathizers.

Third: no more double standards on speech.

Public universities are constitutionally forbidden from imposing content-based restrictions on free speech. And yet, that’s precisely what they’ve been doing. 

Ask any conservative—and I now know a few—who’s tried to speak at a public university and had a “security fee” imposed on them or had their speeches quietly moved off campus and into small, restrictive venues whether there aren’t brazen content-based restrictions on their speech imposed by public universities.

Private universities can legally restrict speech. But their restrictions may not be enforced discriminatorily. And yet, they are. 

Take Yale Law School. In 2021, law student Trent Colbert invited classmates to his “trap house,” in his announcement of a “constitution day bash” hosted by FedSoc and the Native American Law Students Association. It took 12 hours for administrators to process discrimination complaints, haul Colbert in for a meeting, and suggest his career was on the line if he didn’t sign an apology they penned on his behalf. The law school’s dean also authorized a message condemning Colbert’s language. Why? Because trap house was a term some claimed had racist associations with crack houses. 

But when Jewish students wrote to that dean some two weeks after the Hamas attacks, detailing the antisemitic vitriol they have received, they got a formulaic reply from her deputy, directing them to student support services.

For certain students, kid gloves. For others, the maw of whatever hate their classmates and professors can think of. The universities play favorites based on the speech they prefer, and the racial group hierarchies they’ve established. It’s a nasty game and they need to be called to account for it.

Fourth, accept that you are the last line of defense and fight, fight, fight.

If you study history and if you look at where Jews stand, for better and usually for worse, you will understand where a culture, where a country, where a civilization stands. Whether it’s on the way up or whether it’s on the way down. Whether it’s expanding its freedoms. Or whether it’s contracting them. 

Where liberty thrives, Jews thrive. Where difference is celebrated, Jews are celebrated. Where freedom of thought and faith and speech are protected, Jews tend to be, too. And when such virtues are regarded as threats, Jews will be regarded as the same.

As goes Ohio, so goes the nation. The Jews—please don’t quote me on this—are Ohio.

But nothing is guaranteed. The right ideas don’t win on their own. They need a voice. They need prosecutors.

Time to defend our values—the values that have made this country the freest, most tolerant society in the history of the world—without hesitation or apology. 

The leftist intellectual Sidney Hook, who broke with the Communists, and called his memoir Out of Step, used to implore those around him to “always answer an accusation or a charge” to not let falsehood stand unchallenged. 

We have let far too much go unchallenged. Too many lies have spread in the face of inaction as a result of fear or politesse. 

No more.

Do not bite your tongue. Do not tremble. Do not go along with little lies. Speak up. Break the wall of lies. Let nothing go unchallenged. 

Our enemies’ failure is not assured and there is no cavalry coming. We are the cavalry. We are the last line of defense. Our civilization depends on us.

It is a very rare thing for me not to be sitting at a Shabbat dinner table on a Friday night as the sun sets. So I hope you’ll allow me to close with a little bit of Torah.

Tomorrow in synagogue we will read the portion of the Torah where Abraham’s wife, Sarah, dies, at the ripe old age of 127. We read in the Bible that she died in Kiryat-arba—now Hebron—in the land of Canaan. We read that when she passes, “Abraham proceeded to mourn for Sarah and to bewail her.” 

And the very next verse goes like this: “Then Abraham rose from beside his dead, and spoke to the Hittites, saying, ’I am a resident alien among you; sell me a burial site among you, that I may remove my dead for burial.’ ” 

So that’s the first thing Abraham does: he buys a plot of land to bury Sarah. The second thing: he finds Isaac a wife.

The late great Rabbi Jonathan Sacks, who I was blessed to know, tells us this about the sequence of events: “Abraham heard the future calling to him. Sarah had died. Isaac was unmarried. Abraham had neither land nor grandchildren. He did not cry out, in anger or anguish, to God. Instead, he heard the still, small voice saying: The next step depends on you. You must create a future that I will fill with My spirit. That is how Abraham survived the shock and grief.”

This is how generations of Jews have survived. This is how all of us survive.

I am so honored to be here speaking in this place, in honor of someone who stood up courageously for the things that mattered most, and who was murdered by enemies of all that we are fighting for. 

May her memory be for a blessing. It is for me.

There is another phrase traditional Jews invoke when speaking of someone who has been murdered: Hashem Yikom Dama. May God avenge her death.

We leave vengeance to God. But fighting is for all of us. Especially when there is something so precious worth fighting for. 

Ted once said of Barbara that “Barbara was Barbara because America, unlike any place in the world, gave her the space, freedom, oxygen, encouragement, and inspiration to be whatever she wanted to be.” 

There is no place like this country. And there is no second America to run to if this one fails. 

So let’s get up. Get up and fight for our future. This is the fight of—and for—our lives. 

5:45 p.m. - 7:30 p.m.
Barbara K. Olson Memorial Reception

2023 National Lawyers Convention

East & State Rooms
The Mayflower Hotel
1127 Connecticut Avenue NW
Washington, DC 20006

Share

Description

(Ticketed event)

7:00 p.m. - 9:00 p.m.
Red Carpet After Party

2023 National Lawyers Convention

Chinese Room
The Mayflower Hotel
1127 Connecticut Avenue NW
Washington, DC 20006

Share

Description

Hosted by the Harvard Student Chapter (2024 National Student Symposium host)

Celebrate in style at the first annual Red Carpet After Party, co-hosted with the Harvard Student Chapter, and showcasing Katz on the Internet, FedSoc Studios’ most purrfect film.

Back to top
9:00 a.m. - 10:45 a.m.
Showcase Panel III: Originalism on the Ground

2023 National Lawyers Convention

Topics: Constitution
Grand Ballroom
The Mayflower Hotel
1127 Connecticut Avenue NW
Washington, DC 20006

Share

Event Video

Listen & Download

Description

Featuring:

  • Prof. John C. Harrison, James Madison Distinguished Professor of Law, University of Virginia School of Law
  • Hon. Randolph Moss, United States District Court, District of Columbia
  • Hon. Andrew S. Oldham, Judge, United States Court of Appeals, Fifth Circuit
  • Prof. Jed H. Shugerman, Boston University School of Law
  • Moderator: Hon. Gregory G. Katsas, Judge, United States Court of Appeals, District of Columbia Circuit

Speakers

Event Transcript

Nathan Kaczmarek:  Good morning. Good morning. Welcome, welcome. My name is Nate Kaczmarek, and it's my pleasure to serve as Vice President and Director of the Practice Groups for the Society. Welcome to Day Three of the 2023 NLC. I'm a little biased, but I think we've had an excellent two days. And, as you've come to expect over the years, we plan to keep the foot on the gas and finish off the conference with another great day of debate and discussion.

 

      A reminder to those of you seeking CLE: Please scan your QR code on the back of your programs to sign in and sign out today.

 

      As we start today, I'd be remiss if I didn't mention to you that my favorite lawyer is also my favorite veteran. My father, Bob Kaczmarek, served honorably in the Vietnam War, and I hope he is watching on the livestream today. And I want to say to him, and all the veterans joining us virtually, and those of you here in the audience here at the Mayflower, that we revere your service. We owe you a deep debt of gratitude, and I'd ask that we'd -- please join me in thanking all of them for their brave service.

 

      Before I -- excuse me. Before I turn to our great showcase panel, I wanted to flag for you a new project from the Practice Groups, which we are really proud of and think you will enjoy. Three weeks ago, we launched a new platform showcasing important legal and policy debates on our website. We've called this new web page "BriefCase," and it is designed to host, in one place, a debate that mimics the litigation process with short, written briefs, video recordings of oral argument, amicus briefs, and a poll for the public to choose the winner.

 

      On page 34 of your program, you can scan the QR code there, which will take you directly to the first debate, which asks the important administrative law question: Should Chevron doctrine stand -- should the Chevron doctrine stand? There you will see Practice Group executive committee member Mark Chenoweth from NCLA debate Professor Ron Levin of Washington University and Saint Louis School of Law. Polls opened on Thursday, with the start of the convention, so please check out the excellent debate and vote for who you think made the better case. Our hope is that many important Federalist Society debates will be presented by a BriefCase in the months and years to come.

 

      Turning to our showcase, it's a delight to welcome to the stage this all-star panel. We are fortunate once more to have the expert assistance of Judge Katsas to help us navigate this discussion. Judge Katsas was appointed to the United States Court of Appeals for the District of Columbia Circuit in 2017. Prior to that, he served as Deputy Assistant to the President and Deputy Counsel to the President. He previously in many senior positions at DOJ. He clerked for Judge Edward Becker of the Third Circuit, then Judge Clarence Thomas on the D.C. Circuit, and to Justice Thomas on the Supreme Court. Judge Katsas is a graduate of Princeton University and Harvard Law School. He is so generous to the Society, and we are always fortunate to have the benefit of his insights and expertise. Please join me in welcoming Judge Katsas and this great panel.

 

Hon. Gregory Katsas:  Thank you, Nate, and thanks to all of you for being here bright and early on a Saturday morning. Our topic is "Originalism on the Ground." This is largely a continuation of the first panel Thursday morning. We are not primarily focused on high-level theory. We're focused on some practical issues. When you try to operationalize originalism, one can do that as an academic writing originalist law review articles. One can do that as an advocate writing originalist briefs. One can, of course, do that as a judge either writing originalist opinions or taking a step back deciding whether or not to try.

 

      We have on our panel two very distinguished judges and two very distinguished academics, and collectively, the panel also has very significant experience as advocates. So we've got all the relevant perspectives covered, so let me just introduce our panelists and get things going.

 

      John Harrison is the James Madison Distinguished Professor of Law at the University of Virginia School of Law, where he teaches constitutional history, federal courts, and civil procedure. He graduated from Yale Law School, clerked for Judge Bork on the D.C. Circuit, and has served as counselor on international law for the State Department and as a deputy assistant attorney general in the Office of Legal Counsel.

 

      Andy Oldham is a judge on the Fifth Circuit. He graduated from Harvard Law School, clerked for Judge Dave Sentelle on the D.C. Circuit and for Justice Alito on the Supreme Court. And he served as an attorney advisor in OLC as Deputy Solicitor General for the State of Texas and as General Counsel to Governor Greg Abbott.

 

      Judge Shugerman is a law professor and the Joseph Lipsitt Scholar at the BU School of Law, where he teaches constitutional history, fed courts, and administrative law. He received a PhD and JD from Yale, won the Charles Fried Award of the Harvard FedSoc Chapter, and is working on a book questioning historical support for the unitary executive theory of the American presidency.

 

      Randy Moss is a judge on the district court for the District of Columbia. He graduated from Yale Law School, clerked for Judge Pierre Leval on the Southern District of New York and then for Justice Stevens on the Supreme Court, chaired the Regulatory and Governmental Affairs Department at Wilmer, Cutler, and served as the Assistant Attorney General for OLC.

 

      John, you're up first.

 

Prof. John Harrison:  Thank you. I'm going to act a little bit against-type as a law professor. Rather than giving you high-level theory, I'm going to try to make a practical suggestion based on actual facts. Whether a law professor will be able to do that, we will find out. First, the actual facts, then the practical suggestion.

           

      The actual facts and the practical suggestion are framed by something that happened in this room a few years ago when the Rosenkranz Lunch featured Richard Posner talking to Mike McConnell. At one point, Judge Posner was railing on the use of history in law—probably railing on originalism—making the point that the study of history requires an enormous amount of effort. As he said, "People devote their lives to this." Mike McConnell said, "The same might be said of economics."

 

      The room dissolved in laughter then, as it did now, appropriately. But both of them had a point. Posner was making the correct point that there are specialized bodies of knowledge—history and economics—the production of which requires a great deal, not only of expertise but of time and effort. Mike McConnell was making the point that that's true, but decision-makers, including judges, often have to make decisions about very sophisticated and complicated arguments concerning, for example, history or economics. There must be some way to reconcile that. And that's what I'm going to try to do in the next couple of minutes is talk about how hard it is—those are the observations. I have three examples of that—and then the actual practical, concrete suggestion. As I say, coming from a law professor, it may or may not be actually useful.

 

      The observations, the three examples, are to make the point that coming to grips with the work, the relevant information, the relevant evidence on lots of questions concerning, I'll say, originalism, basically original understanding of constitutional text—although that's not the only form of originalism—requires an enormous amount of effort. I'm going to give three examples of that.

 

      One, as you've heard, some people on this panel are involved in the ongoing debate on the unitary executive, in particular president's removal power. The example I want to give starts with the Myers case in the 1920s, decided by the Supreme Court, written by Chief Justice Taft. An opinion that is so long, you might call it Taftian. Taftian was a person of substantial size.

 

      Myers was argued in the fall of 1924. Chief Justice Taft assigned it to himself, worked on it the rest of the term, worked on it the whole summer, worked on it the next term, worked on it the next summer, had a heart attack in the process, and ended up, after almost two years, producing what we now know as the Myers case, which, as I say, is very, very long, was based on an enormous amount of personal original research by the Chief Justice, then lengthy exchanges among the justice's work by the Chief Justice's law clerk. They had only one in those days, who was the late Judge Steve Williams' father, interestingly, the Dickerman Williams. And, since then, there has been even more work on the issues that Chief Justice Taft discussed and raised, including recent work by Judge Shugerman.

     

      The point I want to make is, a decision-maker who wants to have an informed view on that doesn't need to spend a lifetime, doesn't need to spend as much time as Taft did or as much time as professors do, but does need to spend a whole lot of time on that. Getting familiar with the basics about the primary materials, understanding the secondary arguments, understanding what judges and lawyers and scholars have said requires an enormous investment of time. I'm going to say on that particular topic, the unitary executive and presidential removal power just being in a position to make an informed judgment about it is the concentrated work—I will say pulling numbers not completely out of the air—the concentrated work of days or weeks, maybe longer.

 

      Second example: Does the Fourteenth Amendment impose the Bill of Rights on the states? Justice Black did a lot of work on that, wrote a lengthy opinion in Adamson against California in the 1940s, a lengthy historical appendix to Justice Black's opinion, a lengthy response from Justice Frankfurter, and that was the beginning of a debate among judges, academics. A great deal was written about this by academics. In my view, that debate very much continues on a very important contribution to it that's, I think, not obviously a contribution to it, was made this year by Jud Campbell, now at Stanford.

 

      Again, my point is not you can spend your whole lifetime on that issue. You can. But there is now so much—both primary material and commentary—that, again, coming to an informed opinion on that requires for a judge, other decision-makers, somebody in OLC, for example, requires an enormous investment of time. That one, too, is the concentrated work of days or weeks. Okay. Those are two examples involving federal judges. We have federal judges in academics on the panel.

 

      My third example involves an academic, and now I'm going to quote Judge Oldham --

 

Hon. Andrew Oldham:  Oh, no.

 

Prof. John Harrison:  -- sorry -- who might think that academics spend too much time on high-level theory and said, "We need thick, original meanings. That is, we need more and more work that shows particular constitutional provisions, have objectively determinate meanings based on rigorous analysis and academic debate over relevant sources of original meaning. One response is: "And cold fusion and room temperature, superconductors would also be nice. Where's my flying car?" Well, we're working on it.

 

      An example of "working on it" is, in my view, the most impressive and sophisticated piece of original understanding scholarship ever done, published in 1950 by William Winslow Crosskey of the University of Chicago Law School, interestingly, my con law teacher's con law teacher. Crosskey wrote two volumes during his lifetime. There was a third volume published posthumously called Politics and the Constitution and the History of the United States. The two volumes are 1,175 pages long, and there are appendices. So maybe in response to Judge Oldham, what Crosskey did was an example of what everybody's grandmother is supposed to have said, "Be careful what you ask for. You might get it." [Laughter]

 

      Crosskey was, one, immensely knowledgeable about the original materials, about both the conventional original materials and 18th-century law. Crosskey was, two, a rigorous textualist originalist. He was hard-core on the methodological point. Crosskey was, three, a genius. He wrote all those together and took what are today and what were then extremely heterodox views.

 

      Crosskey didn't believe in enumerated powers. He didn't believe in judicial review of acts of Congress. He thought Erie was wrong. He thought that the Constitution created a uniform federal body of common law that the Supreme Court of the United States was supposed to administer. Like I said, Crosskey was a genius. I didn't say I agreed with him.

 

      Coming to grips with Crosskey, his work, and the commentary on it, once again, on any one of those issues, concentrated work of days or weeks coming to grips with everything Crosskey said because it's a system that works together, that's the concentrated work of weeks or months. Okay. Well, socialism is said to be a bad idea because it takes too many evenings. Originalism takes a certain amount of time. That's the observation, as I say, two justices and an academic.

 

      The concrete useful proposal directed to lawyers, academics, academics writing as amici as they sometimes do, and judges including, I think, sometimes especially judges not on the Supreme Court of the United States, is whenever you are talking about what conclusions you've reached about one of these topics that may require an enormous amount of time, try to understand and try to figure out which are the really hard parts, which are the questions that are the closest and that require the most attention? That, if you're an advocate or a judge, that can involve saying, "This is the weakest part of my argument." Well, for your audience to know what's the weakest part of the argument, what's the hardest question, can be very important.

 

      I'll just give one example having to do with the original meaning, having to do with the unitary executive, which is one of the things Taft talked about at great length: the debates in Congress in 1789 about removal power. I think that it's really important. I am perhaps the rare Unitarian who's not a removalist. I think it's very important to understand those debates in light of the context, which had to do with Senate involvement in removal. That's a view of mine on the substance. My meta-view that's relevant here is to make the point that what's sometimes called "contextual enrichment of people's statements," additional information about what people said in their context—every good lawyer knows you can't understand something outside of its context—requires not only additional information but very fine judgments.

 

      Because if you say in context, "That doesn't mean what you think it means," without looking at the context, you are saying that doesn't mean what you think it means. That doesn't mean what may be its literal -- what the literal message somebody was conveying was. That kind of very common, very important question requires fine judgment. Often, that's an important pressure point in an originalist-type argument. That's a point on which a reasonable person could go either way. It calls for judgment. And people who are making those arguments, I think, should be more candid when they come to something. "This is the hard part. This is where judgment has to be exercised." "Maybe something else is easy, but this is not." Again, I think that's something that a lot of people, including academics, don't do nearly as much as they should. Be prepared to say, "This is where my argument is weakest." "This is where you need to focus to economize on time because doing this requires so much time." That's what the observations are about.

 

      I will conclude by saying that this panel consists of federal judges and academics. All of us have one form or other of life tenure. One of the things we should be able to do with life tenure is be honest about the parts we're not so sure about. Justice Brandeis is supposed to have said that the practice of judges is to decide 51 percent and then write 100 percent. My concrete practical suggestion to everybody is when you've decided 51 percent, say you've decided 51 percent. That's how originalism on the ground should work because that's how law on the ground should work.

 

Hon. Gregory Katsas:  Andy.

 

Hon. Andrew Oldham:  Well, thank you very much. It's always a joy to be here. And I'll pick up where John left off with the point of agreement. And that is about epistemic humility. I agree 100 percent that one of the trickiest parts about -- it's certainly about being a judge—I'm sure it's true about being an academic as well—is that we were trying—it's also true about lawyers, I suppose -- which is that you're trying to write something that is clear, that is concise, and that is persuasive. And that is often intentioned with the idea of recognizing the limits of an argument. At the end of the day, judges have to write opinions, have to explain judgments. You have to explain to one side why they're winning or losing. And if you get down to the end and you say, "You're losing, but I'm not really sure why," that is not a particularly persuasive opinion.

 

      But I agree with John 100 percent that it is really, really important to have epistemic humility when it comes to originalism. As I was listening to his remarks, it was evocative to me that passage from Plato's Apology, which I'm sure everyone's read about the trial of Socrates, where Socrates goes off to talk to the purportedly wise man. And he gets into a dialogue with him, and he's trying to plumb the depths of this other man's knowledge or wisdom. And Socrates realizes relatively quickly that the man doesn't know very much about anything. And so, as he's wandering away, Socrates thinks to himself, "I am better off than he is, for he knows nothing, and thinks he knows; whereas I neither know nor think I know."

 

      And that is the -- I think so, too, with originalism in the sense that we really never know. One of the trickiest parts of originalism is something that my friend Steve Sachs wrote about in the Harvard Law Review last year, which is that we don't know what we don't know. And it's even worse, in my view, in some way in originalist inquiries because we don't even really know where to start or where to end, for that matter. It's not like there's some compendium of originalist instruction that says, "Well, you start with source A. And after source A, you go to source B, and then you go to source C, and you can stop when you get to source Z. That's not ever written down anywhere.

 

      And so, it sometimes seems when we're searching for originalist meaning—and this is true, I think, in the academy as much as it is in a case—we often start at some place that might appear random. It's difficult to explain to some external observer, "Why did you start with the English Bill of Rights?" Or "Why did you start at the founding?" Or "Why did you start at Magna Carta?" It's not exactly clear why you start in any particular place. It's not clear why you then trace that to another event. And then it's not clear why you stop in your search for—as John said, I wrote a response to Steve's piece in a plea for thick original meaning—how do you determine when it's sufficiently thick that you can then explain to the party A that they're going to win or party B that they're going to lose?

 

      And it's often seemed to me in trying to deal with some of these issues, both in thinking about academic papers but also in terms of thinking about original meaning in the context of cases and controversies, it has struck me that it seems a little bit like a hound searching a field for truffles. There's no particular place where you stop the truck and let the dog out to go looking. There's no particular rhyme or reason about how the dog is searching through the fields, sniffing, and finding any particular thing. And, once the dog finds something, you don't really know if it's actually a truffle or it's some other kind of mushroom or it's a rock. And so, it seems like it's very difficult in any particular set of circumstances to understand exactly how one is supposed to search for that original meaning.

 

      And so, that has led to some criticisms, which I think are important for originalists to confront. To which is, should we even try? Is the game even worth the candle? Or is the hunt even worth the beagle?

 

      In my view, we absolutely should try. I'm a very proud originalist, and I do think that the hunt is worthy of the effort. But I think that we should be very honest—and I agree, again, wholeheartedly with John on this—about the difficulty of the project, the reality of time constraints, and, really, resource constraints more generally. And, as a consequence, I think, when we make an originalist claim, it should be the smallest, most modest one that we feel a degree of confidence in making precisely because we do not know what we don't know. We do not know that the next article by Professor Harrison or Professor Shugerman is going to say, "Well, the original public meaning of constitutional provision—whatever the Fourteenth Amendment is—turns out it's not X or it's X prime or it's Y." And you never know what it is you have not read. And, as a consequence of that, you should be quite careful, I think, in the way that one goes about making originalist claims.

 

      And that leads to my second point, which is about originalism and precedent. One of the things I've been most -- I don't know if surprised is the right word. But one of the things I found most remarkable in my five or so years in my current job is the number of constitutional cases that we see where there is not a clear precedent totally on point that just dictates the answer. You can't just say, "See, AVB, we're done." And so, for originalists, that means that we then need to conduct some originalist inquiry to try to figure out what the correct answer is. And when you do that, it's not immediately obvious where the precedent -- where the power of precedent should start and stop versus the power of history and tradition should start and stop. Obviously, if the Supreme Court has said it, then for the inferior court judges, that's as good as scripture, and we can move on.

 

      But my court has a very big docket. We have a lot of precedent. There's a lot of it that goes back a long time. And it's not immediately clear how one reconciles a case that may not be quite on point but may be interesting or powerfully persuasive somewhere in that spectrum versus a history and tradition that has been developed by scholars in doing the hard work that Professor Harrison was talking about.

 

      So if you come across a source, you come across a scholar, you come across a PhD who has written a powerful exegesis on a particular provision, how does that then interact with another Fifth Circuit precedent or D.C. Circuit precedent that may be either not quite on point but perhaps close enough? And I think that feeds back to the first point, which is that when you are thinking about establishing those precedents—and this is particularly a plea to the judges—you should be a little bit careful about how much you actually feel confident in dictating for fear that you end up with egg on your face the next time Professor Harrison writes an article about it, and you realize that, in fact, you've missed the boat entirely.

 

      And then the last point I'd like to make, which is a little bit about the bench/academy divide, and as Professor Harrison had mentioned, this is one of my -- I don't know if frustration is the right word. Perhaps it's just a concern. But one of the criticisms of originalist judges—and which I think is understandable—is this concern about—it's true about lawyers, too, I suppose -- law office history, or, as I think Justice Kagan has referred to it, law chambers history. And the idea is that, well, maybe you don't need a PhD in history to study a particular constitutional provision and come up with its original public meaning, but you do, at least, need to have some dedicated research agenda such that it's outside of a particular case and controversy, that it's not -- it doesn't have a litigation focus, so it has a broader horizon. It has a better ability to consider holistically a particular provision of history or a—I'm sorry—a particular period of history and how it interacts with a particular constitutional provision. And the idea being that we really don't want either associates in law firms or law clerks in judicial chambers working on these things and trying to answer these big, monumental constitutional questions in the context of particular cases, both because of a competency concern, also because of a time concern, also the fact that cases and controversies may not -- any particular one may not be the proper way or the lens through which to view these questions.

 

      Okay. Well, I understand that concern. I've heard it powerfully made in the past. And if we just take it as true for a moment, then I guess the one question is: Where do you go to find -- if we don't like that, what is the alternative? And so, Professor Harrison gave one good example. There's obviously lots of really great examples of people who have dedicated years, decades, entire lifetimes to studying particular provisions of the Constitution. There are entire theories of the original public meaning of this or that provision, the Fourth Amendment or Fifth Amendment.

 

      But these things are constantly evolving. We're constantly finding new theories of originalism. Those theories of originalism are constantly interacting with historical materials in new and different ways. And one of the concerns that I have often had is that if you just -- I was in the run-up to this conference, I was just -- went onto the home pages of three or four law reviews that everyone, I'm sure, in the room has heard of, and if you just look at the kind of stuff that's being published on the day-to-day basis, or month-to-month basis, or article-to-article basis, there's a lot of law and education or law and this or that policy or law and this or that particular salient political event. And there's not a ton of "Here is a dedicated, staked-out position on the original public meaning of how the First Amendment applies to prior restraints, or how the First Amendment applies to the establishment of religion, or how the" -- these big issues that interact in the cases that federal courts are asked to decide.

 

      And I'm not in any way suggesting that—I don't want to be confused on this—that somehow the academy exists to make judges jobs easier or that lawyers should be—I'm sorry—that the academics should be particularly concerned with what judges are doing necessarily. I think there's a huge role to be had in the academy for just the freedom of thought and the ability to study things that are interesting and to write those papers.

 

      But the thing that I think is particularly interesting is that there are circumstances where the academy and the bench do have to interact with one another. And it does happen where a judge will say, "Well, I think the original public meaning of this is X." And then there is a cacophony of criticism from people who are historians or academics who say, "What a buffoon," to which one answer from the judge might be, "Well, gosh, I sure wish I'd heard about that before I had to decide the case."

 

      And so, I wanted to give one example of what I mean by this. If we could put up the slides, I'll show you. This is a case from my court. I had nothing to do with this case. This is what a case involving a huge constitutional issue sometimes looks like in the Fifth Circuit. So this is a case everyone's heard of. This is Rahimi. So this is a post-Bruen case involving a Second Amendment challenge to a provision in Title XVIII in the Gun Control Act of 1968. So this is what the briefing looks like originally. So there is a briefing notice. There is one brief and a response brief, and briefing is complete. Okay. So that's like the entirety of what is given to a panel of my colleagues to decide this question. Now, admittedly, this is before Bruen. Okay. So that's Rahimi.

 

      So this is what the United States government has to say about the constitutionality of this provision in 922(g). This is in that one brief that the government files admittedly before Bruen. Okay? So after Bruen, the panel issues this directive and says, "Hey. Can we get some supplemental briefs because we're really concerned about whatever -- how does Bruen apply to this question? And this is what my colleagues got: appellant's supplemental brief, appellee's supplemental brief, and a reply brief. So we've got at least three more briefs, so everything's working out great.

 

      Well, look at what it looks like. This is just at the cert stage of the Supreme Court of the United States. This is just the amicus briefs in support of the petitioner. Here's the merits: page 1, page 2, page 3.

 

[Laughter]

 

      I know. And that's just the one side. Let's look at the other side. This is now in favor of the respondents. One, two -- so we could go on all day to show it to you. And I don't really have a firm view on this, necessarily how what the implications of it are. I just think that it's a remarkable challenge to originalism and practice, the topic of our panel. When you look at the way these things get actually litigated, there are a lot of people who have a lot of stuff to say when the Supreme Court grants it, and this goes back to something, I think, to end on a point of agreement that I have with Professor Harrison.

 

      It takes a lot of time. I don't think in any way that people who have PhDs in history are necessarily monitoring the Fifth Circuit's docket or any other courts of appeals docket for every one of these cases. But, nonetheless, inferior court judges across the United States are being asked to make decisions in these big constitutional questions and having to look somewhere to find the answers. If it's not going to be on the front page of the Stanford Law Review or the Yale Law Review or whatever, and it's not going to be in the briefing, and we don't want them to be doing law office history or whatever, then it's not immediately obvious. It's a lot of nos. It's not exactly obvious to me what is the yes. So, with that, I'll turn it over. Thank you.

 

Hon. Gregory Katsas:  Jed.

 

Prof. Jed Shugerman:  Great. Well, it's such an honor to be here. This is actually my first Federalist Society National Lawyers Convention. But over the course of -- yeah, this is going to be my fifth Federalist -- one of five of my Federalist Society or Federalist Society adjacent events.

 

      Elena Kagan said, way before she was on the Supreme Court -- she said at a Federalist Society event, "You are not my people." Now, I will say I have never voted for a Republican in my life, as far as I know. And yet, especially after last night, I think you are my people. I thought Bari Weiss was extraordinary, and I thought your support for what she had to say was also appreciated. And she speaks the truth, I think.

 

      But to the point that I want to address here, is that it was before October 7th that I was looking around and looking for a respect for intellectual diversity and debate. I did win a Federalist Society prize, as someone on the left, for bringing intellectual diversity and debate to a classroom where I gave voice to conservative and libertarian students. So I think that's part of the background here. But, over time, it's also that I am an originalist. At some point, I described myself as a progressive originalist. I no longer use that phrase. I think it's just an originalist and not in terms of -- I have a lot of respect for what Elizabeth Wydra is doing at the Constitutional Accountability Center, but one of her arguments was to the left there's a lot of good results. I am not a strategic originalist. I am just an originalist, full stop. And I do remember a point --

 

      But I will also say I'm an originalist in theory. And one reason why I'm on this panel is that I have some questions about originalism in practice that we're all addressing. It is enormously complicated. And I've also learned from experience of my own mistakes, which I'll talk about. And I've written or co-written five amicus briefs for the Supreme Court. And six emoluments amicus briefs somehow never got to the Supreme Court, but I have some observations and some of my own learning from that experience.

 

      But what I will say about originalism: A student asked a question: What should those here say to students who challenge them about originalism is immoral or it's the dead hand? And I think the answer -- the basic answer is that's what law is. It is text and context. Now, I would add that my view of originalism is that it's a lexical ordering. It means that there are other sources that are helpful. But my view is that text and context are the first-order lexical starting point, and only when that evidence is unclear do you go to other sources of law, like precedent.

 

      What I will talk a little bit about, and I'm picking up on the panel—the terrific panel from yesterday—on stare decisis, is I think there needs to be a more robust conversation about burdens of proof and who bears the burden of proof. And I'll talk a little bit about that. Given that there are different norms about the burden of proof from a legal system where the plaintiff bears the burden of proof versus if originalism is a historical project, historians have a different ordering of who has the burden of proof. It's those who make a positive historical claim. X meant Y; you bear the burden of proof. And that works out differently in different kinds of cases with originalism. And if it's about originalism and the Constitution, it also has to be reflective of Article V and supermajorities.

 

      So what kind of consensus do you need? I think that burden is relatively high. So my view of originalism is there's a lot of space, after text and context, to get to other sources of meaning because that burden of proof to establish what the Constitution meant for a broad consensus of society has to be a high burden of proof, generally, if you're making a claim.

 

      And the third thing—I'm just picking up on this quick question of burden of proof—there's also question about judicial role, about whether the judge is asked to do something that is activist in terms of overturning a precedent or overturning a federal or a state statute. In the same case, those things can conflict, but I think it's important to think about that as well. So I'd like to see if we can have a conversation about that given that we have this terrific panel with judges who have a harder job than we do in having to have a much broader docket and have limits on time, as Professor Harrison and the Honorable Judge Oldham have both commented on.

 

      So let me say a couple of words about my experience in writing amicus briefs engaged with the Court.

 

      So one is some of you may have been introduced to me on the page of the New York Times, apologizing for a mistake I made in one of the emoluments briefs. And this is the fog of litigation and one of the challenges. And it was in a district court, but—picking up on Judge Oldham's point—it was good that this was a mistake in a district court brief that we could then air out and not make that mistake again. But it was an apology to Seth Barrett Tillman and to Josh Blackman about a mistake that -- I was not the most prominent historian on this brief, but it was a mistake that I played a significant role in making about a Hamilton document.

 

      So, without going into the details there, I think this is my own learning about—we would call here—epistemic humility or interpretive humility. I recommend a piece by Heidi Kitrosser called "Interpretive Humility" that I think connects with what we're saying about burdens of proof.

 

      But the other observation is that doing archive, this was a mistake related to trying to figure out whether a document in the National Archives, with what appeared to be Alexander Hamilton's initials was, in fact, his initials or not. I don't think that's covered in law, in 1L or 2L or 3L. And one mistake we made was over-relying on something that a couple of us had learned in grad school about the signing conventions of the way that documents were archived in the 18th century. And we had assumptions that what we learned in our PhD program were -- we relied on those conventions. Turns out those conventions were wrong. But thankfully, there was a debate, and I think it's important to acknowledge when one has made a mistake. So, again, if Josh or Seth are out there anywhere, again, my apologies.

 

      But then one other point is about this work, this is not an emoluments brief, but I did some work on the unitary executive theory on the word "vesting." And when I placed that article, I had a conversation with Larry Solomon. I'm not sure if Larry is here. But Larry gave me some very constructive feedback that -- what I had done, is I had looked at something like 100 different dictionaries from the 1600s even into the 19th century about the word "vesting" that showed that there are assumptions about the word "vesting" throughout the Constitution that do not mean what we think they mean. I think I'm paraphrasing The Princess Bride here. I hope that somebody -- some people got that. Inconceivable.

 

      So the idea about -- so there's an assumption that—and this is something that we call "semantic drift." Julian Mortenson has used this very effectively—that we have presentist or modern assumptions about the words we use. And we all, in our con law classes, read Chief Justice Marshall's opinions from Fletcher v. Peck, or etc.—Dartmouth case—that talk about vested rights. And we assume that that word "vested" means legislatively indefeasible. Well, it turns out that in the dictionaries in usage, that vesting only gained this meaning—it shifted—its semantic meaning shift in the 19th century given written constitutions.

 

      So that was the main find -- what was one of my findings. And Larry Solomon said, "Well, you're over-relying on dictionaries. And he's right. I was over-relying on dictionaries. He said, "You have to look at usage." And so, then, taking that seriously, I went—with research assistants—went through the archives -- went through the databases to look for every use of the word "vesting" by the Founders from -- in one of the databases that's at the University of Virginia from 1776 to 1789.

           

      And I found something that, frankly, I was not looking for, and it surprised me. But it became clear that there were different flavors of vesting. So there were fully -- there were references to something being "fully vested." And Washington would often refer -- or if something was delegated to General Washington, it might be fully vested in Washington or an officer or might be fully vested from Washington to another officer in a military context. Tax policy, tax rules often had this usage. And there were also references to things being partly vested or temporarily vested.

 

      And it became clear that vesting didn't have its own clear meaning, but there were flavors of vesting, including all vested, all power being vested, plenipotentiary. And it dawned on me, "Well, wait a second. There is a place in the Constitution that uses—tell me if you -- stop me if you've heard -- if you think you can recognize this phrase—"all legislative power shall be vested in a Congress of the United States."

 

      And it struck me without looking for it and without, frankly, sympathizing with this view as of "on the left," but realizing as a commitment to originalism, I added to the article after it was placed, frankly, in the Stanford Law Review. I thought, "I want to get this right." And I said, "There is an argument here from this evidence in favor of the nondelegation doctrine. That when the framers were writing the Article I and Article II, this cuts against the unitary executive theory because the word "all" is not used there. Article II says, "The executive power shall be vested in a president." But Article I says, "All legislative power"—and I don't think it's just the "here" and "granted" that limits that. I think there is a -- and there is a context to that. In terms of the realities of 18th-century governance and republicanism, it was very important to have all power vested in your democratic and republican body. But realistically, in the 18th century, there was too much decentralization -- no cell phones, no airplanes. Executive power needed to be more decentralized. So in pursuing a unitary executive question, I stumbled on evidence that supports the nondelegation doctrine.

 

      But I do ask a question to those who have been filing briefs. I'm just noting that no one has ever cited my article for any nondelegation argument in amicus brief. And I think that's reflective of our silos. And one reason why I'm here is not just that, increasingly, I think I want to talk to people who are serious about the rule of law, having filed -- right? Sidenote: I filed an amicus brief in Biden v. Nebraska, and I did not file it on behalf of the Biden administration. But I think it's important for these conversations that there are -- and I also want to emphasize that in the legal academy, there are more and more JD-PhD historians who understand and take seriously the idea of original public meaning. So I'm here to learn from you, but you're also welcome to cite my work if you'd like to.

 

      And on another note about this research, I take what John Harrison is saying very seriously about the complexity of this material. And there's also a challenge when publishing law review articles about what the conventions are. And so, one experience I had in publishing "Indecisions of 1789" about the problems with unitary executive theories and interpretations of the first Congress, I submitted it as a 50-page article. It then became -- it grew to 114 pages. I do not think the editors -- let me just appreciate all the extra work they did there. And, at the same time, I couldn't give all the block quotes from speeches. So I had to -- so they asked me to publish separately a 60-page document in SSRN. And the way that I tried to resolve this was using an SSRN document that was cited that they didn't publish but that I could go and give several paragraphs from the original source and let readers decide for themselves.

 

      So I just want to suggest this is another way to engage in originalism is it's hard for judges and clerks to get the full sources. Briefs also have very limited page numbers and word counts. So one thing I've learned is how to use SSRN to then give those who want to dig into the materials without having to figure out if it's been uploaded to a database you can search for, give them the full quotes.

 

      What I want to end on here is just saying that one reason why I'm here is that I think it's important to recognize that originalism needs—as the co-panelists have mentioned—epistemic humility. And I think one observation I want to make is that it's also true of originalism, now that there is such a big super majority on the Supreme Court, to sympathize with certain outcomes without necessarily having all of the requisite experience and expertise to deal with these historical materials.

 

      I think there is a -- there is a risk—and I say this as someone who cares about originalism—is to save originalism from itself. I think there are some overreaches that are happening. I did post yesterday, on SSRN, a document that gives a little bit more background to this.

 

      I'm writing a couple of essays about some of these concerns. And one essay I've titled "Heads I Win, Tails You Lose Originalism." And just to summarize some of these concerns about the way the history gets used, sometimes post-ratification evidence is relevant, except when it's not. Sometimes Marbury v. Madison is relevant, except when it's dicta. And so, state constitutions are evidence about executive power, except when they're anti-models on executive power. British Crown is relevant for the unitary executive theory, but the English Parliament is not. And I explain how these different brief writers have shifted -- have played a shell game with which material is relevant.

 

      And in the lion's den, I will also say Steve Calabresi filed an amicus brief where, in one page, he says that English precedent is of "doubtful relevance" because of the differences between the separation of powers. And then, a few pages later, he goes on to cite British colonial administration as a positive model for executive power. I'd just like to say this is an example of heads I win, tails you lose. Colonial British administration is mostly an anti-model for why we needed a written constitution in 17 -- the state constitutions in the 1770s and the U.S. Constitution. It's the way we understand the Bill of Rights. Colonial British administration is usually the anti-model for the context of the Constitution, except in Steve Calabresi's brief, where suddenly it is the model for executive power.

 

      I think one lesson here is we need to have both historians' norms as well as lawyerly norms about trying to get -- have some methodological consistency about what material is relevant and try and theorize that methodologically so that we're consistent and not just trying to achieve ideological results.

 

Hon. Gregory Katsas:  Randy.

 

Prof. Randolph Moss:  All right. Well, thank you. And let me start by applauding Professor Shugerman because I think all of us need to keep in mind that what is ultimately most valuable is the rule of law and the truth. And I think all of us, whether we're judges or academics, in what we're doing need to hold those values most highly. And wherever the best analysis of the law and history takes us, that's where we should go with it. So I applaud those sentiments from everyone here on the panel today.

 

      With respect -- with respect to history, I'll go back to Professor Harrison's reference to Judge Posner. And the truth of the matter is that very few, if any, federal judges have PhDs in history. But it is also the truth that we can't ignore history and that we cannot decide cases in historical vacuums, and we need to understand the context in order to do our best to get the cases and the decisions right. But I think at the same time, Judge Posner's observation is valuable in that we should do so with humility, caution, care, and also thinking about the different contexts in which this comes up. And I want to just touch on some of the challenges as judges that we face in using history.

 

      And the first challenge, which has been touched on today -- Professor Shugerman talked about this. He's, I think, posted for the CLE a brief that he wrote in the Jarkesy case. But our understanding of history is not static. History is static. The facts from the past are what they are. But our understanding of those facts are not static.

 

      I think we should think about what rules actually should apply with respect to the overruling of precedent when it turns out that precedent was based on a historical mistake. There is a jurisprudence on how you think about and the rules relating to when to overrule precedent. But I'm not aware of anything that actually struggles with that question or thinks about how do you think about overruling precedent when it's based on a historical error and then how confident are you that it is an error when the point that -- when you reach that point?

 

      Second point is to think about how do you go about historical fact-finding? When I told my son, who was a third-year law student, that I was going to do this panel, he said, "Dad, stay in your lane."

 

[Laughter]

 

      And what I think he meant by that was, "You're going to be on a panel with some distinguished scholars who spend all of their time thinking about these questions. You've got another job that you spend most of your time thinking about. And so, don't go on a panel like this and start opining on theories of originalism and interpretation when you're dealing with people who think about this day in and day out for years every day."

 

      And the same thing goes for how you think about history and, as judges, how we think about applying history. It's not something that we're doing on the ordinary day. But we have to make those judgments. And how do we go about doing it?

 

      One of the oddities about this is, ordinarily, findings of fact are primarily the providence of the district courts. And in this context, it's almost flipped. And as Judge Oldham made clear in his slides, a lot of times -- if you looked at the district court, the docket would have no amicus filings, probably at all, and it gets reversed. And it's only by the time these cases get to the Supreme Court that you see stacks and stacks of amicus briefs with historians presenting it.

 

      Now, not every historical fact is the same. And there's not a lot of uncertainty—although there may be some uncertainty, actually, involved in picking up a dictionary and reading a dictionary. And I would have thought, actually, before I sat down here today to say, "Well, you can pick up a dictionary from 1789, see what it says, and that's pretty certain." But it turns out that maybe isn't so certain.

 

      But there are different types of uncertainty and historic doubt that can arise. In some cases, it's less difficult. In other cases, it's more difficult. And in some cases, issues are hotly contested. And in other cases, they're less hotly contested.

 

      Again, I could be wrong about this, but my impression is, for example, in the Confrontation Clause jurisprudence, in the history of the Confrontation Clause, and going back to the trial of Sir Walter Raleigh, that in Crawford, that was not hotly contested -- that history. It may have been contested what the implications were of the history. But other times, I think the history is going to be contested. What do you do with competing amicus briefs? You have the one stack on one side and the other side. And they're telling you different things about history.

 

      And you're -- as an appellate judge or as a Supreme Court justice, how do you go about resolving that? I can tell you, the district court, if I have a -- if I have a factual dispute, I want to bring those witnesses in. I want to have them on the stand, and I want to ask -- even experts -- I want to ask them my own questions. And I'm not content. And I tell you, very rarely am I content just picking up an expert report, and reading it, and saying, "Oh, okay." Or particularly when there are competing ones and knowing what I think the right answer is. I want to be able to ask them questions.

 

      Supreme Court justices, they can ask the advocates questions, but they don't have those historians in front of them. And, again, I'm not suggesting that every historical question is like this. But could you imagine a case that turned on an important question of science in which -- not litigated in the district court. Litigated in passing in the courts of appeals. And it gets to the Supreme Court, and there are stacks of amicus briefs by scholars of organic chemistry on one side and scholars of organic chemistry on the other side. The Supreme Court would remand that and say, "You've got to go back down and sort that out. We're not going to decide some question of organic chemistry based on the amicus briefs."

 

      And I'm not suggesting that all history, or even most of it, is like that. But I really raised that point to show the challenge of deciding difficult questions of historical fact in a world in which there oftentimes is not tremendous percolation, even in the courts of appeals, before it reaches the Supreme Court. And it gets teed up for the first time in the Supreme Court with amicus briefs. And, although I would like to think and hope that the authors of each of those amicus briefs are approaching it with a scholar's independence and objectivity, I think in truth at least many of those amicus briefs are written by people who, for instrumental purposes, who have a view in where they want to come out on an issue.

 

      And which raises the question of how much confidence should the judge or the justice place in those amicus briefs, which you'll have to, again, go read all the sources themselves, original sources. Do they need to go to the archives at UVA and go through them?

 

      The third point is, in light of that uncertainty, what do we do? And there are different types of uncertainty. And I think this can inform the relevant jurisprudence and perhaps the questions of the relevant burdens of proof or how judges think about it. There may be uncertainties simply because a question is an obscure one, and it just hasn't been studied much in academia. Again, in some worlds, the Supreme Court or the courts of appeals might allow the question to percolate in the lower courts first before they decide the issue or would want some further development. But what do you do when there's just not that much out there? And even by the time it gets to the Supreme Court, it may be that scholars run out then and start doing the research at that point in time. But that may be six months or a year of research versus a decade or decades of research.

 

      There's other types of uncertainty. There may be questions where the framers themselves weren't in agreement. There may be circumstances where they were intentionally vague because they weren't in agreement about an issue. It may be that there are issues that just never occurred to them. It may be that there is no historical analog to go to where the historical analogs are just not terribly helpful. And so, I think thinking about the type of uncertainty can inform how you go about approaching it.

 

      And the fourth point is -- and I think this touches on my opening comment about the need to be objective and open-minded and take things where they -- to reach results that really represent the rule of law. And that is, I think that there is a risk when you're relying on history that you're going to fall into the same trap that people, decades ago, fell into with respect to legislative history. And Judge Harold Leventhal famously observed that legislative history, at least at times, can be like going to a cocktail party and looking across the room for the heads of your friends. And there's, I think, the same risk, at least at times or in some circumstances, with respect to historical evidence and where there's a large historical record. There's a risk of going out and finding your friends in that historical record rather than stepping back and approaching it with real objectivity and figuring out which are the most important pieces of the historical record.

 

      And I think in that context, we, as judges and as academics, need to think about how to maintain public confidence in the work of the academics in the judiciary and make sure that we don't fall into the trap of finding our friends in the historical record.

 

      So my bottom line is is we need history. We need to understand history. We need to do our best with it to decide cases fairly and correctly, but we also have to do so with caution and need to consider the types of history and the types of -- the different types of traps that we can fall into and make sure that we avoid those.

 

Hon. Gregory Katsas:  I'm going to give the panelists a chance to comment on anything they'd like from the co-panelists in order to make sure we have plenty of time for questions. I'll ask you to try to keep it to maybe two or three minutes.

 

      John?

 

Prof. John Harrison:  Thanks. I want to -- the particular thing—because, of course, economizing on time is very important—that I'm going to talk about is what Judge Moss was just discussing.

 

      Seems to me that it would be a really good idea for courts, with the assistance of lawyers and academics, to develop a way to deal with new historical learning, to develop a -- to develop a way to adjust, when appropriate, their understandings, including of the Constitution itself, based on new knowledge. That would require, I think, some adjustment in the way principles of stare decisis operate. Judgments might be taken; opinions might be taken as standing for propositions with the explicit understanding that the decision was made on the basis of the data available understanding and the data available learning.

 

      I mentioned Crosskey. I mentioned my con law teacher, who was Crosskey's student. My con law teacher started off in antitrust. He would later write a book called The Antitrust Paradox. And one of the things that has happened in antitrust law over the decades, in part because of then Professor Bork's work, was that judges came to think that they had a better understanding of the economic principles that are made relevant by the quite abstract concepts built into the antitrust statutes, mainly the Sherman Act.

 

      They had, they thought, a means of doing evolution of their doctrine based on better understandings, based on new learning, largely in economics to get back to Posner and McConnell. That shows that it's possible. And I hope that if concerns about the original understanding, concerns about the original meaning of the Constitution and statutes continue for a substantial period of time, as I say that judges and lawyers will start to develop techniques to develop and evolve precedent and understand they shouldn't be locked into something they said 40 years ago now that there's been new learning.

 

Hon. Gregory Katsas:  Andy. Andy.

 

Hon. Andrew Oldham:  Thanks. I'm going to pick up on one thing that Professor Shugerman said that I agreed with the remarks.

 

      But one of the things that you highlighted, which I think is really, I think, important about the heads I win, tails you lose theory of originalism, is one of my principal concerns has been that we don't have a generally accepted order of operations. When it comes to economics, of which I have just enough background to be dangerous, there are certain rules. There are certain -- it is at the end of the day—some of it, anyway—math. And there are certain generally accepted assumptions about how one goes about calculating GDP, or, even in microeconomics, how one goes about figuring out what the marginal costs and marginal revenues are. There are things that we can at least -- if you got a group of a hundred economists together, we would agree on how to write the equations. We may disagree about some of the theories. We may disagree about some of the applications. But there's some bedrock conception of how one goes about doing it.

 

      But one of the things that I think that you've raised that's really important is that when it comes to originalism, why do we -- why in one case, would you start with Elliot's Debates? Why, in another case, would you start with colonial practice? Why, in a difference, does it matter what the state constitutions say? Why is it sometimes that the colonial practices is the anti-rule? And why is that we're sometimes deviating from English practice?

 

      And so, part of it is like, how do we know when something is evidence of the absence of constitutional meaning or the anti-Constitutional meaning? But some of it's also, is it's not completely obvious to me how we even go about figuring out the step A, step B, step C, much less where we stop. When can we finally be confident and say, "Okay. Well, that's good enough for this case. And we can, therefore, have reached the 51 percent confidence interval that Professor Harrison mentioned in his opening." And, "Judgment for the plaintiff." And I think that's one of the biggest challenges of originalism in practice is figuring that out and legitimizing in a sufficient way so we can explain to a party, "This is why we're going to rule this way. It's because we are confident that we started in the right place. We took the right steps, and we ended in the right place, at least as to today."

 

Hon. Gregory Katsas:  Great.

 

Hon. Andrew Oldham:  Thanks.

 

Prof. Jed Shugerman:  Good. I'm happy to pick up right there because I'm actually struggling with this problem. Don't get me wrong. Just because I've said, "Well, sometimes some sources get used." Sometimes the British Crown is cited, but sometimes -- when it's convenient for the argument. But parliament is dismissed because of the Americans rejected parliamentary supremacy.

 

      Sometimes, that's true. Sometimes -- but you need evidence to explain why it's one versus the other rather than just make those assertions. And, frankly, I'm getting feedback about a paper I have -- I posted on the history of venality or freehold offices that there was a robust tradition that went into the 19th century in England where there was the sale of office. And the exchange for the sale of office was then, once you bought an office, some of those offices were family property that would be passed along.

 

      And Montesquieu wrote about this in Book 5, Chapter 19 of the Spirit of Laws. And the pushback has been, "Well, the sale of offices and the ownership of office was part of a monarchic or aristocratic system and not a republican system." And one way I've got to deal with that is to say, "Well, that's reflective of a lack of consensus about offices because some of those practices continued." But I have to make that argument more clear. I think it was an exposition. I think in my head, I knew that was a distinction, but as I've gotten feedback from moderate, conservative, and liberal scholars—who all have different problems with where this research goes—I'm now trying to be more careful about avoiding the heads I win, tails you lose problem.

 

      But I also -- I appreciated Judge Moss's reference to the going to a cocktail party and finding your friends. I also go to the originalism conference. I went last year to the San Diego and one thing that I -- and it was tremendously helpful, and I appreciated the feedback I got. But one thing I heard in the comments based upon research was -- well, there was a phrase that came up, and someone in the audience said, "Well, just go into the databases and hit Control-F and look for that word. And now, in addition to this essay I've just posted—again, on SSRN Heads I Win, Tails You Lose Originalism, get it wherever your SSRN documents are sold—I'm also going to be writing an essay called “Ctrl-F Originalism,” where the risk is that you go to a database, and you Control-F your friends. Just to be clear, Control-F, the F stands for find.

 

[Laughter]

 

      I think one last thing I'll say is about epistemic humility and judicial activism versus judicial restraint. I also went to the Boyden Gray Center in September at Scalia Law School, and Mike Ramsey presented a terrific paper about the major question doctrine. And one observation is that—and there's a risk here, but when there is doubt about the -- let's say, a constitutional doctrine like the nondelegation doctrine, the backup -- and I want to -- again, this is breaking from my ideological bedfellows—that's just a metaphor, by the way—that I defend the major question doctrine. And one defense of the major questions doctrine—Mike Ramsey made this more clear—Scalia said in Mistretta that because the nondelegation doctrine is so hard to administer—and, also, maybe there's also this epistemic doubt about its scope—the major question doctrine is most justifiable, not in Amy Coney Barrett's terms in our concurrent Judge Barrett's terms in her concurrence as textualism. It really is, I think, in Gorsuch's conception, a doctrine of constitutional avoidance of the nondelegation problem. And that is a more restrained way to enforce that constitutional commitment.

 

      So I would just endorse the idea that sometimes judges when the history is unclear about constitutional interpretation, that statutory interpretation and the doctrine of constitutional avoidance is a second best, or maybe a first best.

 

Hon. Gregory Katsas:  Randy.

 

Hon. Randolph Moss:  Well, I'll be very brief since I was the last.

 

       In any event, and I'll simply say that it's been a pleasure to be on this panel with all of you. And one of the things that I think is most interesting to me is how much agreement there is among the panelists.

 

Hon. Gregory Katsas:  Okay. We have about half an hour, plenty of time for questions. There are two mikes on the side if people want to start lining up. Just going to take the moderator's prerogative and ask the first question or put an idea on the table. Very -- oh, my gosh. We have long lines. Very practical.

 

      I was struck, John, by your formulation of days or weeks of concentrated effort. So let me kind of think that through as a judge with a docket and a budget. So I have to decide nine cases a month. Many of them are tremendously complicated ad law cases. And before I can do a deep dive on the law—to borrow a phrase—I have to spend days or weeks of concentrated effort just to figure out how the administrative scheme works, what the agency did, and so on. Those are my numbers. I'm pretty confident Andy probably has two or three times as many cases as I do. And Randy probably has, what, a couple hundred at any given amount of time.

 

Hon. Andrew Oldham:  At least. Yeah.

 

Hon. Gregory Katsas:  So days or weeks of concentrated effort to figure out one case. The numbers just don't add up. So I guess my question for the judges is: How do we make the numbers add up? And, for the academics, can you help us out?

 

Hon. Andrew Oldham:  Sleep less?

 

Hon. Randolph Moss:  Yeah. You want to go first?

 

Hon. Andrew Oldham:  Yeah. That's all I've got is sleep less.

 

Hon. Randolph Moss:  Yeah. I'm not --

 

Hon. Gregory Katsas:  I need more sleep than you do, Andy. I know your sleep schedule.

 

Hon. Randolph Moss:  I think part of the answer to that is also sorting through where your time is really most needed. And we all would like to have more time for all of our cases, but when you have a case that raises a particularly important question and it involves difficult issues, including history, we'll end up spending more time on that. We'll still wish we had even more time to do it. And that's part of the problem here. But I think it is a question of just how you allocate your scarce resources.

 

Hon. Gregory Katsas:  Okay. Let's go to questions. We'll alternate back and forth, and let's start over there on the left. Go ahead.

 

Questioner 1:  Hello. Can you hear me? All right.

 

      Having read a number of originalist's decisions over the years and a number of nonoriginalist's decisions here and there as well, I find there's usually a section in every originalist's decision that goes to heterodox result that has the -- what I call the "Oh, but don't you worry" section of the opinion.

 

      For example—well, this isn't an opinion, but—before Judge Oldham went on the bench, he wrote this very long and very good law review article basically saying the Sherman Act was unconstitutional. But then, in the lower sections of his opinion, he had one of these sections, where I call it the, "Oh, don't you worry" clause, where he said, "Oh, but don't you worry. If we get rid of the Sherman Act, there'll be plenty of state antitrust laws that we can just use instead." I'm from Pennsylvania. We don't have an antitrust law, so you know. And the little section of Heller where it says, "Oh, but don't you worry. These particular gun laws are fine," or another example.

 

      Should we have those opinions -- those sections of opinions if we have originalist opinions that reach that or reach any decision, really? And, if so, why? If not, why not?

 

Hon. Andrew Oldham:  It's always haunting when something you write in law school comes back.

 

      I think one answer to that is that -- I think really, if there's anything that this panel agrees on across the board, it is that modesty is perhaps the principal command. And so, I think what might be phrased -- what might be termed as a "don't you worry" section could also be phrased as to say, "Listen. Maybe I'm wrong about this." Or, "Maybe the consequences of this are different than I'm anticipating. But here are some reasons that it might not be as terrible as you might think."

 

      And so, I think having some degree of caveats is always important and for any number of reasons, and, in particular, when it comes to actually judging because of the fact that you could be wrong. And these cases are important, and the precedents are important, and we have to build into them some ability to recognize the limits of what we're doing.

 

Hon. Randolph Moss:  Yeah. It's hard to answer that question entirely in the abstract because it's going to vary from case to case and in opinion to opinion. But what I would say is -- I do think that judges need to struggle when they consider the consequences of what they're doing. If the law leads them to a result and the consequences are not good, but that's the result, they're stuck with that. But I do think that we do need to think about the consequences.

 

      And I also think that it's important to make clear, if an opinion has a limited reach, that it has a limited reach because everyone -- there will be folks out there who want to read it as broadly as they can. And if, in fact, the court only intends it to go so far, well, indicating that can be valuable, particularly with appellate courts and with the Supreme Court, to make sure that it doesn't invite more trouble, perhaps, than the authors of the opinion anticipated. And I also think that it's important to make clear, if an opinion has a limited reach, that it has a limited reach because everyone -- there will be folks out there who want to read it as broadly as they can. And if, in fact, the court only intends it to go so far, well, indicating that can be valuable, particularly with appellate courts and with the Supreme Court, to make sure that it doesn't invite more trouble, perhaps, than the authors of the opinion anticipated.

 

Hon. Gregory Katsas:  On my right. I can't see too well through the lights, but go ahead.

 

Art Macomber:  Good morning. Art Macomber, Coeur d'Alene, Idaho. I am an active litigator and struggle with these issues all the time. And I appreciate the academicians. We got to get the answer right for all time. I think that's kind of in the arguments that the judges' task is. We got to get the law right for these set of facts.

 

      And so, recognizing the limits on time, the limits on brief length, and then the limits of the facts, as they're given in the trial court, especially at the appellate level, but also in the trial level, I'm interested in what the panel can tell us about what they see as the effect of the adversarial system on fleshing this stuff out because you can take an originalist approach, and of course, you start with the text. And then you jump off into the cliff of historical swamp. And there are different analytical methods you can use depending on which side of the argument you're on. And so, what is the effect of the adversarial function in the court system on these arguments?

 

Prof. Jed Shugerman:  I can jump in and just say one part of my experience is learning from, first of all, that the adversarial system is the design of the system, but it should not be part of the approach to the writing of history. And so, from experience -- and I'm always -- and I appreciate what Professor Harrison is saying too. I try and take this to heart because just to say to the historians out there that it's important to—and do as I say and not as I do—but to let that adversarial system take the best of it. And I think that's actually been helpful in honing these different arguments.

 

      I do want to add something about the role of amicus. I work for free. Every brief I've written -- I've never been paid for a brief, and my coauthors have not been paid either. I think my concern is about Bruen and Rahimi and what Judge Oldham put up on the board is that I would not work for free to do that kind of digging. It's one thing to try and explain what the word "emolument" meant or to translate the articles we are already writing into a brief. But in a case-by-case perspective—and I'm also -- I have agreed, for free, to help the NAACP out with a question in Mississippi about judges and prosecutor elections. But that's based upon my research I've already done.

 

      My concern about Bruen: We're talking about the problem of originalism in theory versus originalism in practice. I'm just picking up on what Tara Grove -- her excellent observation in yesterday's panel. Bruen is unmanageable for how historians are going to work. And there's an assumption that "Oh, just have historians do the research for district courts." That's just -- I have a hard time imagining how that's workable over the long term.

 

Prof. John Harrison:  I think there's a negative effect often from the adversary system because, especially lawyers with clients, including will have a client when they're extensively filing amicus, think they have to write 100 percent. And so, you get a brief on one side saying, "It is obvious that we are right," and a brief on the other side saying, "Only an idiot could disagree with us." Well, apparently there are a lot of idiots out there.

 

      And I would like to ask the judges when a brief is more persuasive by saying, "This is a hard question." And then, of course, explaining why we're right and my client must win, but recognizing that it's a hard question because I think counsel have a fear that they should never do that.

 

Hon. Randolph Moss:  I think you're certainly right about that. And, both as a matter of oral advocacy and written advocacy, lawyers who are willing to be candid with courts, with respect to areas where they're stronger or weaker tend to be more effective. And there's -- I can tell you that judges bristle at statements in briefs that say, "There is no doubt whatsoever that it" -- "No sane person could think otherwise." And you immediately as a judge start thinking to yourself, "Well, what's the argument for the other side then," when people do that. So I think it's a matter of advocacy that's right.

 

      The one thing I will say, though, in response to Professor Harrison, though, is in some sense, I think the amicus briefs may be able to strike that balance. One of the things that's a little bit more comfortable for judges, though, about the parties' briefs is that you know where they're coming from. You know what their job is. And you can weigh it in that context.

 

      It's not as obvious to the courts with respect to amici. And the advocates have to live by a set of rules that amici don't live by. And if a party is raising an argument on appeal for the first time, they may not get away with that. Or they're raising it for the first time in the Supreme Court, whereas amici just do that freely. And so, there are some greater constraints, which actually give some comfort to judges on the parties.

 

Hon. Gregory Katsas:  Next question.

 

Art Macomber:  Thank you.

 

Brett Busby:  Good morning. Brett Busby, Supreme Court of Texas.

 

      Thanks to the panel for the wonderful practical observations on how this work can be done in courts. We also don't get very many amicus briefs, and I wanted to pick up on something that Judge Moss said about, "It sure would be nice if they came in in a trial court and you could question the experts about, well, 'Let me push on this.' How does that really work?"

 

      And I wonder if that's an analogy that maybe helps us think about this because, in scientific expert testimony and other types of expert testimony, it's actually quite disfavored to have litigation-motivated research done where you come up with a conclusion just not based on any prior scientific or other expert inquiry. And I wonder if the panel has thoughts on should you give different weights to amicus briefs depending on if the research was done independently before this particular controversy arose. Or maybe the amicus brief is at least citing things that were done before versus research that's being done on the fly in the context of a particular case to try to answer a particular question?

 

Hon. Andrew Oldham:  Me?

 

Hon. Gregory Katsas:  Yeah. Whoever.

 

Hon. Andrew Oldham:  Yeah. I'm happy to jump in. Yes, I think ideally it would be some preexisting body of law. But we see this all the time in cases, too, is where -- and I appreciated, also, Judge Moss's observation about this. Expert reports are almost always drafted in the context of a particular set of litigation. And, yes, I'm sure it draws on somebody that you're qualified as an expert based on the stuff you've done in the past, but at the end of the day, Judge Moss has to rule on the Daubert motion based on an expert report that was drafted in anticipation of litigation or in the fire -- in the crucible of litigation. But at least he gets to cross-examine those witnesses.

 

      And one of the things that I think is so remarkable about what happens in originalist cases -- one of the cases I was thinking about, as we're having this dialogue, is a couple terms ago, the Torres v. Madrid case, where the question presented is: What is the original public meaning of the Fourth Amendment as applied to seizures, and does an attempted seizure constitute a seizure?

 

      And what was amazing about that case is that everyone—the majority and the dissent—both agree about the relevant sources of material. There's none of this—none of these complexities about—is this all drafted in anticipation of litigation? Are we all looking at the relevant stuff? Both sides say, "Look. We're looking at the same body of stuff. It's Blackstone. It's these things from the founding. And both the sides agree, even as to the relevant precedent, this Countess of Rutland case and with the touching of the mace in a civil bankruptcy proceeding. Everyone agrees as to all of that, and then the majority and the dissent both say that the answer's obvious. And so, I don't know what the right way out of that puzzle is. But, yes, ideally, it would all be sorted out ahead of time. But practically, I have a hard time thinking it would be.

 

Prof. John Harrison:  It would be -- it would be great. And I can't think of a way to do this. If there were a legal or historical equivalent of preregistration in social science for researchers to say before they conduct the research, "Here's the question I'm going to try to answer. And I'm going to publish it however it comes out."

 

Hon. Gregory Katsas:  Please.

 

Harry Lewis:  Harry Lewis from New York.

 

      I'm a voracious consumer of history of all kinds, as many of my friends know, but I'm observing, as I read the more contemporary books and articles and things, that many of the newer histories are becoming increasingly woke. And, obviously, in this context, because we're all sitting -- we're talking about enlightenment settlement. This is a brilliant panel, but everyone in the room assumes that enlightenment principles of argumentation, debate, opposing viewpoints are going to be fairly heard. This is at the foundation of our legal system. But we're starting to get a competing historical and philosophical perspective called -- we understand as "woke" that really rejects basic enlightenment principles in reading, understanding, analyzing history.

 

      So my question to the panel is this: Given this competing -- this rising surge of competition, if you will—and I think it's obviously a throwback to a less enlightened time that this is now happening—it's starting to submerge some of the historical organizations. People are getting -- historians are being silenced now in our society. And Bari Weiss, yesterday, noted we're kind of the last bastion. But just a quick question to the panel: Are any of you starting to perceive what I call this "debasing of the historical currency" in a legal setting? Or do any of you have concerns about that? Do any of you have further thoughts about that?

 

Prof. Jed Shugerman:  I'll just quickly say as I speak to my friends who are in law schools but my friends who are professors in other areas, the law schools are -- after October 7th -- and it may not be obvious from the news, but law schools are handling this better -- and that's a low bar maybe. But the universities have, frankly, been a disaster. Law schools have been better. And so, I just want -- and there are explanations, maybe because of professionalization. Maybe because, thankfully, some employers had standards about when to rescind offers that have an effect. And sometimes chilling effect is good when it means people need to chill out. So I just want to -- that's one observation.

 

      The other observation is, tenure is an amazing blessing, and thank goodness. And so, as someone who has written things recently that get the left as upset with me as some things I've written in the past that get the right upset with me, I feel like I've got this privilege. And I think many of us use that privilege effectively without feeling like that there's this blowback. So I just want to say I think the academy still is thankfully engaged with integrity.

 

Hon. Gregory Katsas:  Next question.

 

Cam Atkinson:  Thank you, Your Honor. Cam Atkinson from Connecticut.

 

      I had a question about the choice for a litigator deploying originalism. I litigate both First and Second Amendment cases, and one of the challenges I see in choosing to deploy originalist arguments is, obviously, Bruen recalibrates Second Amendment analysis to an originalist argument. But we're still dealing with the terrors of scrutiny in First Amendment litigation, etc. And many of the panels I appear in front of at the Second Circuit, etc., we don't know who our panel's going to be until the week of the oral argument.

 

      Are there signs lawyers should be looking for in terms of when a court is going to be receptive to an originalist argument, or they're going to follow what I would call the more traditional path of analysis of what can you analyze or analogize to precedent?

 

Hon. Randolph Moss:  Any takers?

 

Hon. Andrew Oldham:  Well, the First Amendment is a great example of a place that is thick with precedent and perhaps thin with original meaning, or at least when it comes to things like speech. And I'm as receptive to originalist arguments as anyone I hope you'll find. But at the end of the day, especially when you're coming to an inferior court, there's a lot of precedent, and we're bound by it. And that's the end of it.

 

      I think the interesting question is -- we have the same practice of -- we don't announce our panels until the week -- I guess the Monday before the arguments. And so -- and I think there's a huge virtue in that because you don't know who it is that you're talking to and therefore you have to make the best arguments you can for your client. And at the end of the day, there are originalists on a wide spectrum of these issues and I think the more we litigate those, the better off we will be.

 

Hon. Gregory Katsas:  Hoping to get to everyone. It's going to be close. We'll go to rapid-fire round. I'm just going to ask for quick questions, please.

 

Charles Miller:  Yeah. Yes. I'm pretty good at that. So Charles Miller, Institute for Free Speech.

 

      So this is our practical panel. So we know advocates are going to advocate. We also know that historians aren't typically ringing in until the end. So my question is this: Are there historians out there that are briefing to the Supreme Court and just sometimes saying, "The history record is actually inconclusive," and not doing advocacy either way -- just saying that, "Hey. We can't get there yet"?

 

      And then, second, when there are disputed historic facts, should the Supreme Court develop some fact-finding process with a master commissioner or special whatever to kind of get to the historic answer?

 

Hon. Randolph Moss:  Well, I'll just answer the second question, which is I think there are lots of things we can do to try and address some of the issues that have been flagged today. I don't think the Supreme Court having commissioners make these factual findings is likely in our future. But what I will say is that the Supreme Court does have the advantage of having certiorari jurisdiction, and it can wait to take a case until it feels as though the record has been adequately developed.

 

Prof. Jed Shugerman:  I know in the Jarkesy case, Ilan Wurman—someone I disagree with on most of this stuff—filed a brief on behalf of neither side, saying that the issue in Jarkesy is the administrative law judges. And his theory about unitary executive is that it applies to department heads. And I'll shout out to Gary Lawson here as well and Steven Calabresi on this point. There is a -- the principal officer was in neologism. There was no principal officer in English history. There was principal secretaries. So I just want to give credit where credit's due. Some of the -- many originalists do this work.

 

      And then I just want to name Ilan Wurman as someone who didn't take the unitary executive side in that case out of a principled historical commitment.

 

Hon. Gregory Katsas:  Yes, ma'am.

 

Audrey Lind (sp):  Good morning. Audrey Lind from Georgia.

 

      I want to say I've been fascinated today by the discussion of the need for a methodological consistency, the challenges of understanding the reliability of resources, sometimes the lack of resources, as well as where you start, where you end research.

 

      In my relatively short career, I've had the somewhat unique opportunity to work as a law librarian, an appellate law clerk, and now, currently, as a practitioner of a small firm. And one of the things that strikes me is the stark differences of informational resources and information on awareness in those three contexts.

 

      And so, what I'm wondering is, if in light of the call for more originalist analysis that we see coming from the U.S. Supreme Court, is there correspondingly a call for greater collaboration between legal academia and courts and perhaps the continuing legal education experts to talk about and have a vigorous discussion concerning what kinds of resources need to be available to practitioners to courts in order to do this kind of analysis as well as to educate lawyers and judges about appropriate research methodologies and reliable resources?

 

Hon. Randolph Moss:  Well, I'm glad you made that point because I think librarians, in particular, can be extremely helpful in this area. We, in our circuit and district courts, have a tremendous librarian. And we can call up and say, "Help us find these sources."

 

      And I remember, as a law clerk at the Supreme Court, we had the Library of Congress at our disposal. And I remember working on one project where we did end up doing our own historical research. And we called the Library of Congress, and they sent us some really helpful and interesting material. So I think drawing on librarians is something that could be very helpful.

 

Prof. John Harrison:  There is experience with the courts trying to improve their institutional capacity in dealing with various kinds of technical and specialized questions, including, for example, economics and science. And so, somebody who was interested in that for originalism, I think, could look to those models what courts have done in the last 50 years to increase their sophistication about other kinds of specialized inquiries.

 

Prof. Jed Shugerman:  Very quickly. I just want -- there are a couple of resources for those who want to get into this material about where to find materials. And so, in addition to librarians, I think Steve Sachs and Will Baude wrote an article about -- I can't remember which article it is, but if you search for "Maggs," they cite a series of resources. And so, there is a scholar who -- Gregory Maggs, M-A-G-G-S. Never met him, but he has well-documented the different resources. Or you can --

 

Prof. John Harrison:  One of my co-clerks. He’s a wonderful professor. I --

 

Prof. Jed Shugerman:  Oh, didn’t even know...

 

[CROSSTALK]

 

Prof. John Harrison:  He's in the armed forces now.

 

Prof. Jed Shugerman:  Great.

 

Hon. Gregory Katsas:  Yes.

 

Richard Samp:  Richard Samp, New Civil Liberties Alliance.

 

      I oftentimes get discouraged by whether we're ever going to arrive at any kind of consensus on certain issues about what history says, let alone how that applies to particular cases. Certainly, that bothers me in the Second Amendment area.

 

      I have a question, I guess, perhaps for Judge Moss or anybody else. One issue that seems to be continuing to be contentious is whether a sitting president can ever be indicted. I know you have been involved very long in that issue. I'm wondering if your feeling is that, over the years, have we arrived at any better consensus on that issue, or are the issues still the same when you were first involved 25 years ago in that?

 

Hon. Randolph Moss:  So I'm not -- I have not gone back there -- had reason to go back and study that question again. But will I -- no one has brought to my attention new historical sources on it, but I just -- I have not gone back to look at it again. So I don't -- there always are new sources. So if someone looked into it, I wouldn't be surprised if there was something else out there.

 

Hon. Gregory Katsas:  Penultimate question.

 

Roger Abbott:  Roger Abbott at Miles & Stockbridge.

 

      I've one question regarding how these court cases filter up. There seem to be a lot more originalists on the Court of Appeals than the district court. And, as a practical matter, what happens if an issue doesn't get raised before the district court because maybe you don't have an originalist judge, or maybe you just don't have the resources to raise an issue that it's unlikely? And so, I think that's a real issue that you see: litigations that simply aren't raised, and I don't know if there's sometimes a way that judges on appeal can slide them in. But that seems like a practical problem.

 

Hon. Gregory Katsas:  Anybody?

 

Hon. Randolph Moss:  Yeah. What I'll say is I think that's an issue that comes up, not just in this context but in other contexts, where issues become more refined as they go up through the appellate process, and there is more attention and additional briefing, amicus briefs, as they come up through the process. And appellate judges have to make sometimes tough decisions about whether an issue has been preserved or not. And there's a continuum because there are variations of an argument that was raised, but it may be raised a lot better on appeal than it was raised at the district court. But if it was raised, I don't think there's a prohibition on doing a better job of it in the Court of Appeals.

 

Hon. Gregory Katsas:  Last question.

 

Heather Hacker:  One thought that occurred to me -- Heather Hacker from Austin, Texas.

 

      One thought that occurred to me when looking at Judge Oldham's example of the very truncated docket that the court is working with in deciding a very complicated constitutional case is the practical problem a lot of these very important cases coming up to the Court in the first time in a very expedited posture, so in like a stay posture.

 

      Do you think that when a potential solution to that problem, aside from perhaps practitioners being more judicious about asking for extraordinary relief like that -- do you think that a potential solution to help the Court is to allow more amicus briefs to be filed at the district court level in order to frontload that docket experience by the time it gets up to the appellate court and then the U.S. Supreme Court?

 

Hon. Andrew Oldham:  Yeah. I certainly think that's true. And you hit on a really important point that we haven't discussed yet today, so I'm glad we can close on it, which is that a lot of these cases do happen very quickly. And it's never been obvious to me -- I read a lot about the emergency dockets and how they work. And obviously, we see a lot of it in the Court of Appeals. And it's never been obvious to me what is exactly to be done about it because, when they -- in any given case, the equities are such that it truly is an emergency. And so, what are you supposed to do? It's not like we asked for the emergency. It just ends up there, and then it has to be dealt with.

 

      But one form of solace that I have always taken in all of this, Justice Jackson famously said about the Supreme Court that they're not final because they're infallible. They're only final in so far -- so only infallible in so far as they're final. Well, we're neither -- we're neither final nor infallible. So I take some solace in the fact that we try to do the best we can, and, thank God, there's someone else behind us to check.

 

Hon. Gregory Katsas:  I've been asked to make two brief announcements before we break.

 

      The first is there will be a book signing for The Soul of Civility: Timeless Principles to Heal Society and Ourselves by Alexandra Hudson. That will be on the mezzanine level right after we break.

 

      The second is I've been asked to encourage all of the audience to socialize among yourselves and engage with the panel but to please do so outside this room so that our logistics people can set up the room for the next panel.

 

 

      Please joining me in thanking great panelists for a wonderful presentation. 

10:30 a.m. - 11:00 a.m.
Book Signings

2023 National Lawyers Convention

Mezzanine
The Mayflower Hotel
1127 Connecticut Avenue NW
Washington, DC 20006

Share

Description

The Soul of Civility: Timeless Principles to Heal Society and Ourselves

  • Ms. Alexandra O. Hudson, Founder, Civic Renaissance

Speakers

11:00 a.m. - 12:30 p.m.
Nightmare on Half Street? Free Speech and the NLRB

2023 National Lawyers Convention

Topics: First Amendment • Labor & Employment Law • Free Speech & Election Law
District Room
The Mayflower Hotel
1127 Connecticut Avenue NW
Washington, DC 20006

Share

Event Video

Listen & Download

Description

Is the National Labor Relations Board doing more than any other federal agency to impose broad restrictions on non-coercive speech, based exclusively on whether the speaker is an employer? Under other statutes, speech prohibitions require evidence of actual threats, unlawful retaliation or potential injury to health and safety, and the National Labor Relations Act expressly protects the right to express “views,” “argument” and “opinion” unless the message “contains” an illegal threat or promise. The NLRB General Counsel is prosecuting numerous complaints claiming it is “inherently” coercive and “per se” unlawful for employers to address certain subjects in the workplace.

This session will involve diverse views about important questions: Where do these cases leave the First Amendment? Does commerce regulation override the First Amendment? Does the NLRB have authority to prohibit workplace discussions by employers regarding certain subjects? And what role exists in this critical area for the courts?

Featuring:

  • Hon. Philip A. Miscimarra, Partner, Morgan, Lewis & Bockius LLP
  • Craig Becker, General Counsel, American Federation of Labor–Congress of Industrial Organizations
  • Moderator: Hon. Chad A. Readler, United States Court of Appeals, Sixth Circuit

Speakers

Event Transcript

Pepper Crutcher:  My name is Pepper Crutcher to introduce our moderator today, who will introduce the panelists. Our moderator is Judge Chad Readler of the United States Court of Appeals for the Sixth Circuit. He's a Michigan undergraduate and law degree holder, and we will avoid the sign stealing jokes at this point. He was a clerk on the Sixth Circuit to Judge Alan Norris. He was in the Columbus, Ohio office of Jones Day for ten years as a partner in the appellate practice group. He was acting assistant attorney general for the Civil Division of the United States Department of Justice from 2007 to 2019. In March of 2019, he was confirmed as a circuit judge and he resides in Columbus, Ohio. Judge Readler.

 

Hon. Chad A. Readler:  Pepper, thank you very much. So living in Columbus, Ohio, as I do, Michigan jokes are not uncommon, so it would not have minded. But good morning, everyone. Welcome to our panel discussion. Let me say thank you to The Federalist Society for inviting me and putting together this panel. It's hard to find these days organizations that are willing to put on programs that are not only thoughtful but also diverse in terms of viewpoints. I think The Federalist Society is probably first and foremost in that category. And so we're all really fortunate to have had a week long discussion from diverse viewpoints, and that will be also true this morning. I'm quite confident, and so I think you're in store for a real treat.

 

The one downside about The Federalist Society Convention, which is one of my favorite weeks of the year, is that between two or three days out in the hallway at the Mayflower Hotel where you're screaming to try to talk to one another, having dinner with 2,400 of your closest friends where you can barely hear the person next to you, it can challenge your vocal cords. Mine are hanging in there, but I think by a thread. So I will do my best this morning to make it through the program. But it's been a great week and great to see so many of you.

 

So our discussion this morning is about labor law and some current initiatives by the National Labor Relations Board. And we just have two wonderful speakers to help us flesh out those issues. So let me introduce them. First, closest to me is Craig Becker. Craig is the general counsel to the AFLCIO. Before assuming that position, he was a member of the National Labor Relations Board, having been appointed by President Obama in March 2010 and serving until January 2012. Before joining the board, Craig served as associate general counsel to both the SEIU and the AFLCIO. After law school, he clerked on the Eighth Circuit, and he then became a partner in the Washington, D. C. firm that was counsel to the American Federation of State, County, and Municipal Employees. Craig was a professor of law at the UCLA School of Law and has also taught at Yale, the University of Chicago, and Georgetown Law School. He's published numerous articles on labor and employment law in scholarly journals as well as in the popular press, and he's argued labor and employment cases in virtually every federal court of appeals and in the Supreme Court. He's a graduate of Yale Law School.

 

On the far end of the table is Philip Miscimarra. Philip Miscimarra is a partner at Morgan Lewis and leads the firm's NLRB special appeals practice. His practice focuses on labor management relations, business acquisitions, and restructuring and employment litigation. He is also a senior fellow at the University of Pennsylvania's Wharton School and the Wharton Center for Human Resources. He is the former chairman of the NLRB. He was appointed to the board initially by President Obama in April 2013, and he's been confirmed by voice vote. That sounds awfully nice. Later that year -- and he served until December 2017. In 2017, he was named chairman of the board by President Donald Trump, and he currently serves -- is currently serving a six-year term on the USMCA Independent Mexico Labor Export Board, created pursuant to the United States Mexico Canada Agreement, which is the successor to NAFTA. He's the author and co-author of several books involving labor law issues. He's testified in front of Congress on labor and employment law matters, and he's a graduate of the University of Pennsylvania Law School. So I think we've agreed to give each of you sort of some opening comments, and then I'll have some questions. And of course, as is tradition, we'll take questions from the audience. Craig, I think you're going to start us off with sort of a history of where we are and how we got here.

 

Craig Becker:  I feel like I'm in a law school class with no one wanting to sit in the front. But thank you. Thank you, Judge. And thank you to The Federalist Society for inviting me into the lion's den. So at the NLRB, where Phil and I both serve, there's a quaint tradition called the personal footnote. So this is where a member either doesn't want to write a full dissent or has already dissented and wants to continue their opposition to prevailing doctrine. So I just want to pause to drop a personal footnote as to the title of today's program, "Horror on Half Street." Continuing on that theme, when Phil was chairman or just after he became chairman, a host of important decisions issued reversing important decisions of the Obama board. And within the labor movement, we lovingly called it the Miscimarra massacre. So I think Phil probably felt about that title the same way I do about the title of today's program.

 

Hon. Philip A. Miscimarra:  I knew that was coming.

 

Craig Becker:  Okay. Now to the point. So I want to do three things. One, I do want to give you a little bit of history, just background of the changes or the potential changes that we're about to talk about. Then I want to talk about those changes, the position of the general counsel on captive audience, so called captive audience meetings, and some state laws that have been passed concerning captive audience meetings more broadly. And then I want to make an argument intended to convince you that you should support those changes.

 

So, first, some history. Prior to the Taft Hartley Act of 1947, the NLRB held that employers’ participation in campaigns before union elections was unlawful. The board reasoned that it was improper for the employer, who was neither a candidate nor a voter, to attempt to influence the choice of employees of who would sit across the table from the employer in collective bargaining. The board reasoned, "The election is not a contest between a labor organization and the employer of the employees being polled, and participation by the employer in a pre-election campaign as if we were a contestant is an interference with the employee's right to bargain collectively through representatives of their own choosing." And of course, it wasn't simply that the employer was not a voter or a candidate. It was also that, "The relationship existing between the author of the utterances," i.e. the employer, "and the employees, attained a force stronger than their intrinsic connotation and beyond that of persuasion amounting to illegal coercion." I. E. the employer would exert undue influence because of its economic authority over the employees.

 

So, in other words, the board held employees statutory right to choose their bargaining representative free from employer interference, imposed a correlative duty on the employer to maintain complete neutrality with respect to an election. And the Supreme Court, interestingly, initially endorsed that notion -- that underlying notion. The Court held slight suggestions of employer preference, have a telling effect upon men who know the consequences of incurring their employer's strong displeasure. But the Court soon departed from that understanding and made clear that the board's doctrine was untenable under the First Amendment. First, in a case involving a Texas law which actually restrained union speech requiring union organizers to register, the Court struck down the law. But Justice Jackson, in a concurrence, made clear that the First Amendment extended not only to unions but to employers. Justice Jackson wrote, "Labor is free to turn its publicity on any labor oppression. The employer, too, should be free to answer." He expressly criticized the earlier rulings by both the board and the Supreme Court that denied employer the right to speak freely in a unielection campaign, writing, "Free speech on both sides of the labor relations is to me a constitutional and useful right."

 

Congress in 1947, just after these Supreme Court decisions, codified that right in the Taft Hartley Act, so called free speech proviso, what we now refer to as Section 8C of the act, which we'll be talking about at some length, I believe, and let me quote it in full. So the so-called free speech provides, "The expression of any views, arguments, or opinion, or the dissemination thereof, whether in written, printed, graphic, or visual form, shall not constitute or be evidence of an unfair labor practice under any of the provisions of this subchapter if such expression contains no threat of reprisal or force or promise of benefit." So critical to the argument now being made by the general counsel, as I'll lay out more later, is the limit of the protection in Section 8C. That is, "If such expression contains no threat of reprisal," because such a threat is, of course, inherent in a captive audience meeting. Captive audience meeting means employees are required to attend on pain of discipline up to discharge. That is a threat. If you don't attend, you'll be disciplined. Now, nevertheless, despite that logic, immediately after Taft Hartley, the Board held that the proviso not only protected employer free speech but protected the compulsion inherent in captive audience meetings.

 

That decision had reasoning which is confined to two sentences, and I'll read them for you. "The language of Section 8C of the amended act and its legislative history makes it clear that the doctrine of the Clark Brothers case no longer exists as a basis for finding unfair labor practices in circumstances such as the record discloses. Even assuming that the respondent required its employees to attend and listen to the speeches, we conclude that it did not inherently violate the act." That is the sum total of the reasoning. Of course, the language of 8C says no such thing. That should be the end of the inquiry. As for the reference to the discussion of Clark Brothers in the legislative history, Phil and I can give you an extensive discourse on the legislative history, probably from memory, in Phil's case in the question-and-answer session.

 

But for now, suffice it to say that that's a reference to a sentence in the Senate report on the Taft Hartley Act which did disapprove the Clark Brothers case. But the Clark Brothers case was a case which held that any speech by the employer in the workplace during the workday was unlawful. So the rejection was of the restriction on employer speech generally, not on the compulsion inherent in a captive audience meeting. Now, indeed, if you want an exhaustive catalog of the legislative history of Section 8C, which Phil, I'm sure, will give you, but I commend to you Phil's testimony from the House Ed and Labor Committee hearings, where you've got, in true Law Review fashion, two pages where two thirds of which are covered by footnote, which is in a font too small to read, which recount in great detail the legislative history of 8C. And if you look at all those references, you'll find pay on after pay on to the First Amendment. But you'll look in vain for anything in the legislative history which says free speech includes the right to compel listening. It's not there.

 

To the contrary, the legislative history makes crystal clear that 8C was intended to codify the First Amendment. And we all know that the First Amendment, the Supreme Court has construed time and time again to allow protection of captive audiences in different contexts. Subsequent board decisions simply follow the original decision, no further reasoning. And yet, stripped to its essence, the board precedents permits the employer to force employees to listen on pain of discipline, to discipline employees who decline to attend or politely leave such meetings, and even to require employees to remain silent during those meetings, and to discipline employees who respectfully disagree. I believe, along with the general counsel, that that original board decision is grievously wrong. It's inconsistent with the language of 8C and with the fundamental purpose of the act, which was to allow free choice of employees free of employer coercion. It has nothing to do with employer free speech.

 

So what's happening now? The general counsel is arguing to the board that they should reverse that 1948 decision and hold captive audience meetings are unlawful. Her argument is simple, and I'll quote it "Those meetings inherently involve an unlawful threat that employees will be disciplined or suffer other reprisals if they exercise their protected right not to listen to such speech. Employees clearly have a right to receive information about unions from others, both unions and employers, and corresponding, they have the right to decline to receive information. After all," she argues, "the Supreme Court has stated, 'Private citizens have always retained the power to decide for themselves what they wish to read and within limits what oral messages they want to consider.'"

 

That issue is now pending before the board. At the same time, four states, California, Maine, Minnesota, and New York, have recently passed -- and Oregon has had on the books for some time -- laws that we call worker freedom laws. And those laws prohibit employers generally from requiring employees to attend meetings in which the employer expresses its views or has a third party express its views on politics and religion, with politics being broadly defined to include electoral politics, ballot initiatives, joining a civic organization, including a labor organization. The chamber, represented by Phil and others, has challenged the Connecticut law on labor law preemption and First Amendment grounds. So that's the history, and that's what's happening currently.

 

So now I want to convince you why you should support the general counsel's position in those state laws. So first, you're all textualists. The text of the free speech proviso and the NLRA clearly does not protect threats. It explicitly doesn't protect threats. And a threat is necessary to create a captive audience meeting. You attend or you be disciplined. You leave and you'll be disciplined. Therefore, captive audience meetings are not protected by the proviso. End of the story. Secondly, you believe, as I certainly do, in religious liberty, and I'm sure you believe that it violates Title VII for an employer to require employees to attend a religious meeting, prayer or otherwise.

 

And that's not a hypothetical possibility. Just last summer, the EEOC settled a case against a North Carolina home repair company called Aurora Pro Services. Since at least June of 2020, Aurora had required all its employees to attend daily employer led Christian prayer meetings. The meetings were conducted by the company owner and included Bible readings, Christian devotionals, and solicitation of prayers requested from employees. Aurora's owner took role before some of the meetings and reprimanded employees who did not attend, et cetera. EEO sued, and the case was settled. The EEOC alleged, correctly in my view, that this violated Title VII. If you believe the First Amendment extends to permitting employers to compel employees to listen to anti-union speech, you have to believe that Title VII is unconstitutional in that respect. I'm sure you don't. And I don't.

 

Third, you're all originalists, and one of the Founder’s deepest fears was that propertyless laborers would obtain the franchise and be subject to undue influence from their employers. In fact, many opposed extending the franchise to workers for that reason. They opposed extending the vote to, "mechanics and manufacturers who received their bread from their employers." Even if they were granted the franchise, Governor Morris argued, "Propertyless wage earners will not truly be represented because they would sell their vote to the rich who will be able to buy them." In James Madison's words, working men, "will become the tools of opulence and ambition." So surely the founders, who were so concerned about the undue influence of employers on those who didn't hold property and thus had to work for a living, would not have believed that the First Amendment extended to allowing employers to require employees to sit and be told how to vote.

 

Same can be said about the second founding. The reconstruction witnessed a burst of legislation in the south reflecting Republicans' concern that Southern employers were pressuring their employees, including newly freed slaves, to vote in favor of Democrats. And this, too, is not a hypothetical concern. The last several elections have witnessed countless news stories about employers doing exactly that. That is, requiring their employees to sit and listen to the employer tell them how to vote. In 2012, for example, miners at Murray Energy Century Coal Mine in Beallsville, Ohio, reported that they were forced to attend a rally for then candidate Mitt Romney at the mine. The founders clearly did not understand the liberty protected by the First Amendment to encompass employers' ability to coerce employees in this way.

 

Fourth, you believe Governor Ron DeSantis is a smart, Harvard trained lawyer who would certainly not violate employers First Amendment rights. But right now in the Eleventh Circuit -- right now, the Eleventh Circuit is considering a First Amendment challenge to his, "Individual Freedom Act," which, among other things, bars employers from forcing employees to attend meetings that espouse any one of eight concepts related to race, color, sex, and national origin. One of those concepts that employers can't speak about or can't compel their employees to listen to their speech about is, "an individual, by virtue, his or her race, color, sex, or national origin bears personal responsibility for, and must feel guilt, anguish, or other form of psychological distress because of the actions in which the individual played no part committed in the past by other members of the same race, color, sex, or national origin."

 

So the Florida law being defended by Governor DeSantis in the Eleventh Circuit prevents employers from compelling their employees to listen to speech about those subjects. Exactly what the state laws do in the states I mentioned, and what the general counsel is arguing to the board should be unlawful in the labor context. Governor Santis argues that these laws don't regulate speech, but conduct, quote, "What the act does, all it does is prevent employers from conscripting their employees against their will into the audience as a conditioner of their employment." That's from his brief to the Court. The First Amendment, "does not protect the ability of employers to use their economic leverage over their workers to force them, on pain of losing their jobs or other sanctions, to attend training sessions advocating such views on questions of race."

 

Interestingly, citing an example from the Supreme Court's fair decision, DeSantis argues, "A legislature, for example, can prohibit racial discrimination in hiring without violating the First Amendment even though such a prohibition would require an employer to take down a sign reading "White applicants only." And here, the Individual Freedom Act does not even impose that much of a burden on speech. Rather, the act employment provisions are akin not to a prohibition on white applicants only sign, but rather to a prohibition on employers practice of forcing all employees to look at it." And the governor goes beyond arguing that the law regulates conduct, and that's not speech, to argue that even if it regulates speech, incidentally, there's a compelling government interest.

 

And what is the compelling governmental interest? Protection of a captive audience. He argues that the Florida law's provisions, "Liberate an employee from being coerced into attending an instructional event that he cannot practically avoid, at least not without risk to his livelihood." Now, the Florida law is obviously different from what the general counsel is proposing or what the state laws provide in that it suppresses speech based on viewpoint. That is different. But if you believe anything that I just quoted from Governor DeSantis' brief, you have to believe that the state laws at issue are not prohibited by the First Amendment and that the general's counsel's position is consistent with the First Amendment.

 

Now, as to the state laws, there's obviously a labor law preemption argument as well as a First Amendment interest. But in the interest of letting Phil have some time to talk, I'm going to leave that for later. So let me just finish. I assume, based on what I have to say, that you'll now all be willing to sign a brief opposing Phil's position in Connecticut and arguing that the Connecticut law is lawful and support the general counsel's position. So thank you, and I'll turn it over to Phil.

 

Hon. Chad A. Readler:  I will just say, thank you, Craig. We promised a disagreement, and we got a rousing endorsement of the DeSantis administration. So this is going a different direction than I had thought. But, Phil.

 

Hon. Phil A. Miscimarra:  Yeah. I appreciate Judge Readler's introduction and also the fact that Craig is speaking with us on this panel today. When I served as chairman or board member on the NLRB, I was constantly reminded of one statement made by John Fanning, who was one of the longest serving NLRB members and former chairman of the board. And John Fanning served on the board four days short of 25 years. He participated in some 25,000 NLRB decisions, and he said, "One factor every NLRB case has in common is the presence of at least two people who see things completely differently." So this is not unusual to have divergent views with respect to important issues that are addressed by the National Labor Relations Act.

 

And I think everyone in this room believes, and Craig and I share this view, that the NLRA deals with important issues. But I think the speech restrictions that Craig supports and which are being pursued by the NLRB General Counsel in a number of different cases, I think, in my view, that -- I think they are contrary to the NLRA. And I think the NLRA cases that are being prosecuted infringe on First Amendment rights, not only the underlying claims in those cases, but I think the cases themselves infringe on the First Amendment. And I want to say at the outset that I have respect for the views that Craig just articulated. I also have respect for the NLRB's current general counsel, Jennifer Abruzzo. And I respect all of the current and former and future members on the National Labor Relations Board. But in connection with the impermissibility, in my view, of the NLRB General Counsel's speech, restrictions on employer discussions in the workplace about union issues, or the exercise of NLRA protected rights, I'll make four points.

 

And the first point, I'll start by saying when I was in my Senate confirmation hearing ten years ago for the NLRB, I said that if I was confirmed to serve on the board, I would remember that labor law policy originates with Congress, not with members of the National Labor Relations Board. And so I think we're all lawyers. At least most of the people here are lawyers. When we talk about a statute's requirements or restrictions, the first place to look is not policy. The first place to look is what does the statute say? And Craig made reference to Section 8C of the NLRA, but I think it makes sense to unpack it a little bit. So this section, in the statute, it says that the expressing of any views, argument or opinion, not just facts, any views, argument or opinion, or the dissemination thereof, shall not constitute or be evidence of an unfair labor practice under any of the provisions of this act.

 

This is not common language that you see in statutes. And it doesn't just relate to making statements that are neutral with respect to objectively describing events. It protects views, argument, or opinion, and they won't violate any of the provisions of the act. And there is a proviso. And here's what the proviso says. This section ends with a statement that says, "If such expression contains no threat of reprisal or force or promise of benefit," but the word there is, "the protection afforded to these expressions are lost if the expressions themselves contain a threat of reprisal or force or promise of benefit." Now, Craig and I agree on a couple of things. One is if an employer statement contains a coercive threat or unlawful promise of benefits, I think we agree that's prohibited by the act, and it's not protected by Section 8C.

 

And by the way, the National Labor Relations Act contains a significant number of provisions that explicitly protect employees from unlawful employer discrimination or retaliation or interference or restraint or coercion regarding union related issues. So we agree that protection exists in the statute with respect to those things that are prohibited in the list that I just mentioned. But the NLRB general counsel contends that an employer's workplace discussions that say anything about a union or anything about the exercise of protected rights, they are per se unlawful when the discussions do not contain any coercive threat or improper promise. That contention does exactly what Section 8C prohibits. Under Section 8C, if an expression contains no improper threat or promise, the statute says again, "It shall not constitute or be evidence of any violation under, 'any of the provisions of this act.'"

 

Now, here's my second point. I don't think meetings and discussions can be deemed inherently unlawful by calling them mandatory. The concept of employment involves choice on both sides, and employees choose to work and they're paid for their working time. That's a voluntary relationship. And no surprise, the place and time when employers have the opportunity to engage in discussions with employees is when they're at work. So what the general counsel describes as unlawful mandatory discussions involves nothing more than having employees come to work, during which employers and employees engage in all kinds of discussions, and the employees are paid for that time.

 

But what's claimed to be inherently unlawful in these discussions is not where they take place or when they take place. Instead, these discussions are deemed inherently unlawful when the employer is the speaker and when the subject matter involves union issues or some other exercise of NLRA rights. And that's the type of content-based restriction that, under long established First Amendment law, is unconstitutional under the First Amendment. My third point is this, and I don't mean to offend the textualists in the audience who believe every inquiry starts and ends with statutory language, but if the language in Section 8C is not considered dispositive, then most lawyers would ask -- at least some lawyers would ask -- even some judges -- is there any relevant legislative history?

 

And Craig described some of the NLRA's legislative history relating to NLRA Section 8C. And I'll just say that there's a lot of legislative history, which I think, in fact, is dispositive of these issues. And I view the legislative history quite a bit differently than Craig. But in 1946, it's true, the NLRB decided a case. The name of this case was Clark Brothers. And in that case, the NLRB held that an employer's, "Superior economic power," and "Its ability to control employee actions during working hours," meant that any company was inherently, "Coercing its employees," if it forced them to, "Listen to speeches relating to their organizational activities." Now, in this 1946 case, the board said -- in finding that these discussions were inherently unlawful, the board said that the, "Employees were compelled to assemble during working time to listen to anti-union campaign speeches."

 

And the NLRB embraced exactly the same restrictions on employer speech for the same reasons that are now being articulated again by NLRB General Counsel Abruzzo and supported by Craig and others. Now, the very next year -- this Clark Brothers case was decided in 1946. The very next year, in 1947, the year after Clark Brothers was decided, Congress amended the National Labor Relations Act by adding Section 8C. And the House and Senate reports and debates clearly indicate that Section 8C was added to restore employer First Amendment rights that the NLRB had tried to take away in Clark Brothers and other cases. In fact, in 1947, when the Taft Hartley amendments added Section 8C to the act, the House Democrats opposed the Taft Hartley amendments -- and the original Wagner Act -- the NLRA that was adopted in 1935 -- didn't even have union unfair labor practices. It only had violations by employers.

 

One of the things that the Taft Hartley Act added in 1947, apart from Section 8C, was a number of enumerated union unfair labor practices as well. So in 1947, when the Taft Hartley Act was being considered, the House Democrats opposed the amendments, except they supported the amendment protecting employer speech because -- and this was in the minority report in the House --"The First Amendment protects an employer's expressions of noncoercive opinion to his employees respecting union organization." Now, in 1947, John F. Kennedy was a freshman House member, and he authored his own separate minority report. And in his report, he also expressed support for the restoration of employer free speech rights that the NLRB had tried to take away.

 

And in his minority report, he stated, "The First Amendment protects an employer's expressions of non-coercive opinion to his employees respecting union organization." And where do you think those expressions that the Democrats in the House believe should be protected -- where do you think those expressions took place? They took place in the workplace. And they took place in the workplace during paid time. It's true that the NLRB, in the 1948 case called Babcock and Wilcox, interpreted Section 8D, I think, correctly, as repudiating this entire captive audience theory of violation. But the board is not the only agency or the only adjudicator that had this view. Courts of appeals also state it is clear that Section 8C repudiated the captive audience theory of illegality.

 

In 1969, the Supreme Court decided the Gissel Packing case, and the Court said that "An employer's free speech right to communicate his views to his employees is firmly established and cannot be infringed by a union or the board. And in 2008, the Supreme Court in Chamber of Commerce v. Brown said that Section 8C, "Implemented the First Amendment in that it responded to particular constitutional rulings of the NLRB." And the Supreme Court in the same case said that the NLRA reflected a "Policy judgment favoring uninhibited, robust, and wide-open debate in labor disputes." And the Supreme Court said that freewheeling use of the written and spoken word has been expressly fostered by Congress and approved by the NLRB. So if the NLRA makes it inherently unlawful for employers in the workplace to have discussions about union issues or the exercise of protected rights, that news has not made its way to the Supreme Court or the courts of appeals.

 

And for my fourth and final point, it is worth talking about policy considerations in this area. I've worked in a large number of workplaces in my life. I started working at age 14 as a caddy. I worked as a movie theater usher. I worked in a public library. I worked as a musical director and show pianist and was represented by Local 6471 of the American Federation of Musicians. And I've been exposed to thousands of workplaces in the course of my career in private practice and in my years on the NLRB. An inherent part of every job is for employees and employers to have all kinds of workplace discussions -- all kinds. Some discussions involve safety, some involve important product quality or customer service issues, and other discussions may involve union issues or other NLRA protected rights. And by the way, employers in workplace discussions may affirmatively state the company respects the rights of employees to make their own decisions about union issues, or the company is committed to avoiding any unlawful interference with NLRA protected rights.

 

And the one other thing about policy is -- I'll say one more thing. The speech restrictions that are advocated by the NLRB General Counsel and supported by Craig and others, I find especially troubling and disappointing when they are viewed in conjunction with other NLRB decisions that recently have diminished the role played by NLRB elections and the manner in which NLRB elections occur. On August 25, the NLRB decided a case called Cemex Construction and Cemex indicates that the board will issue orders imposing union recognition on many more employers and employees, in many more cases without any employee voting in NLRB conducted secret ballot elections.

 

Separately, on August 25, the NLRB published new election procedures that will greatly accelerate the timetable for conducting elections and, in fact, to make sure that elections occur at the earliest date practicable. These new procedures, which will take effect at the end of the year, provide that in most cases, elections will take place first, and only after the election will the board determine who is eligible to vote in the election. No joke. The election goes first, and afterwards the board will determine who are eligible voters in the great majority of cases. So now, in the fewer number of cases where employees will even have the opportunity to vote in an NLRB secret ballot election, the NLRB general counsel seeks to extinguish the right of employers to say anything positive or negative when the subject matter in workplace discussions involves anything about a union.

 

Now, I don't think that can be reconciled with what the Supreme Court said in Chamber of Commerce v. Brown when they talked about the policy judgment that Congress placed in the NLRA, which was to have uninhibited, robust, and wide-open debate in labor disputes, including the, "freewheeling use of the written and spoken word." So I'll stop there. I'll say again, it's really a pleasure to be here at The Federalist Society meeting and to be on this panel with Craig and also Judge Readler.

 

Hon. Chad A. Readler:  That was great. Thank you to both of you. If your Bingo card had Phil arguing legislative history and Craig arguing the Florida governor, then you win. But I doubt that was on anyone's card. So you've both teed up some pretty interesting legal issues. So it seems like we have a statutory question of how to interpret the NLRA, what prohibitions that places on the employer, and then we have the First Amendment overlay, and we had both acknowledgement of the employer's speech rights under the First Amendment, and then maybe some rights of the employees to not be forced to hear certain kinds of speech, and maybe there's some constitutional avoidance doctrines that we should be thinking about. So if you're a judge, how do you sort of hash out all these legal arguments? What's the right way to sort of look at the statute against the First Amendment backdrop? And either of you can go first.

 

Craig Becker:  I'll jump in. I mean, I think that question really poses some questions about what Phil just said, because I think it's very important how we describe what the general counsel is arguing for. Phil called it "speech restrictions." "Speech restrictions in the workplace." But in fact, there are no speech restrictions at issue here. The general counsel is not arguing that the employer can't speak anytime, anyplace on the subject of the union and how employees should vote in a union election. All the general counsel is arguing is that the employer cannot discipline people who refuse to speak. There is no restriction on speech. That's exactly what the governor is arguing. So I think if you're a judge, you have to be very careful to look at exactly what's being argued for. The employer will still have vast advantages in speaking on this topic.

 

My old law professor, Jack Getman, many years ago, don't know how many decades ago, did a study of NLRB elections. It's very controversial in a number of respects, but one of the most important findings of this study was that employers are able to reach a key group that a union can't. And that key group is the undecided. That is, before a union election, employers have everybody in the workplace. Employers can walk throughout the workplace. Employers can talk to people, bring in their consultants. They keep the union agents outside the workplace. They have vast advantages in reaching everybody. The union can only reach the willing listeners. So this study found that the undecided, that critical segment, are reached by the employer and not by the union. So there's not going to be any restriction on employer speech. There will be a robust debate. What won't happen is there will be coerced listening and employees either threatened with or actually disciplined for not listening. So I'm not concerned about the First Amendment argument or the 8C argument, because if you clearly define what's at issue, there is no free speech issue, either under the statute or under the Constitution.

 

Hon. Philip A. Miscimarra:  Yeah, and I would say that, I think, Judge Readler, with respect to the question that you asked, what's a judge to do in looking at this? I think the first place that a judge would look, like other lawyers, is the text of the statute. And it's also possible that to the extent that the statute is not considered to be dispositive, again, no offense to the textualists here, legislative history is also worth looking at for guidance. And I think, with respect to the issues that we're talking about here, I think that they're consistent both in terms of the protection that the statute affords to these types of discussions, including meetings that take place on paid time.

 

And notwithstanding the distinctions that Craig tried -- suggested exist where the general counsel is just suggesting it's the mandatory nature of the meetings that makes them unlawful. That is precisely the same theory that the board embraced in 1946. And it's precisely the same thing that Congress repudiated in 1947. And to the extent that employers or other parties engage in protected speech that they have a right to engage in, then I think the predicate of the general counsel's current view, which is various requirements and additional rights can be imposed as a penalty for exercising that right to engage in protected speech. I think that those penalties or restrictions that encumber protected speech are themselves violative of the First Amendment.

 

Hon. Chad A. Readler:  Let me then pose this question to you, Phil. I think some of the policy considerations underlying the NLRB's interpretation would try to reflect the power dynamic here between oftentimes a very sophisticated employer and individual employees who might not be as deemed sophisticated. I just had a case involving Starbucks, it could be other employers. But you can have very sophisticated employers who are delivering a message to a captured or captive audience, and that audience may feel compelled to follow the instruction of the employer, at least the strong advice of the employer, and they may have economic reasons that they feel like require them to do so. I assume those are some of the policy considerations. Craig can probably give us more, but what's your response to that? And Craig, we'll let you follow up.

 

Hon. Philip A. Miscimarra:  Well, the one thing I'll say is, without question, employees have important rights under the National Labor Relations Act, and they're rights that warrant protection and need to be protected. But that's why we have a legislature. And so Congress in the National Labor Relations Act protected the rights of employees in various ways. Congress protected the rights of Employers in certain ways, and Congress protected the rights of unions and also put a significant variety of obligations on employers and unions, too.

 

So the National Labor Relations Act reflects various types of protection and choices that were made by Congress, taking into account all of the considerations, Judge Readler, that you just mentioned, the need for protection, the fact that employees may be economically dependent on their employer. But as I said before, the essence of every employment relationship is voluntary. Virtually every state still recognizes in some way employment at will. And the NLRB's job is to call balls and strikes in an even-handed manner. And before the NLRB, every party is entitled to the protection that the NLRA affords. And I think that it gets things in reverse to suggest that the NLRB should skew its jobs in trying to referee these important labor management issues and employment related issues by suggesting that one party should be afforded special protection by the NLRB, even if that diverges from what is reflected in the statute itself.

 

Craig Becker:  The fundamental part of the statute is that you can't say this is a voluntary relationship. If you don't like it, go elsewhere. By that argument, it would be fine to say, "I'm going to fire you if you sign a union card," that's illegal. And nobody argues that that's not illegal. Now, the notion that employees are particularly vulnerable to strong expressions of view by their employer, that's undoubtedly true. But we have a First Amendment and the Supreme Court has made clear, and Section 8C makes clear that that's not unlawful, even if we might think that's undue influence. The employer has no, as, as the board said prior to '47, the employer has no business, not only has no business trying to influence who sits on the other side of the table, but it's coercive for them to do so. That argument is clearly no longer possible, but a clear threat or discipline for protected activity, which is listening or not listening.

 

Do you think I could defend that it doesn't violate the act if a union agent goes out and says, "If I don't see you at tonight's union meeting, I'm going to break your arm." Am I going to be able to argue that the threat is not contained in the speech, that I can divide those two, as Phil has attempted to do under 8C, that the speech does not contain the threat because there's a period between the statement, "If I don't see you at tonight's meeting, period, I'm going to break your leg." There's a threat. Unquestionably there's a threat implicit in a captive audience meeting. It's not the implicit threat, it's an explicit threat. And when you tie that together with the strong urging of an opinion, "Come to this meeting, I'm going to urge you strongly to vote no in the upcoming election." And then if someone stands up at the meeting and says, "I've heard both sides, I know what I want to do, I want to leave." And the employer says, "If you leave, you'll be terminated." So tying the economic power and that threat directly to the message contemporaneously, obviously, that's what the act is intended to prohibit, and 8C allows the board to prohibit.

 

Hon. Philip A. Miscimarra:  And Judge Readler, if I could just --

 

Hon. Chad A. Readler:  Of course.

 

Hon. Philip A. Miscimarra:  -- add one thing. It's important to note that the NLRB general counsel's views, they're not limited to meetings and they're not limited to meetings that are characterized as mandatory. So the general counsel's memo that deals with these issues that was issued in April of last year explicitly stated that what the general counsel believes would be inherently unlawful or per se unlawful and inherently coercive are either meetings that deal with either union issues or the exercise of protected rights. Not just meetings, but also one on one discussions between an employer and even individual employees that occur on paid time.

 

So, number one, these restrictions are not limited to meetings. And number two, the general counsel has made very clear in the briefs that have been filed in several cases, one involving Cemex and another involving Starbucks, that the meetings don't have to be characterized as mandatory. The meetings in these discussions will be presumed to be mandatory, resulting in an implicit threat of discipline unless every one of these discussions dealing with union issues or the exercise of NLRA protected rights is preceded by a catalog of different disclaimers that the employer has to present that resemble Miranda rights, which have to be given to criminal suspects by law enforcement authorities before their people are placed under custodial interrogation. Except the assurances that the general counsel would require are longer than Miranda rights. And Craig was nice enough to make reference to the written version of my congressional testimony, and I quoted the assurances that the general counsel has indicated must precede any of these protected discussions and also Miranda rights. And the Miranda rights are actually considerably shorter. But these are very, very broad prohibitions, and they don't just relate to meetings, and they don't just relate to meetings or discussions that have been described as mandatory. It's a much more broad-based prohibition than that.

 

Hon. Chad A. Readler:  Okay. So, Craig, let me pose a question to you that the foundation is stare decisis. So this first 75-year period, I think the board had an unbroken practice of allowing employers to hold these types of meetings and convey this type of information. And that has now, at least from advice of the general counsel, that has changed. If you think of Dobbs, Roe was a 50-year-old decision where there were lots of arguments about reliance interests. Here we have 75 years. And did something change in the meantime that required the general counsel to revisit this issue? Or if a court's looking at this, why shouldn't they take into consideration that agencies change their mind quite often, especially when administrations change, and this position had not changed over many administrations?

 

Craig Becker:  I think that's a very good question, and I think probably that's the most powerful counterargument that the doctrine has existed for a long time. What's the reason for changing it now? And I think the answer, I would say, is a fewfold. One, I think the doctrine that permits captive audience meetings is so fundamentally contrary to the central purpose of the act, which is to prevent economic coercion and I think if you were to go and talk to people on the street, non-lawyers, and you would say, "Is it fair in a political election or a union election for employer to force employees to listen to their position on pain of an economic sanction," I think you'd have a large vote against that being lawful.

 

So I think it's just fundamentally inconsistent with the statute and common notions of fairness. I think there is -- the reason why it's come more to the fore recently is much greater use of captive audience meetings by employers. I think, like everything else in our society, the question of unions has become more polarized. Employers have run more vigorous campaigns in the last 20 to 30 years. There's been a number of studies which talk about the prevalence of the use of captive audiences. Something upwards of 80 percent of employers use multiple captive audiences before elections. I think at Amazon, the warehouse on Staten Island, employees were subject to countless captive audience meetings. So I think there has been a change in practice. But I think most fundamentally, this is simply wrong. Wrong under the statute and wrong as a matter of common sense.

 

Hon. Philip A. Miscimarra:  I would just add to the one point that Craig made. I don't go all the way back to 1935, when the National Labor Relations Act was adopted, but I go back at least to the 1950s, and I grew up in Pittsburgh, western Pennsylvania. When I was born, Pittsburgh was still -- there were steel mills all over town. The local paper in Pittsburgh didn't just have a business section, it had a business and labor section. And of course, the United Steel Workers has its headquarters -- had and still has their headquarters in Pittsburgh. But the notion that suddenly employers are resorting to workplace discussions, or as Craig calls them, captive audience speeches, more now than took place in the 30s, after the National Labor Relations Act was first adopted, or in the 1940s, when there was a proliferation of strikes after World War II. The act was adopted in the mid-30s during the New Deal. And if you don't believe that employers at that time had strong feelings about this new statute, you're wrong.

 

And the reason why there are so many protections for employees in the statute deals with all of the tactics and strategies that employers back then employed that had a very deleterious effect on employee rights and union rights. But I don't think one of the reasons for suddenly this doctrine, which the board had embraced in 1946 and which Congress repudiated in 1947, I don't think that changes in practice in terms of these types of discussions being worse now than they were back then. I don't think that that really survives serious scrutiny. And I also think that it's not possible to think that the Supreme Court and the courts of appeals and the board have all been wrong every day for the past 70 years. I just don't think that that's reasonable either.

 

Hon. Chad A. Readler:  So we're fortunate to have two leading experts on labor law and two former members of the NLRB. So maybe ask if we zoom out a little bit, is this rule change or change in approach reflective of a broader agenda at the board itself or in the Biden administration? Are there other lessons to draw here? Are there other issues that we should be thinking about as we try to sort of look at the full picture?

 

Craig Becker:  Well, I do think that, appropriately, the position of the general counsel on this and other issues does reflect the Biden administration's general position on labor. Not that Biden administration is giving directions to the general counsel, but you all know probably that, for the first time in history, President Biden removed the prior general counsel consistent with unitary executive theory and decisions about the President's authority control the Executive Branch generally. The general counsel is not protected by just cause provision in the statute, unlike the board members and President Biden exercises authority to remove the prior general counsel and appoint a new one.

 

So I think it's consistent generally with the administration's position, obviously not directed on these specific issues. I think it's also consistent with, and this goes to Phil's very accurate statement that the general counsel has taken a very broad position, perhaps broader than what I've described. Another thing that's been, I think, quite unique about General Counsel Abruzzo is how open she's been in the theories that she is either propounding or even going to propound, that as she's announced long in advance, sometimes through formal memos, sometimes through social media, what she's going to argue.

 

And I once asked her, what's the theory about doing that? And she was very frank in saying, "I'm trying to create a discussion. I'm trying to get people to think, including the board members, before they have to decide these issues." So the fact that she's propounded a very broad theory, I think is intended to provoke a discussion about what the statute says and what's the best policy, not necessarily to accomplish everything that's set forth in her argument. So I think that's, in both of those ways, it's consistent with overall administration policy appropriately and then in process, I think it's consistent with her approach.

 

Hon. Philip A. Miscimarra:  And I said before, and I'll repeat this, that I have respect for the General Counsel Abruzzo who was, among other things, the deputy general counsel during almost my entire four and a half years on the board when I served. And I totally agree with Craig that she has been very open with the theories that she has been advocating. And the general counsel, as most of you know, functions like the NLRB's very important prosecuting attorney, and she has embraced that role with a vengeance. And it is also true that President Biden has described his administration as the most pro union administration in history. And I think that's probably true, too.

 

And as Craig alluded to this, but the former general counsel, Peter Robb, received an email literally 23 minutes after President Biden was sworn in indicating that he was going to be removed that day if he didn't resign, even though roughly ten months remained in Peter Robb's term as general counsel. And in fact, he declined the opportunity to resign, and he was removed that very day. And that particular issue in the president's -- whether the president has the right to remove the general counsel at will, is something that's still the subject of litigation, including one case that I'm currently handling for a client. So that remains unresolved.

 

But I do think that it's worth noting the NLRB is an independent regulatory agency. It's also sometimes called a quasi-adjudicative agency. And there's lots and lots of Supreme Court case law and other case law indicating one case, First National Maintenance, the Supreme Court said that the act is not intended to advance any individual's interest, but it's intended instead to foster, in a neutral manner, a system in which the conflict between the interests of different parties can be resolved. So it's damaging to the NLRB. It undermines the NLRB's role for the board to be regarded as an extension of any particular administration. And I think that viewing the board in that light, it really undermines confidence that parties on all sides, both employees, employers, unions, and the public, can have in the board institutionally. And I think that's very damaging not only to the board, but also to the administration of justice in these cases. And the board is the only place in the first instance that these cases can be adjudicated.

 

Hon. Chad A. Readler:  Great. Well, we'd love to take questions from all of you. I see a microphone here in the back. I have more questions, but we'll go ahead and start with the gentleman who's up at the mic now. Maybe say who you are would be great.

 

Pepper Crutcher:  I'm Pepper Crutcher. I'm the guy who introduced you.

 

Hon. Chad A. Readler:  I knew that. But just for the general --

 

Pepper Crutcher:  Flip side, of the coin. Mr. Miscimarra, if your analysis is correct, how do you continue to justify the Peerless Plywood rule if you do? For Mr. Becker, if your analysis is correct, how do you continue to justify, if you do, the union demands regularly conceded by employers that new hires be required on work time to listen to union membership solicitations made by union representatives?

 

Hon. Philip A. Miscimarra:  I think in terms of Peerless Plywood you're referring to; the board has had a long-standing practice in representation case that bars captive audience speeches during the 24 hours preceding any election. And a couple of things. One is that doctrine which has been around for a long time, it relates to the board's conduct of elections. It doesn't find that those discussions would end up being unfair labor practices under the act, violations of the act. It would just be found to be objectionable conduct for purposes of overturning an election. And that is uniquely within the board's authority to monitor. And the board has also for many, many years regulated various types of election related conduct as it pertains to elections. But the protection that's afforded by Section 8C relates to alleged unfair labor practices, and it's explicit on that. It says the expressions of views, argument, or opinion shall not constitute or be evidence of an unfair labor practice under any of the provisions of this act. And that's the most important distinction between the two.

 

Craig Becker:  Can I take the liberty of answering both questions? The distinction between representation proceedings and objections and unfair labor practices is obviously important, both for the reason Phil just mentioned, which is that the free speech proviso is expressly limited to unfair labor practices, and also because several courts have held that overturning an election is not a sanction which implicates the First Amendment. So in the context of unions, for example, filing lawsuits on behalf of employees on the eve of an election, that's protected petitioning activity. And yet, several courts, the D. C. Circuit, and the Fourth Circuit, have said it's still a grant of benefits and you can overturn an election on that basis. So this argument is even stronger that captive audience meetings should be objectionable than the argument the general counsel is making, which is that they should be unlawful. The question about meetings to inform employees in a newly organized workplace about the union enjoying the union is a good one, and I actually haven't thought about it before, so I appreciate the question. I do think it's different in the sense that you have a balance. The employer is not holding the meeting to express its own views, but rather is acceding to a request by the union to be able to speak to employees about joining the union and the other benefits being union members. So I don't think it involves the same type of threat, but it is a good question. I'd like to think about it some more.

 

Hon. Chad A. Readler:  Okay. Go to this side.

 

Tammy McCutchen:  Thank you. Tammy McCutchen. Most people think of me as a wage an hour girl, but in the wee dawn of time, I actually was among the associates representing Overnight Transportation Company in the Teamster Corporate campaign. And at that time, I actually litigated -- we lost, of course, First Amendment. We had the Fourth Circuit, and the board said, a button that said, "Give Jim a chance," Jim being a new CEO, was an unlawful promise, and a wheel of misfortune, which helped employees determine how much money they would lose if they went on strike, was an unlawful threat. So I'd like you guys to back up a little bit and help us understand what is a threat, what is a promise, and how does the First Amendment restrict findings that truthful factual statement like the wheel of misfortune could actually be a ULP -- it can be a violation? And also one more. What if, instead of a mandatory meeting, I promised every employee who attended a $50 gift certificate to the Texas Roadhouse?

 

Hon. Philip A. Miscimarra:  I'll take the threat question, Tammy. And what Section 8C makes explicit reference to are threats of reprisal or force as not being within the protection of the statute. Otherwise, the board does interpret the threat in a variety of different ways, and it's true that threats -- if there are threats, they can be explicit or they can be implied. But this was the specific focus of Congress in 1947, when Congress amended the act. And what Section 8C is quite explicit about is the expression of views, arguments, or opinion will not be considered unlawful, period, unless the expression itself contains a threat of reprisal or force. I'm not going to go into the details, but there's also a very important Supreme Court case that was decided called Counterman a short while ago, and the Counterman case deals with a threat of violence. And the Supreme Court held that the First Amendment requires, even in connection with a criminal matter involving a threat of violence, there has to be some consideration of the speaker's subjective intent before because of the First Amendment protection that speakers have. So even in a threat of violence case, the Supreme Court in the Counterman case, it's C-O-U-N-T-E-R-M-A-N, in the Counterman decision really introduces, I think, some significantly greater protection for speakers from a First Amendment perspective than previously existed.

 

Craig Becker:  That is a really good question. Justice Breyer, in his dissent in Sorrell said, the First Amendment, as understood by today's Supreme Court, is essentially a radical deregulatory tool because all regulation involves precisely the kind of hard questions you're asking. It's a threat based on its subject matter. That is, you say the same thing about joining a union, but say the same thing not about joining a union, and it doesn't violate the NLRA subject matter discrimination, and it's true of many, many statutes. I would add to your list of problems. I asked my president, Liz Shuler, to take a picket sign and walk back and forth peacefully in front of the door of this hotel with a sign that says, "Don't enter because the Mayflower is using a cleaning contractor which pays substandard wages," per se, unlawful under the statute. How is that possible? So under this statute and many others, there is regulation of speech and a very difficult line drawing. That's what Gissel is all about, what is a threat and what is not. And there is very, very difficult line drawing to be had. In terms of the last part of your question, there is an argument there, too. In fact, Unite Here has made the argument different from the general counsel that what's unlawful about captive audience meetings is that they always involve a grant of benefits because you're basically allowing people to sit and do nothing and get paid when otherwise they'd have to be working. So, yeah, maybe a grant of benefits, too. But your question just raises a host of difficult First Amendment problems about this and other regulatory schemes.

 

Hon. Chad A. Readler:  Okay.  Over here.

 

Richard Samp:  Richard Samp with the New Civil Liberties Alliance. First of all, this is a subject I knew nothing about before today, so I wanted to thank the panel for a very interesting presentation. I was interested in particular with Craig's discussion of the Florida law that I gather makes it illegal for an employer to coerce employees to listen to woke speech. And it convinced me that that law is unconstitutional. So I guess I wanted to address that issue to Philip, what your view of that Florida law is, and if you don't have a view that you're willing to express, I would be interested in -- I can't think of any possible constitutional justification for the law. What would be the best possible argument that you would make for Governor DeSantis if you were trying to defend it?

 

Hon. Philip A. Miscimarra:  Well, it's interesting. The one thing that my mother always taught me, and this was even before I went to law school, is don't opine about a law that you have not read and don't give advice to a client that you don't represent. So I think I'm going to withhold judgment because I literally have not spent, not even a minute, probably not even five seconds focusing on that law. And I'm not in a position, I think, to give an informed answer to those questions.

 

Hon. Chad A. Readler:  These are excellent questions. So we'll continue on this side.

 

Jim Young:  Jim Young, National Right to Work Legal Defense Foundation. I was -- fascinating presentation. Thank both speakers. I was interested in the things I didn't hear about. I heard very little about employee rights. And as Justice Thomas wrote in Lechmere lo these many years ago, the act protects employee rights, not union rights, not employer rights, but primarily employee rights. So I don't know how you make people listen. They can be present, but they can't be forced to listen. And I also didn't hear any mention of Excelsior lists, which give union organizers the tool to appear on the front porches or at the front stoops of employees during an organizing campaign and during the critical period leading up to an election. Aren't those employees also forced to listen? And do we also have to cast aside Excelsior? Is everybody here a labor lawyer? I don't think so. If you're not a labor lawyer, raise your hand. Okay. Excelsior list is the employee list. Names, addresses, if they maintain them, email addresses, telephone numbers, and they're given to all the parties to an election. I didn't hear any mention of those -- the instrumentality to force people to listen. Could the speakers offer any comment on that?

 

Hon. Philip A. Miscimarra:  Yeah. I'll just mention one or two things. In terms of employee rights. An important part of speech in relation to workplace discussions is so that employees are exposed to what an employer thinks or guidance that an employer can give. And certainly in an organizing drive, employees are exposed to the union's views. And it's also important for employees to be exposed, I think, to employers’ views. Whether employees choose to exercise their right to have union representation or whether they choose not to, those are important issues, regardless of how that turns out. And they're important implications for the workplace. They're important implications for the company. They're important rights, but also important obligations that relate to employees.

 

And one of the interesting things about a different aspect of legislative history -- I mentioned that when the Taft Hartley Act was amended in 1947, John F. Kennedy was a freshman House member. Well, by 1959, he was a senator, and he chaired the conference committee that considered the 1959 Landrum Griffin Act amendments to the act. And he advocated that there be enough time in every election, at least 30 days, so that employees would not be rushed into making a decision too fast when they were unfamiliar with the relevant issues. So I think employee rights are very much implicated in these workplace discussion restrictions, because, as the Supreme Court has indicated in a number of different cases, including the Chamber of Commerce case, the NLRA contemplated robust discussion about these issues. And I think that part of the reason for that under the act is so that employees can get the perspective, multiple perspectives, not only from the union, but from employers as well.

 

Craig Becker:  Yeah. I frankly don't understand the question. This has nothing to do with the union rights. The whole discussion is about employee rights, employer rights after 1947, to support or to refrain from supporting, to listen or to refrain from listening. So this is all about employee rights. In terms of the Excelsior list, it's an accepted practice, I believe, in every state, in elections for public office, that the voter rolls are open. You can go and get a list and find everybody who voted in the last election and their address. And many of us find it annoying when those people call us up and tell us to vote and vote for a particular person or knock on the door or leave a flyer. But I don't think any of us find it coercive that that goes on. No one's being forced to listen. No one's being forced to take that flyer. I mean, the analogy would be if the representative came to the door and the person said, "I don't want to talk to you." And they said, "If you don't talk to me, I'll break your arm." That's the analogy. If you don't come to the meeting, you'll be fired. It's all about employee rights.

 

Hon. Chad A. Readler:  I saw you standing. I saw you just sit down.

 

Unidentified Speaker:  I didn't want to get in the way of lunch, but I have a quick question. Abruzzo's memo, is there any concern about the chilling effects of Abruzzo's sort of campaign to overturn the NLRB's decision, not only through one case litigation, but also through multiple cases and her memo?

 

Hon. Philip A. Miscimarra:  Well, I will say, I expressed the view before that I think the prosecution of these cases, not just the claims in those cases, infringe on First Amendment rights. I think that the NLRB's prosecution of these cases also infringes on First Amendment rights, because at least these cases, when they're being prosecuted, produce a chilling effect on all employers with respect to any speech that they engage in or workplace discussions that they choose to engage in. And if they are lawful, then the threat of prosecution is a very significant thing, especially for employers who are involved in some of these cases, because as everyone knows, an NLRB unfair labor practice case often takes three to five years or more from start to finish. And sometimes court litigation makes those cases last for five to ten years.

 

The one other thing that's very important in the Supreme Court Counterman case that I made reference to is the Supreme Court expressed great concern about the chilling effect of restrictions on employer speech, excuse me, restrictions on a speaker's speech, even in criminal cases involving threats of violence. And the Supreme Court expressed a concern about the chilling effect on the speaker. In these employer NLRB cases, the speaker is the employer. The Supreme Court didn't express concern about the chilling effect on the recipient of whatever is alleged to be a threat. It's a chilling effect. The Supreme Court was concerned about the impact on the speaker. And I think that gives rise to significant concerns about possible infringement that results just from the prosecution of these types of cases or an indication that these types of discussions will result in prosecution.

 

Craig Becker:  I mean, the chilling effect is in some sense the answer to the stare decisis question. That is, the general counsel is given notice, very public, as we've both described, that I'm going to advance this theory. I now am advancing this theory. So in terms of reliance interests, those are being lessened by that very public advocacy. In terms of chilling effect, I'm not concerned about chilling coercion. I'd be concerned about chilling speech, but I'm not concerned about chilling coercion. And what's going to be the sanction? If there's no coercion, if this is really willing listening, and somehow, it's still held to be unlawful, the sanction would be a notice posting and a cease-and-desist order. The only meaningful sanction is going to be if someone is fired. So unless there's economic retaliation, there's not going to be a meaningful sanction even if speech is at issue, which I don't think it is.

 

Hon. Chad A. Readler:  Okay. We have time for two very quick questions, so we'll start here.

 

Dan McLaughlin:  All right. Dan McLaughlin from National Review. A big picture question. I'll set the context for just a moment, but I promise there is a short question at the end of it. I covered the ALJ and board decisions that were ultimately overturned by the Third Circuit in the Federalist case involving a joke tweet being treated as an unfair labor practice. And it seemed to me, at least as a veteran litigator, but from outside of labor law, that if you read things like Gissel Packing and then you looked at how they were actually applied by the board and the ALJ, that fundamental concepts like reasonable listener and the relevance of evidence were just being applied in radically different ways than you would find almost anywhere else in the law. So I guess my question is, on a big picture level, is the board and the agency a little too siloed from how law works in every other area of practice?

 

Hon. Philip A. Miscimarra:  Well, I think the answer to that is yes. The board has a range of cases. The biggest one involves cases where, for many years, the board provided for special protection that would be afforded to sexually or racially offensive statements and actions, even if those offensive statements and actions would uniformly result in discipline or discharge, and consistent with anti-harassment policies that are required in Title VII cases and EEOC regulations. And the board recently, in a case called Lion Elastomers, reinstated that special protection afforded to sexually or racially offensive conduct. And there are a number of other cases where the board really focuses more on its statute to the exclusion of other statutes. And I think that's been an issue with the board generally, and it's an issue with the board at the present time.

 

Craig Becker:  Believe it or not. I actually agree with that a little bit. I think that I'd much rather the board prohibit actual coercion than try to draw the impossible line that you're describing and that Tammy described between is this slightly over the line? Is it not over the line? Going back to the Getman study I described earlier, very controversially, he found that most of what the board prohibits has no effect on employees, even promise of benefit, what the board might consider be a threat. But what really matters is being forced to listen, and that is clearly coercion. I really think that it might make sense for the board to stick to what's really coercion and shy slightly away from the kind of cases you're describing.

 

Hon. Chad A. Readler:  Well, I am tempted to end on a point of agreement, so I apologize. I think we are about out of time, but I'm sure our panelists will stay around for any final questions. But many of us raised our hand as non-labor lawyers. This was incredibly informative, even for those of you who are labor lawyers. I suspect you learned a lot. So please join me in thanking the panel. And enjoy lunch.

 

     

 

 

11:00 a.m. - 12:30 p.m.
Second Amendment: Will the Supreme Court Adhere to Bruen (and Originalism) in Rahimi and Beyond?

2023 National Lawyers Convention

Topics: Constitution • Second Amendment • Supreme Court
State Room
The Mayflower Hotel
1127 Connecticut Avenue NW
Washington, DC 20006

Share

Event Video

Listen & Download

Description

Oral argument was held in U.S. v. Rahimi on November 7, 2023. The case asks whether 18 U.S.C. Section 922(g)(8), which prohibits possession of firearms by persons subject to domestic violence restraining orders violates the Second Amendment on its face. What does the Court's jurisprudence foretell about the decision? Is there an obvious originalist answer?

Featuring:

  • Prof. William G. Merkel, Associate Professor, Charleston School of Law
  • Prof. Mark W. Smith, Senior Fellow, Ave Maria School of Law
  • Mr. David H. Thompson, Managing Partner, Cooper & Kirk
  • Moderator: Hon. Lawrence VanDyke, United States Court of Appeals, Ninth Circuit

Overflow: Cabinet & Senate Rooms

Speakers

Event Transcript

Nathan Kaczmarek:  Good morning. My name is Nate Kaczmarek. I help direct the Practice Groups here for The Federalist Society. We have a great panel and an important topic, so let’s get started.

Welcome to this special session sponsored by the Practice Groups titled, “Second Amendment: Will the Supreme Court Adhere to Bruen (and Originalism) in Rahimi and beyond?” The vast majority of the panels and the content this weekend are the result of our FedSoc leadership volunteering their time and formidable expertise to support our mission, and we’re grateful to each of them. If you’d like to get more involved with the Practice Groups and help drive our programs and content, I’d be delighted to talk to you. So please don’t hesitate to catch me in the halls or shoot me an email so we can talk after the conference.

Before I turn things over to Judge VanDyke, I also wanted to briefly take a moment to thank The Federalist Society staff who have helped to put this NLC together. Please join me in thanking my hard working colleagues.

[Applause]

Nathan Kaczmarek:  Turning to our moderator, I was instructed by him to keep it very short. All of the bios for him and our panelists have been provided to you already, and they are available on our website. Judge Lawrence VanDyke serves as a circuit judge on the U.S. Court of Appeals for the Ninth Circuit. Prior to that, he had a very distinguished legal career, which he forbade me to mention. So I’ll just say that to know him even a little or to speak to his family or his clerks is to understand immediately his deep warmth, generosity, and his brilliance. Please welcome our panel.

[Applause]

Hon. Lawrence VanDyke:  Well, thank you, Nate, and thank you very much to The Federalist Society for setting up an amazing panel with amazing panelists on a great topic, and it’s great to see so many people interested in it. I see that, like my court, The Federalist Society has Judge Bea sitting here right in front so that—my colleague, Judge Bea—so that assuming that things will go off the rails and he’ll have to step in and might have to put some semblance of order back in here. [Laughter]

But this morning, we have David Thompson and Mark Smith with us. Before we start, we had a third panelist, but unfortunately, he fell ill and so was not able to join us. But Bill Merkel, professor at Charleston School of Law, is not able to be with us this morning. But David Thompson is going to channel his best inner professor and be able to try to give us his perspective on that this morning. But David’s going to lead us off.

David is a Managing Partner at Cooper & Kirk. He’s argued before the United States Supreme Court on several occasions and each of the 13 federal courts of appeals. He’s litigated in over 30 district courts around the country, as well as before many state courts. And he’s currently litigating dozens of Second Amendment cases. He’s a graduate of Harvard College and Harvard Law School. And then after David speaks this morning, then he’s going to be followed by Mark Smith.

Mark Smith is a constitutional attorney and Host of the Four Boxes Diner Second Amendment Channel, whose videos on YouTube have been viewed 23 million times. Mark is a Visiting Fellow with Oxford University’s Department of Pharmacology. He’s also a Senior Fellow with the Ave Maria School of Law. He’s a New York Times bestselling author who frequently appears on Fox News. His most recent books include Disarmed and also First They Came for the Gun Owners and Duped. He’s published in many law reviews, including the Harvard Journal of Law & Public Policy.

So what we’re going to do this morning is David is going to lead us off, and then Mark is going to speak, and then David is going to give some comments, maybe even ask a question or two, about -- to Mark, and we’ll just go back and forth. And then we’ll obviously have some time for questions and answers once that’s all finished. Thank you very much. David?

[Applause]

Prof. David H. Thompson:  Well, thank you, Judge, and it’s a pleasure to be on this panel with both Judge VanDyke, who’s a hero to anyone who cares about the Second Amendment, and Mark Smith, whose YouTube channel is now must-see TV for anyone who cares about the Second Amendment. I want to talk about Rahimi.

This week, the United States Supreme Court heard oral argument in that case. It’s a case that’s been rushed to the United States Supreme Court by Merrick Garland with the intention of doing maximum damage to the Second Amendment. And the case has the worst facts imaginable. Here are the allegations.

In 2019, the defendant, Zackey Rahimi, bashed his girlfriend’s head into the dashboard of their car, and when someone tried to intervene and protect his girlfriend, he whipped out a gun and started shooting it in the air to ward off any intervention. Rahimi then—allegedly—engaged in five shooting sprees over the coming months. I’ll just share with you the details of one of them.

He was at a [Whataburger] with one of his buddies, and his friend’s credit card was denied. And like any rational person, he whipped out his gun and started shooting it into the ceiling, not once, but on multiple occasions. I guess once wasn’t enough to show his displeasure with Visa. In any event, this is the man that we’re dealing with. And investigators then started looking into this, and they found that a protective order had been entered after bashing the girlfriend’s head into the dashboard and that he was in violation of 18 U.S.C. § 922 (g)(8). And that’s the statute that he’s challenging here.

Now, what are we to do with someone like Mr. Rahimi? The rather obvious answer is lock him up and throw away the key forever.

[Applause]

Prof. David H. Thompson:  That way, he’ll never have a gun ever again, okay? But for whatever reason, the district attorney in Texas is slow walking this case. There are charges that are pending. They would lead to Mr. Rahimi being in prison for 60 to 70 years, but they are in a slow boat. And so that has permitted Rahimi and his public defendant lawyer to come forward and challenge 922 (g)(8).

So let’s start with the Bruen methodology. We start with the text. It’s really not complicated. The Operative Clause, of course, as you all know, says, “The right of the people to keep and bear arms shall not be infringed.” Can we just pause a moment? If we were all collectively to sit around a table and try to come up with words that would capture an enduring, robust right to self-defense, could we really have done any better? I mean, they just said it; it’s so crystal clear. And the government, not surprisingly, does not make any reference to the actual text in their arguments.

And the reason is, of course, Rahimi was keeping, that is, possessing a handgun, which is an arm. And so the only possible argument for excluding him from the text is the meaning of the term “people”—the people. But that’s been addressed in the Heller decision. Justice Scalia wrote in all six other provisions of the Constitution that mention “the people.” The term unambiguously refers to all members of the political community, not an unspecified subset.

As we said in United States v. Verdugo, “the people” refers to a class of persons who are part of a national community who have otherwise developed sufficient connection with this country to be considered part of that community. And we know from the First Amendment—and Lord knows we know from the Fourth Amendment—that criminals have First and Fourth Amendment rights. That’s why we have an exclusionary rule. And so it’s no wonder, given the meaning of the term “the people,” that the solicitor general does not quote the text.

Now, the solicitor general instead has a gloss on the text that she repeated like a mantra over and over again, saying, “It’s responsible law-abiding people who have a right to keep and bear arms.” Now, there’s a litany of problems with this approach.

The first is she’s quoting from Heller and Bruen. But as Justice Barrett made clear this week, that was a descriptive -- it’s not even dicta in Heller and Bruen. Nobody was challenging that Heller and Bruen were law-abiding citizens. It was rather just simply a description of the fact that they were law-abiding citizens. And they’re very good reasons why the Second Amendment test should not be a responsibility.

As the chief justice made clear in his questionings, he said, “Well, if somebody goes 30 miles an hour in a 25-mile an hour speed zone, are they responsible? And what about somebody,” the chief justice said, “who fails to recycle?” And you can imagine a variety of leftwing jurisdictions saying, “Are you a vegetarian? How many times do you do yoga? How many pronouns do you have?” I mean, there are all sorts of metrics that the government could use to limit the Second Amendment. That’s not the system the Founders had.

And so, to her credit, the solicitor general read the room, realized that wasn’t going anywhere, and she said, “Well, what I mean by responsible, I mean, is dangerousness.” Well, last time I checked, those aren’t really synonyms. But in any event, she fell back, and she kind of called out on her sleight of hand.

Now, I do want to note that even though, as she was saying, “Well, responsible means dangerous,” she also said that with respect to law abiding, that doesn’t include dangerous. And she was holding out the possibility that anyone who commits a felony can be stripped of their Second Amendment rights forever. Throw a pile of dirt in a wetland, lose your Second Amendment rights. Make an improper tax deduction, no Second Amendment rights. Dabble in a little Martha Stewart insider trading, no Second Amendment rights. [Laughter]

And so we have another case. We call it, at Cooper & Kirk, the “Jean Valjean” case. It’s a man who stole a loaf of bread 40 years ago to feed his family. And the Third Circuit has, in an en banc decision—an excellent decision—has just struck down that statute as applied to Mr. Range. And Justice Barrett made reference to that case. And not surprisingly, Merrick Garland put that one on a slow boat and extended the time for the cert petition, sped up Rahimi so that Rahimi will be in front of the court, not Jean Valjean. And so we may be back next year at the convention talking about the Range case.

But going back to Rahimi, the bottom line is that Rahimi is covered by the text. So under Bruen, now we turn to history. And the burden—this is important—the burden shifts to the government. The government must come up with an appropriate analog to justify departing from the text. The basic idea is simple. The text governs. But if at the time of the Founding the text was understood not to have some sort of limitation, then that limitation still applies.

Now, the Department of Justice has a little bit of difficulty understanding the consequences of a burden shift because they articulated in their briefs—and again this week at oral argument—that even if there’s no regulation, they should still win. Well, that’s not the way it works. And Bruen confirmed this obvious point.

Bruen said, “When a challenged regulation addresses a general societal problem that has persisted since the eighteenth century, the lack of a distinctly similar historical regulation addressing that problem is relevant evidence that the challenged regulation is inconsistent with a Second Amendment.” So, in other words, they’ve got the burden, and if they don’t have anything, they lose.

Now, here are a few other methodological points that are relevant in Rahimi. One is, what’s the right time period? Can you look to 1900 to divine the public meaning of the Second Amendment? No, you can’t. And we’re lucky to have Mark Smith here, who has written the definitive takedown of the left’s efforts to try to first say, “Well, we should really look at Reconstruction, and then we should extend now decades beyond to understand”—and that’s all inappropriate.

Another methodological point is the government is trying to say, “Well, we shouldn’t confine ourselves to looking at the history of firearms regulation.” The government obviously wants to try to get away from looking at the history of firearms regulation because there was very little firearms regulation that really curtailed in significant, meaningful, and pernicious ways the text of the Constitution at the time of the Founding. And so the government knows that if the focus is on the history of regulation of firearms, they’re going to lose most of their defenses of their crazy gun control laws.

And so what the government says is, “Well, look. When we’re looking at other constitutional sources, we don’t blind ourselves to Blackstone. We don’t blind ourselves to Joseph Story’s commentaries. We don’t blind ourselves to The Federalist Papers.” And, of course, they’re right. Judges looking at this shouldn’t blind themselves to that here either, but they should look at those sources only far as they relate to firearms regulation.

Here again, Bruen made this clear. “The government must demonstrate that the regulation is consistent with this nation’s historical tradition of firearm regulation. Only if a firearm regulation is consistent with this nation’s historical tradition may a court conclude that the individual’s conduct falls outside the Second Amendment’s unqualified command.” Okay.

Now, the analogues also have to match the “how” and the “why” of the statute that’s being challenged. What Bruen meant with respect to the “why” is that the purpose of the law has to be the same. And with respect to the “how,” the means of obtaining that purpose has to be the same. And they don’t have to be identical twins, but they do need to be distinctly similar.

So what sort of analogues does the government have? Well, the government first starts by trying to sort of weasel out of having to find analogs by saying that, “Domestic violence,” they tell us, “really wasn’t seen as a problem at the time of the Founding.” And so it’s hardly surprising that there wasn’t regulation about domestic violence. This is wrong in every respect.

We were founded as a Judeo-Christian country. And do you think Cotton Mather would have thought that it was okay to beat your wife? Do you think he thought, “Oh, yeah. Love your neighbor as yourself, except if it’s your wife, and then you can beat her up as much as you want”? Well, that’s not what he said. He condemned it from the pulpit, from pulpit after pulpit after pulpit across the country at the time of the Founding.

Domestic abuse was condemned. Those who engaged in it were condemned as beasts. And it wasn’t just at the pulpit. The law also condemned these individuals. And Blackstone makes that very clear as well. So the premise of the government’s argument that, somehow, at the time of the Founding, spousal abuse was permitted is wrong, factually. So what does the solicitor general rely on? Well, there are two sources of analogues. The first is the surety system. And for those of you who don’t tuck Blackstone under your pillow at night, let me describe to you what the surety system was.

There were a variety of different surety systems, but the one that I want to focus on was basically someone could come forward—let’s say a wife—and say, “My husband is a danger to me.” And then a judge would engage in an individualized finding of whether there was a credible threat and credible evidence as to whether that was true. And if so, the person who was accused could still keep a firearm, could keep and possess it, provided that they could find two people in the community who would come and vouch for them and who would put up money that would be lost if there was any subsequent misbehavior. And if two people wouldn’t come forward, the person went to prison. And that was the system they had.

And it was really a very clever system because it relied on the wisdom of judges who had to make this individualized finding, and it also reminded on -- depended on someone’s standing in the community. Does anyone think that Adam Lanza or Jared Loughner would be able to find multiple members of the community to come forward and say, “Yeah, this nut job can be trusted with a gun”? I don’t think so.

And so if you posted the sureties, you just had to behave, and if you didn’t, you went to prison. And so that was one of the primaries. It wasn’t the only way, but it was one of the primary ways that domestic abuse was dealt with at the time of the Founding. And it was a system of preventative justice. But it was a system of preventative justice that did depend upon an individualized finding of dangerousness.

Now, if we translate that into Bruen and look at, “Well, how does that match up to the ‘how’ and the ‘why?’” The “why” is the same. The purpose is the same, as this is a person who’s been determined to be a highly dangerous, credible threat of physical violence. But the means was very different, right? You had members of the community who could come in and vouch for the person, and the person could potentially continue to keep and possess a firearm.

So the point is that the Second Amendment clearly allows for a system of preventative justice, one that aims at disarming people like Rahimi. I doubt there are two people who would have been willing to come forward. Maybe that guy whose credit card didn’t work would have scrounged together a few bucks. But it’s very likely he would not be able to meet a modern day surety system, and nothing would preclude a state from having a modern day surety system.

Now, the second -- but the means is very different, and so the government really should not get credit for the surety system as an analog. Now, the second analog the government points to is an affray. And an affray is conduct that’s been committed to the terror of the public: so someone who’s a drunken rioter has committed an affray, someone who’s beaten somebody else up has committed an affray, someone who’s gone to a burger joint and shot a gun into the roof has committed an affray.

The most important thing to know about the affray is it is a criminal offense. And as such, there would be the full panoply of protections, criminal law protections, the right to a trial by jury, the right to a high standard of proof. And 922 (g)—with its focus on domestic restraining orders—domestic violence restraining orders does not have those protections.

Rahimi didn’t have a lawyer, and he really had the deck stacked against him when he was considering signing the protective order because, if he had not, he would have had to pay all the attorneys’ fees associated with this. And for someone who’s really know, that doesn’t matter, so know he had to sign the paper. But there’ll be tens of thousands of Americans who can’t face that sort of crippling financial liability and will just go ahead and sign whatever is put in front of them. And that’s very pernicious.

And so here again, we have a match as to the purpose, the so-called “why,” but we don’t have a match as to the means is what has been argued. And I think there’s considerable force to that. I tend to think, based on the arguments and the questioning at oral argument, the Court will find that the sureties and the affrays are proper analogues. And the Court may well emphasize that Rahimi didn’t even contest the individualized findings. And so that may be the dispositive point.

There are other analogues that at least the amici have pointed to. They’ve pointed to the fact that slaves were disarmed, and Native Americans were disarmed at the time of the Founding. The problem—as even the solicitor general recognizes—is they were not understood to be part of the people. Moreover, the “why” behind those laws was there was a fear of armed insurrection, and that’s obviously very far afield from the why behind 922(g)(8).

Now, you might be thinking, “Doesn’t Rahimi have any due process rights?” And he does, but unfortunately, he never raised that point. You might be thinking, “How can the federal government—even under Wickard v. Filburn—have the authority to be regulating something like this under the Commerce Clause?” That’s an interesting question, and it’s one he didn’t raise, so the Court is not going to have the opportunity to look at this.

Now, as was made reference to at the beginning, our fellow panelist is not here. And so we want to try to give due regard to the other arguments that might be made on the other side of all this. And so I think the best way to do that is to take a selection of quotes from the oral argument this week. Unless you think that I’m caricaturing anyone, these are all direct quotes from the justices. Let’s start at random with Justice Jackson. Okay.

Justice Jackson said, “I’m trying to understand whether we can really be analyzing this consistent with the Bruen test at the level of generality of dangerousness. I wonder whether we need to be taking into account how historically domestic violence in particular was treated so that if we had evidence that men who engaged in domestic violence were actually perceived not as dangerous from the standpoint of disarmament, what would we do in that situation?”

Well, answer is that physical violence -- we may have learned how to split the atoms in 1791, but physical violence hasn’t changed. If somebody hits you in the head in 1791, it hurts just as much if they hit you in the head today. It was perceived as violent and dangerous then, and it is violent and dangerous now. It was a scourge then and now. And so the premise of her question is wrong.

Now, another question she had was, “But you seem to be suggesting that what we’re looking for is Reconstruction error sources, I suppose, that apply to the regulation of white Protestant men related to domestic violence.” This is wrong at every conceivable level.

First of all, we’re not looking to the Reconstruction—Mark Smith will address that—at 1791. That’s true for the states, but, I mean, this is a federal statute. Under what conceivable rationale would we be looking to Reconstruction with respect to the federal government?

The second is that there’s zero reason we would confine our analysis to the way white Protestant men were regulated for domestic violence. All history relating to the regulation of firearms is relevant and we -- and must be addressed under the Bruen methodology.

Justice Jackson also said earlier, “I’m trying to understand if there’s a flaw in the history and traditions kind of framework. To the extent that when we’re looking at history and tradition, we’re not considering the history and tradition of all people, but only some of the people, as per the government’s articulation of the test.” And, of course, that’s wrong because we’re looking at whoever the people were. We’re looking at how were they regulated.

But to the extent she’s saying, “Well, why isn’t the regulation of slaves relevant?” It can be relevant. In Bruen, it was very relevant because in Bruen, the left was trying to pretend that there was a nationwide ban on carriage, that every Founder—George Washington, John Adams, Thomas Jefferson, James Madison—that they were all habitual felons who were carrying in violation of this unseen prohibition on carriage. And there were lots of reasons that was wrong and a lie.

But one of the reasons was the slave laws because there were specific statutes banning slaves from carrying firearms. Why would you need that if everyone understood, as they claimed, that there was a ban on carriage for everyone? So those laws can be relevant, but Justice Jackson is simply wrong in terms of saying that somehow we’re going to ignore certain parts of history.

Now, her next question. Okay. “But let’s say I’m a legislator today in Maine, for example, and I’m very concerned about what has happened in that community. And my people, the constituents, are asking me to do something. Do you read Bruen as step one being going to the archives and having to determine whether or not there’s some sort of historical analog for the kinds of legislation I’m considering?”

Answer, you don’t have to do that. You could simply honor the text. That would be fine if you’re a legislator in Maine. You don’t have to go to the archives at all. Now, it might be too hard for someone to have to actually go read the text. I suppose maybe that would be the rejoinder, but I don’t think that’s very persuasive.

In any event, the point is, yes. If you’re going to try to chip away and erode and denigrate the text of the United States Constitution, yes, you have to do the work of googling and looking to see what is the scholarship available with respect to proper historical analogues. She asks, “What’s the justification for this?” The text. That’s the justification for this limitation on the legislatures.

Now, we turn to Justice Sotomayor. She said, “Just to be clear, none of the situations that Justice Alito is pointing to are the facts of this case, are they?” Oh, that’s a “gotcha.” [Laughter] General Prelogar, “No, they’re hypotheticals.” And Justice Sotomayor or -- and they’re not the facts of this statute. I didn’t know that statutes had facts, so I can’t really answer that question. Okay.

Now, so let’s step back for a moment and just sort of take cognizance of where we are in all of this. I mean, any just society will have a mechanism to disarm dangerous people, and it will have a system to disarm those who have misbehaved in the past. And the Founders had that. It was the affray system. And it will have the ability to disarm those who have been found to, on an individualized judicial determination, to be a threat. And that’s a preventative justice system that the surety system had.

And the bottom line is that the Founders created a just society. It was a society that honored the right to self-defense, but it was also a system that had the means to ensure that those who are truly dangerous, as evidenced by an individualized judicial finding of dangerousness, could be disarmed.

Now, the old adage is that bad facts make bad law, and we’re going to find out pretty soon about that. The Court is likely, I believe, to rule against Rahimi, and I hope, if they do so, they will point out that he did not raise any Due Process objections. He did not raise any Commerce Clause objections. He did not raise a challenge to (c)(2), the part of the statute that doesn’t require a finding of dangerousness. And he didn’t even contest the findings that were embedded in the protective order against him about his prior crime spree. So I think those would all be limiting principles for the decision that we’re likely to say.

Let me just say the stakes are really high here. The Second Amendment is the area of constitutional law that is the most free of debris and clutter of bad precedents that we have. And so if we can’t make originalism work in the Second Amendment, it’s a very bad harbinger for those who want to see originalism restored to the entire Constitution. The good news is that the Supreme Court has articulated a highly functional, highly rational, highly efficacious test with Bruen, and I’m confident that they’re going to stick to it and not throw it in the trash. Thank you.

[Applause]

Prof. Mark W. Smith:  Thank you for that introduction, Judge VanDyke, and always a pleasure to be in attendance with David Thompson of the law firm Cooper & Kirk—one of the premier Second Amendment law firms in America.

Before I begin, I just want to give a moment of honor in light of the fact that today’s Veterans Day, so I want to honor all veterans, including my late parents, both of whom were veterans of World War II. I also want to give a moment of honor, of course, to those that participated in the militia going back to the founding of our country, the Battles of Kings Mountain, the Battle of Bennington, the Battle of Saratoga, of course, the Battle of the Green at Lexington and Concord.

And given the topic is today, “The Second Amendment,” I wanted to, of course, remind everyone that when the British left Boston to march on Lexington and Concord, they were not there to enforce the taxes. They were there to steal the Patriots’ guns. So we must always keep that in mind with that history when we talk about the Second Amendment and where it comes from.

The other thing is, when I found out from The Federalist Society that Judge VanDyke was going to be the moderator, I was actually greatly concerned because, as you know, Judge VanDyke is a judge on the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals. And that concerns me to this very moment because I’m concerned that everything I’m about to say here is going to be en banced and reversed by Judge VanDyke’s colleagues. [Laughter] But I’m hopeful, if that happens, Judge VanDyke will write a powerful dissent.

[Applause]

Prof. Mark W. Smith:  Okay. So since Bruen was decided in June of 2022, we have seen a huge amount of Second Amendment litigation. Arguably, this is the most fruitful and busy area of constitutional law in America today. And with all due respect to the many federal judges in this audience and Judge VanDyke, unfortunately, the inferior courts, as we understand them, under Article III of the U.S. Constitution throughout this country—many of whom, unfortunately, have not gotten the Heller/Bruen methodology correct—and I want to talk about some of those errors and how to correct them in my speech today.

And just as a reminder, there’s two sets of litigations going on. Some of the challenges involving the Second Amendment are to laws that were on the books before the Bruen decision in June of 2022, and they are being challenged. And then you have a whole spate of other types of litigations that arose from the hissy fits thrown by blue states controlled by the Democrats that just basically said, “We want to thumb our nose at the U.S. Supreme Court and the Second Amendment, and we’re going to engage in a type of massive resistance to our civil rights, to our constitutional rights, that we haven’t seen since the 1950s, which certain states decide to fight the effort of civil rights workers to desegregate the South.”

That is what we are seeing in the Second Amendment context in some of these blue states. And there is a lot of litigation arising from those laws that have been passed in a rush, trying to just punish gun owners for exercising their constitutional rights and again, engage in massive resistance to this Supreme Court.

So I want to do two things today. I want to identify many of the major mistakes, many of what I would also like to call the “feigned mistakes” or the “feigned confusion” that we’re seeing in the lower courts, and then I want to explain the proper way to address some of these issues.

So the key is, of course, you have to understand when you approach the Second Amendment as a subject matter, that, like it was once taught that Gaul is divided into three parts, the Second Amendment today is divided into two parts. The first part—or the first bucket, if you will—are arms ban cases. The second bucket—or the second part, if you will—are non-arms ban cases.

Now, this distinction I’m making is not trivial in any respect. It is extremely important that people interested in the fundamental right to keep and bear arms get this distinction correct because if you fail to draw this distinction in the context of arms ban cases, you will be led down a very bad, a very expensive, a very time consuming, and a totally unnecessary rabbit hole. This is because you will allow the anti-gun lobby in this country to essentially relitigate the historical analog portion of the Heller/Bruen test of text first, burden shifts to the government, and then government has to do the history.

Now, instead, when you’re dealing with arms ban cases, you simply have to apply the legal principle set forth in Heller, and that’s the key. Now, before we get to that test and how you apply it, which is really very simple, we have to understand and debunk one myth. That myth that you see in the press—and I spent a lot of time in and around the media—is that the Bruen decision in 2022 was groundbreaking.

The Bruen decision in 2022 was not groundbreaking at all. It was simply a reiteration and a reaffirmation of the Supreme Court’s 2008 originalist decision in the District of Columbia v. Heller. That’s all it was. In fact, to prove the point, let us quote the U.S. Supreme Court and Justice Thomas himself in Bruen. “The test that we set forth in Heller and apply today” -- I repeat.

Bruen said, “The test that we set forth in Heller and apply today requires courts to assess whether modern firearms regulations are consistent with the Second Amendment’s text and historical understanding.” So the Supreme Court itself in Bruen is literally telling us, “We are simply applying in Bruen Heller.” So there’s nothing groundbreaking about Bruen.

But then you might ask, “Well, what was Bruen all about? Why did they spend all of this time going into all of these issues?” Well, there’s a couple of reasons for why they did this. And again, a lot of it speaks to the “mistakes,” if you will, that occurred between the year of our Lord 2008, which is Heller, and 2022, which is Bruen.

So the first thing that Bruen did was to fix mistakes. And the major mistake that Bruen did after it points out they’re applying just a Heller methodology of text first, burden shifting to the government, historical analog analysis, is they wanted to fix once and for all—which never needed to be fixed because Heller was pretty clear on this—but they wanted to fix once and for all there would be no more interest balancing tests, no more tiers of scrutiny, no more strict scrutiny, none of those barnacles that are stuck upon our jurisprudence involving things like the First Amendment.

So they made clear no more interest balancing. And again, this was entirely unnecessary and only brought about in Bruen because of the “inferior courts”—not all of them, of course, but some of them getting that totally wrong. For any doubt about this, one only needs to look at the language that Justice Scalia used in Heller on this question of interest balancing.

This is what Heller said in 2008. “We know of no other enumerated constitutional right whose core protection has been subjected to a freestanding interest-balancing approach. The very enumeration of the right takes out of the hands of government—including the third branch of government, the courts—the power to decide on a case-by-case basis whether the right is really worth insisting upon a constitutional guarantee subject to future judges’ assessments of its usefulness is no constitutional guarantee at all.” That powerful language was not in 2022 in Bruen. It was in 2008 in Heller. So, clearly, as we stand here today, Heller remains good law and should be followed, in particular, in the case and the types of cases that Heller decided, which are arms ban cases.

Now that we clearly understand that Heller is the binding, definitive law—which a lot of people want to pretend it’s not, and you’ll see why in a second—we have to say, what did Heller decide and why do we care today? Well, we know what Heller decided because in Heller, the Court was asked to whether or not the handgun ban of the District of Columbia was constitutional under the Second Amendment. And just as a strong originalist court should do in trying to search for the original public meaning of the constitutional provision, it started with the best historical evidence of them all as to what something means.

It’s called the text of the Constitution itself. Mind you, remember, when we talk about history, the Constitution itself is history, and probably the dispositive history on many issues. And the text speaks for itself. Never lose sight of that because, of course, the anti-gun community, as I see it, doesn’t like the text of the Second Amendment for obvious reasons.

So with that said, we turn to what Heller said about arms bans. It starts quite simply by defining its terms. And the key term in Heller was, “What do arms mean?” And they very simply said—quoting English lexicographers like Samuel Johnson and the like—simply said that arms can be anything that can be used offensively or defensively. And then it went on to confirm by looking at history, to say, “Yeah, that all makes sense.” It looked at history going back from England all the way to the post-Civil War era and said, “Are there any historical analog laws?”

Now that we know the text says that an arm is anything that can be used offensively or defensively, are there any historical analog laws at the time of the Founding or otherwise that could give rise to justifying the D.C. handgun ban?

Well, the only thing they uncovered was a law that says there is a “historical tradition of prohibiting the carrying of dangerous and conjunctive, dangerous and unusual weapons.” And in light of this history, they did the historical work. There’s a historical basis for saying you can ban the carrying of dangerous and unusual weapons. And in light of that, the Court said, “Well, in light of this, this means, by definition, that if an arm is in common use by Americans for lawful purposes today, it cannot be banned because under the historical tradition, only dangerous and unusual weapons can be banned.” If a weapon is in common use by Americans, it obviously cannot be unusual. And because it cannot be unusual, it cannot possibly meet the historical judicial standard of firearms regulation known as “dangerous and unusual.”

So that was the legal principle, the legal test set forth that if you’re dealing with an arms ban case—because DC was an arms ban case, in the form of a handgun bans case—you apply the historical standard of dangerous and unusual. And, of course, everything we’re talking about in today’s court system are obviously in common use: AR-15s, magazines that hold more than 10 rounds, suppressors, and the like, there’s millions of these things. They cannot be banned.

And mind you, one other thing. As to who gets to decide what are the weapons that are protected under the Second Amendments—the right of the people to keep and bear arms shall not be infringed—the Supreme Court answered that question as well. And the answer is, “We, the people, get to decide what arms are protected.” You don’t have to take my word for it. Why don’t we turn to the Supreme Court again in Heller?

The Supreme Court, in pointing out that the handgun ban was unconstitutional, wrote the following: “Whatever the reason, whatever the reason, whatever the reason, handguns are the most popular weapon chosen by Americans for self-defense in the home, and a complete prohibition on their use is invalid.” It doesn’t matter what the reason is. We, the people, choose. And if it’s in common use and we have these guns, they’re protected.

Now, I also want to make a note that guess who else agrees with me? You may find this hard to believe, but the solicitor general under Joe Biden’s administration agrees with Mark Smith. I don’t often say that, but I will today, and I will then prove it with a statement that the solicitor general made at the Rahimi oral argument this week.

She says that, “Once you have the principle locked in, then I do not think it’s necessary to effectively repeat that same historical—that same historical—analogical analysis for the purposes of determining whether or not a modern day legislature’s disarmament provision fits within the category.” The point is that even the solicitor general when talking about the history—remember there’s the text first, then you shift to the burden to the government to do the history. The burden is on the government to do the history—when they’re doing the history, even the solicitor general of Joe Biden says, “Once the history has been done by a Court and the Supreme Court has done the history and has come up with the legal test or the legal principle that arises or derives from that historical spade work, that’s it. That is the test you apply.” And that concept applies 150 percent to the fact that Heller came up with the legal test or the legal principle to apply in all arms ban cases in the United States.

But now let us ask, in light of this. What have the lower courts done with this very basic analysis that a first-year lawsuit could nail in an exam in December of its first semester? Well, unfortunately, the lower courts seem to make this more complicated than it needs to be. One wonders why that’s happening in some of these courts. Well, the first things we’re starting to see, of course, and occurs, these cases usually involve two things. We’ll talk mostly about two things: AR-15s, which are nothing more than semi-automatic rifles, right?

So let’s just step back for a moment. In Heller, they said modern firearms are protected. Modern firearms consist, at least in the handgun context of Heller, revolvers and semi-automatic pistols that are responsible for maybe -- I don’t know what the number is, but something like -- let’s say, 10,000 deaths here in the United States or whatever associated with homicides.

In contrast, we’re now litigating over semi-automatic rifles, which are the exact same firearm as semi-automatic pistols protected by Bruen -- by Heller, except they’re rifles, and they’re only responsible for 300 deaths a year of all long guns. Now, I’m not saying that that’s a good thing or anything, but the point is, it would seem to me that the long guns, semi-automatic rifle case is much easier. But for some reason, these blue state courts don’t seem to agree.

So let us go through the mistakes that the lower courts are making with respect to this. The first thing is they are pretending that Heller is not the law, and they’re using this opportunity to relitigate, again, these gun ban cases from scratch. And again, rather than applying the in-common use test, they come up with new tests because once you pretend that Heller is no longer good law—and this is why I’m dwelling on this here—once you are in an arms ban litigation today in America and you don’t apply Heller because you pretend it’s not binding on you as an inferior court judge, you then have free will and free hand to make stuff up.

And that is why we are seeing these gun bans of AR-15s and semi-automatic rifles getting banned under such new legal tests invented by certain lower courts—and these are some of the legal tests that come up—that you can ban these arms because they are “exceptionally dangerous, they are particularly dangerous, or they are assault weapons'' and so on and so on. Again, these are all effectively a form of interest balancing test that you’re not allowed to use as per Heller and, of course, Bruen. But that’s exactly what’s going on.

But the good news is some courts do get this right. In a footnote this week in the Fifth Circuit Court of Appeals VanDerStok case, they laid it out beautifully a few days ago. This is what the Fifth Circuit wrote. “The Supreme Court has held that to be banned, a weapon must be both dangerous and unusual, and thus, the relative dangerousness of a weapon is irrelevant when the weapon belongs to a class of arms commonly used for lawful purposes”—citing to the Justice Alito dissent in Caetano. And, of course, the Fifth Circuit went on to say, “Of course, for many years now, millions of AR-15 rifles have been sold to civilians who may lawfully possess them.”

Now, I should also note that this is, I think, where the biggest game gets played, and you have to be extremely careful with what I’m about to say. And it’s very easy to defeat if you know what’s coming because I’ve seen in many briefs involving gun control cases a sentence from Bruen gets cut in half, and you’ll see why it gets cut in half in one second.

Specifically, what we’re seeing is a lot of the lower courts are using a phrase or an argument that says, “Unprecedented societal and technological change allows them as an excuse to make things up and get around Heller and get around Bruen and again, invent new legal tests that all of which conveniently seem to uphold gun bans.”

Specifically, the language that they are using from Bruen is this:  “While the historical analogies here and in Heller are relatively simple to draw other cases—other cases—implicating unprecedented societal concerns or dramatic technological changes may require a more nuanced approach.” You see there? The sentence starts off with talking about Heller, and then it talks about other cases implicating “unprecedented societal concerns or dramatic technological changes.”

So, of course, what happens is that a lot of these lower courts conveniently cut off the opening clause of that sentence from Bruen and simply mouth the words, “Hey. If we have unprecedented societal concerns or unprecedented or dramatic technological change, we get to make it up as we go along. We get to ignore Heller and simply say, “Oh. Well, these are dangerous. I don’t like them. You lose.”

No, that’s not how it works because it turns out that the language of that sentence itself prevents that because, again, it starts off that while historical analog analogies here and in Heller are relatively simple to draw other cases. So this sentence is talking about other cases, other cases from Heller, which is the arms ban case that sets forth the legal test to govern arms ban cases. Nevertheless, that is a game that we see played over and over and over again.

And mind you, just to be extra clear, that any suggestion that either an AR-15 semiautomatic rifle or mass shootings would be considered to be either an unprecedented societal concern or a dramatic technological change is not just defeated by the fact that the first clause of that sentence says, “Heller controls,” okay? It’s also defeated by the text, of course.

But moreover, Heller came out in the year of our Lord 2008. What happened in the year of our Lord 2007? 2007, we saw one of the worst mass shootings in American history at Virginia Tech, where a student using semiautomatic handguns and magazines that held more than 10 rounds, killed something like 30 people, unfortunately, at Virginia Tech in 2007. In 2008, this point was made in amicus briefs to the U.S. Supreme Court in the Heller case itself.

So the Supreme Court was aware of semi-automatic firearms; they were aware of magazines that held more than 10 rounds; and they were aware of mass shootings in 2007 when they decided the Heller case in 2008. Moreover, because the dangerous and unusual test gives rise to sort of the back end, the in common use test—which, as you know, applies to the modern world. We’re not limited to muskets, as the Supreme Court has repeatedly said—the in common use test by Americans for lawful purposes implicitly within its test articulated by the Supreme Court in Heller implicates and encompasses any such social change, societal change, or technology that exists today because the question is, “What do we, the people, decide we need today?” And any societal changes involving arms bans or any technological changes involving arms bans, again, is encompassed in that test.

And mind you, don’t forget. We had mass shootings at the time of the Founding. I won’t list all of them, but the simplest one, of course, is the Boston Massacre in 1770, where 8 Americans were killed by British soldiers, and they were tried with John Adams successfully defending by and large the officers there. So mass shootings existed before even the Constitution.

So the next error we see by the lower courts involving these arms ban cases, of course, they try to argue because once you get away from the Heller and common use test, you get to make it up. And next thing you know, you see some of these courts embracing arguments made by the anti-gun lobby to say things like, “Oh. Well, these AR-15 semiautomatic rifles, magazines that hold more than 10 rounds, these are not commonly used for self-defense.” See that little sleight of hand?

So we go from Heller that says, “In common use by Americans for lawful purposes” as a legal test. And by the way, the solicitor general made this exact point in Rahimi. She said, “Oh. Well, weapons that are in common use by Americans and used for self-defense, commonly used for self-defense,” this is where they’re trying to make that shift. And again, this is why it’s so important to understand that the Heller test is the law because there is an attempt to rewrite Heller and make stuff up to get around that binding precedent.

And again, one of the popular ones we see over and over and over again—including by this Department of Justice—is, again, “If an arm is not shown to be commonly used for self-defense, it cannot be protected.” Now, of course, there are many reasons why this is a mistake.

The first is that mere possession, mere possession of a handgun is using the gun. That gun on your nightstand when you go to bed that just sits there is in use for self-defense when you sleep. That gun in the holster of a police officer is in use just when it sits in the holster. If it’s never pulled out and fired, it’s still being used, no different than a health insurance policy is being used even if you’re not going to the doctor or a fire extinguisher is being used in the building—in this building itself, I’m sure—even though it’s not being sprayed at anything.

So the mere possession of a firearm in and of itself is a use, and thus, the mere possession satisfies in common use. You don’t have to do what the anti-gunners like to say, which is, “You got to show that it’s commonly used for self-defense. We need to see that people use AR-15s every day to pull the trigger and defend themselves,” which, of course, does happen. We know that does happen.

The next point, of course, that I want to mention here is—and this is important—that the Heller case was decided on a motion to dismiss, a motion to dismiss. The Supreme Court gave rise to the Heller case -- the Heller decision. Now, this is important because the Heller decision arose without the benefit of testimony, without the benefit of experts, without the benefit of a trial, and without the evidence being presented of how many times guns are used in self-defense or any of these things because none of it mattered. None of it mattered.

So the point being that for lower courts to pretend that Heller is not the binding law and to look for ways to redo the Heller debate by redoing the history and redoing the historical analog analysis in arms ban cases is totally unacceptable. And this is a huge deal because we see this all across the country in magazine cases and semiautomatic ban cases all across the country where they’re simply not applying Heller.

And once you apply Heller, of course there is no way that the anti-gun lobby can win because there are millions and millions of magazines, hundreds of millions of magazines, and tens of millions of AR-15s. And they can’t possibly show that these things are not in common use.

And one other thing. Because the in-common-use, dangerous, and unusual standard arises from the history part—the history part of the analysis—guess what? Where does the burden lie with the government? So it’s not that the Second Amendment community has to prove that an arm or a magazine is in common use. In fact, it’s the opposite.

Because this is part of the history portion of the text first, burden shifts to the government to do the history. Because it’s part of the historical analysis part of the text and history methodology of interpreting the Second Amendment, the burden is actually on the government to demonstrate that an arm that they’ve banned is dangerous and unusual. And to do that, they have to prove -- the government has to prove that these arms are not in common use, which is simply impossible because they’ve all gone on the record a thousand times that we have too many AR-15s and too many magazines in the country.

They can’t possibly even argue it, and they don’t. And that’s why it’s all about them trying to redefine the legal test, the legal standard that was set forth by the Supreme Court in Heller, which remains good law.

So I now want to turn just briefly to magazines because there’s some confusion about magazines specifically. Magazines, as you know, is the device—and sometimes they’re fixed, and sometimes they’re not fixed—that are inserted into a firearm that allow a firearm to be shot multiple times without having to manually reload it. We see magazine bans of magazines that hold more than 10 rounds all across the country.

There’s one simple reason why these things are clearly unconstitutional. Step back for a moment and ask yourself, “What have you effectively done if you ban magazines that hold more than 10 rounds of ammunition?” What you have done is you have banned an entire category, an entire class of firearms specifically, just like in D.C. in Heller, where they banned the entire class of firearms known as handguns.

If you ban magazines that hold more than 10 rounds of ammunition, you have banned an entire class of firearms, i.e., firearms that are capable of firing more than 10 rounds without having to be manually reloaded. That entire category of firearms has been taken off the table and effectively banned.

So when you hear the words, “It’s just a magazine ban,” your first instinct should always be, “No, this is an actual firearm ban of firearms that can hold and fire more than 10 rounds without having to manually reload.” It is a firearms ban. But even going beyond that, of course, if you want to take it at a second level, magazines are essential components, integral components of modern day firearms of all semi-automatic firearms, including handguns that are protected arms specifically under the Heller precedent. So even if you wanted to go down that path, of course, they would be protected.

And last but not least, in terms of magazines, there’s really only one argument historically or one possible historical analog that one could justify banning magazines. And you don’t need to do this, remember, because Heller always gives you the legal test. So what I’m about to say is unnecessary, but you could just throw it in there because it’s often argued by those that support gun control, and that is, they quote the eighteenth century examples of black powder storage regulations.

And they say, “Oh. Well, at the time of the Founding, there were regulations that prevented the storing in cities or in homes of large quantities of black powder. And therefore, that’s part of ammunition. Therefore, that’s effectively a limitation on ammunition in a sense.” But no, that’s not true because, as David Thompson articulately explained, the “how” and the “why” of a historical analog is not satisfied there because why did you have black powder regulation involving the storage of large quantities of black powder in the eighteenth century?

And the answer is because entire cities like Boston and Philadelphia were made out of wood. And if this highly flammable black powder—which, by the way, is still regulated today as a highly flammable substance—if this black powder, heaven forbid, ever caught fire, it literally would burn down entire cities. And that is not something that’s impossible to imagine for our Founding Fathers because in the year 1666, the entire city of London burned down because of a fire.

So when they talk about in these gun control cases, “The storage of black powder is an example of gun control,” no. It was a fire regulation. And under the Bruen test of how and why of regulations have to be met, the “why” of the regulation in that case was fire prevention, fire control, and not gun control or crime control. So the “why” cannot be used to satisfy magazine capacity limitations.

Now, I want to turn briefly and talk about non-arms ban cases. All of what I’ve just talked about were really arms ban cases. And I spent time on it because it’s very important because, again, this is where we see the greatest amount of feigned confusion by pretending that the law that’s binding on these lower courts does not exist.

So, to begin with, I want to talk briefly about the textual analysis of the Second Amendment, and then I’ll go back and talk about some of the historical analysis. It is important to understand when you’re looking at Second Amendment cases that, at the textual level, you have the text, which is, “The right of the people to keep and bear arms shall not be infringed.” But you also have ancillary rights in the Second Amendment in the same way that you have ancillary or implied rights in other aspects of the Bill of Rights.

So, to give you an example, if you look at how two eighteenth century/early nineteenth century lexicographers defined the word “infringed,” as we know, the right of the people to keep and bear arms shall not be infringed. So let’s take a look briefly at the definition of the word “infringed” in the eighteenth century.

Well, Noah Webster and Samuel Johnson both said that “to infringe is to hinder or destroy”—hinder or destroy. And I think there’s three things that pop up that clearly are examples of modern day gun control laws that hinder and/or destroy the right to keep and bear arms. First -- but they’re implied in the context of the Second Amendment.

One is the right to train with guns. You can’t use guns effectively if you don’t train with them. So anything involving restrictions on, let’s say, gun ranges or the ability to train, I think, is an infringement. You also have several cases dealing with the right to buy guns. For example, in the Fifth Circuit right now, you have a case called Reese v. ATF as to whether or not 18 to 20 year olds are allowed to acquire guns. We’ll talk about that in one second.

But in terms of the right to buy guns, obviously, the right to keep in arms presupposes that we acquire guns in some way. And, of course, two of the obvious ways one can acquire guns is one can go out and buy guns, right? And there’s restrictions on that. And then, of course, you can go out and make guns. And go out and make guns is a historical tradition in the United States. But also, keep in mind, this speaks to the “ghost gun issue,” which is really just a ban on do-it-yourself gun kits and the like to prevent Americans from being able to make their own guns. Again, these are examples of what I call ancillary rights that speak to this.

Now, there’s two examples of other -- I just want to mention how you see ancillary rights. First, in the First Amendment, we have other ancillary rights, like the right to expressive association, the right to gather news, and the right to attend criminal trials. These are not expressly in the text, but they are still there—likewise, the Sixth Amendment. You have a right to pay for your lawyer, even though it doesn’t specifically say that.

So now, let’s just talk briefly about history, and then I’ll wrap up. The most important thing I want to talk about the history is that the relevant time period is 1791. The Second Amendment was adopted in 1791 with the rest of the Bill of Rights. So 1791 is the key year. The Supreme Court has repeatedly said that whether you apply the Bill of Rights to the states or to the federal government, it is to be interpreted the same. And because it’s to be interpreted the same, you look to 1791 because that was when it was created.

And the purpose of the Fourteenth Amendment in 1868 was to take the 1791 understanding of the Second Amendment and to apply it to a new group of protectives, if you will, people protected by it, i.e., the freed African American slaves. And it applied to a new group of government, i.e., states and localities. But it was the same 1791 understanding.

And to prove the point, one need only look at the 2020 decision by the U.S. Supreme Court in Espinoza v. Montana, where an opinion by Chief Justice John Roberts dealing with public funding to religious schools, he talks about the role of nineteenth century historical precedent when he points out that in the late nineteenth century, there were 30 states.

Thirty states had adopted really what were called no-aid provisions, meaning you could not spend public money on religious institutions. This was motivated mostly by anti-Catholic bigotry. In this context, Justice Roberts got it right. He says that, “I don’t care that 30 states adopted something that violates the 1791 First Amendment because that’s too late in time.”

And then when he was criticized by Justice Sotomayor for having a double standard, he came back and says, “No, you don’t understand. Late nineteenth century evidence can be used to confirm the 1791 understanding, but late nineteenth century evidence cannot be used to contradict the 1791 understanding.” And there’s no more powerful evidence of this than the 30 statewide laws that the Supreme Court rejected in the Espinoza case. So again, I think it’s 1791.

So anyway, I’m available for questions, obviously, and I will just sum up this way. I’ve spent a lot of time this morning talking about the lower courts, but I want to say something about the Supreme Court.

If you look at the statistics of the number of cases taken by the U.S. Supreme Court going back several decades, guess what? There were periods in time where there were over 300 cases taken. I understand there were certain rule changes. But even in more recent times, we’ve seen cases -- case dockets of the U.S. Supreme Court of upwards of 150 and so on.

And now, we’re seeing a trend towards 60, 70 cases a term. And I would, in addition to encouraging lower courts to get a right on the Second Amendment, I would also encourage the U.S. Supreme Court to take more Second Amendment cases to clear up some of this feigned confusion we’re seeing in the inferior courts.

And I hope that the start with Rahimi and hopefully the range case and more, I hope that’s a trend we will see more of, and I hope it will be favorable, and I think it will. But I think the Supreme Court itself should be doing more work in the Second Amendment area. It is not unusual to see the Supreme Court take multiple Fourth Amendment cases or First Amendment cases in a term. Why not multiple Second Amendment cases in a term as well? Thank you.

[Applause]

Hon. Lawrence VanDyke:  Thank you, Mark, and thank you, David. So I’m going to go ahead. I want to make sure we have enough time for questions. I want to ask a question that I guess is sort of a little bit of a technical question. What you see, especially if you listen to the oral argument of Rahimi is you see -- the government’s argument seems to be, “Let’s look at the history from the history. Let’s extract the principle.” The principle in the Rahimi case they’re saying is dangerousness responsibility.

And then what they’re saying is they take that principle, and they say, “We don’t need to have” -- really, what they’re saying is, “We don’t need to have a very direct analogy. We just need to have -- take that principle of dangerousness, say is what the state or the federal government is doing trying to protect against people being dangerous. And then there you have it. You’ve got your analogy.”

And the problem with that, obviously, is that that’s a very flexible standard and seems to be somewhat inconsistent with what at least people thought Bruen meant when it first came out because everybody knows pretty quickly after law school that if you can extract a principle, depending on how generalized the principle is, if the principle is just how -- we want to make the world a better place, and that’s what this law is trying to do, and that’s what the Founders are trying to do. And so there’s a match.

On the other hand, I mean, there is the language in Bruen that it doesn’t have to be an exact match and such. So what can we do to try to constrain courts to where they are getting the match at the right level of generality, I guess, is the question I’ve got.

Prof. David H. Thompson:  Yeah. So I think that is one of the problems that it’s the lack of -- that it’s at too high a level of generality, number one. But number two, it’s sort of jettisoning the whole -- the how part. It’s focusing just on the why, the purpose. Dangerous people, we don’t want them to have firearms, but the anti-gun community just wants to blind itself to how. And that is one of the two parts of the Bruen test. And it’s really important.

We can see in the analogues that they point to in Rahimi. They’re really falling short on the “how” because an affray was a criminal violation, and you got the full panoply of protections from criminal law before you were disarmed. And likewise with a surety, it was a very different system where members of the community could come forward and vouch for you. And so they’re just sort of throwing that away and skipping over and trying to impermissibly sweep in more analogues. But Mark, do you have a --

Hon. Lawrence VanDyke:  Yeah, okay. Well, it looks like we have a bunch of folks lined up, so I think I’m just going to go ahead and we have about 15, 20 minutes left, so I’m going to go ahead and start taking questions if that’s all right with my panelists. I’ll come up here. So I will remind you, in The Federalist Society National Convention tradition, you should not ask a question. You should just state your views, and then put a question mark at the end of it.

[Laughter]

Hon. Lawrence VanDyke:  No, I think it’s the other way around. They’re here to state their views. You’re here to ask a question. And I will endeavor to ask questions at both microphones because I’ve seen that be missed a few times. But I’ll start here in the front. Try to keep it a little bit short since we’re short on time.

Questioner 1:  Sure. Thank you so much. Brilliant panel. I have a question about the barnacle. So, Judge, you touched on the analogy issue.

Hon. Lawrence VanDyke:  Can you get a little bit closer to the microphone?

Questioner 1:  Oh, sorry. Sorry, Judge, you touched on the analogy issue. But as much as I think strict scrutiny and the tears aren’t popular here, isn’t there an issue where at least we could have some concept, in addition to everything we have with Bruen and Heller, an issue of tailoring because many of these laws, they just don’t even make any sense at all, and they have never managed to produce any logical or statistical basis that gun control makes people safer or it stops mass shootings?

The vast majority of mass shootings happen in gun-free zones, as we know, for obvious reasons. Will there be any clarification or slight modification to add another level where they also have to at least meet some kind of rationality test in addition to just, I’m concerned, just playing the analogy game and stretching it as much as they can?

Prof. David H. Thompson:  No, it’s really a test that trusts the Founders, that if they had a system that they put in place—even if we might think today, “Well, it’s not really that well-tailored”—then that doesn’t matter. Tailoring is gone. For whatever reasons, the Founders had a surety system. It was okay then, and it’s okay now. So I don’t think we’re going to see a resuscitation of the tailoring concept.

For those of you who haven’t read this law review article by my colleagues John Ohlendorf and Joel Alicea, it is a fantastic takedown of the tears of scrutiny. Mark was quoting Chief Justice Roberts from the Heller decision, calling them a barnacle. They’re a lot worse than a barnacle.

It is a judge-empowering test to chip away and erode the protections and the rights that the Founders gave us. And then for judges to say, “Yeah. Well, we know it says, ‘Congress shall pass no law abridging the freedom of speech,’ but we think this is really important. So we’re going to say you can’t, oh, for example, say the name of a candidate in the 60 days before general election,” which was the issue in the McCain-Feingold case, okay? So it’s very pernicious, and I think the conservatives have driven a stake through tears of scrutiny in the Second Amendment, and we’re not going to see it come back.

Hon. Lawrence VanDyke:  Yeah. Let me ask a follow-up to that real quick because it’s true. Tailoring is supposed to be off the table because interest balancing is supposed to be off the table. But if you listen to the Rahimi argument and if the idea is that you’re extracting some principle and then you’re deciding whether or not the legislature is essentially just trying to effectuate the same principle—and, of course, you have the -- I don’t know how you --

How would you get away from some sort of fit concept because if the idea is dangerousness but the legislature says, “Well, this group of people is dangerous, but only some set of that -- some subset of that group is dangerous,” I mean, how would you get away from having some sort of tailoring analysis sneaking back in at that level if that’s what you’re going to do? That’s one of the questions.

Prof. David H. Thompson:  Well, you do have to look and see whether it’s distinctly similar. And so, in that level, yes, okay? You’re making a comparison, which I guess with tailoring, you’re making a comparison of, “Does this sweep too broadly?” And likewise, when you’re looking at whether something meets the “how” part of the test, you have to see, “Is it distinctly similar?”

So you’re making a comparison, but I think it really does cabin the discretion of judges not to allow them to say, “Well, this is really important.” So even though it says, “The right of the people to keep and bear arms shall not be infringed,” we think there’s a real -- a problem with X, Y, or Z, so we’re going to clamp down on that.

Hon. Lawrence VanDyke:  So you’re not just focused on the problem that they’re trying to address but how is it that they tried to address that problem?

Prof. David H. Thompson:  Yeah, that’s right.

Hon. Lawrence VanDyke:  All right. I’ll go to the back, back there.

Cam Atkinson:  Cam Atkinson from Connecticut. Attorney Thompson said that -- if I recollect correctly earlier, he said, “Bad facts make bad law.” And my question regarding Rahimi is, obviously, there’s bad facts there.

But do you see Rahimi as being -- going to be reflective of a larger trend when the Supreme Court is confronted with scary facts—for instance, the Nigrelli case out of New York arguing for guns in private schools? The argument could be made under the Bruen methodology that pistol permits themselves have no historical support. Do you see Rahimi as turning into something broader of a pushback on scary facts just not bad facts?

Prof. David H. Thompson:  No, I think it was a savvy strategic maneuver by Merrick Garland. Here, he’s got this terrible set of facts, and so he rushes it to the Supreme Court in the hopes that the bad facts will make bad case law. I was heartened by the fact that the justices really seemed to be looking at and disregarding the various ways in which the solicitor general was trying to really weaken the Bruen methodology.

And so I don’t think it’s actually going to be that bad a decision. I think it’ll be a narrow decision that focuses on the fact that Rahimi basically agreed that he was a dangerous person. He signed on to the protective order saying that he had done all these terrible things, and that would have been enough at the time of the Founding.

Hon. Lawrence VanDyke:  All right, we’ll come to the front here.

Paul Kraus:  Thank you, Paul Kraus from Oakland. Could the panel comment on place-based or situation-based restrictions, such as what has been happening recently in New Mexico?

Prof. David. M. Thompson:  Yes. So this is another very important -- maybe the arm bans are super important. But another super important fight that’s going on is, “Where can you carry?” And the Court in Bruen acknowledged that there were sensitive places at the time of the Founding, and those included courthouses; those included polling places; and it included schools. I’ll get to schools in a second.

      And so the left is trying to say, “Well, look. We’ve got all these places that are very sensitive.” And, first of all, we know that’s not true because they were never sensitive until Bruen came along, and then they magically became sensitive after the fact, number one.

Number two, if we properly apply Bruen, we look at something like the courthouses. And at the time of the Founding, courthouses had comprehensive security. By that, I mean every entry point had an armed guard, a bailiff, a sergeant at arms. And so your need for self-defense was reduced going back to the purpose of the Second or one of the purposes of the Second Amendment, the need for self-defense.

And so that’s why at a courthouse at the time of the Founding, there were bans on carriage. Likewise, in schools were not gun-free zones at the time of the Founding. It’s true that starting in 1655, Harvard said that students couldn’t carry guns, and Yale and others followed suit shortly thereafter. But that was students. Teachers were always permitted to carry firearms. And the rationale had nothing to do with comprehensive security. There wasn’t. It was that the schools were acting in loco parentis for the students. And so they therefore had the authority to tell them what they could carry and what they couldn’t.

And so those sensitive places, if you take those principles, the principle of comprehensive security and you bring it to the twenty-first century, look at a place like TSA. There’s comprehensive security. So they can say, “You can’t carry a firearm beyond the security checkpoint” because they are providing the defense to keep people safe. So that’s going to be a big fight, and it’s something that’s playing out, and it’ll probably hit the Supreme Court next term, maybe the term after that.

Prof. Mark W. Smith:  I want to add one thing to that, which is, as we know from Supreme Court precedent, the government has no legal duty to protect you from criminals. The only exception to that is if you are in government custody. If they put you in the back of a patrol car or they put you in prison, they take over the obligation to protect you. But absent being in custody, the notion of “to serve and protect” is simply a model and not legally meaningful.

I mention this in the context of the sensitive and sensitive places as euphemism for government mandated gun-free zones. The way I see this issue and why I think comprehensive security makes sense is if the government is willing to put their money where their mouth and said, “We will protect you. We will spend the money on metal detectors. We will spend the money on armed guards to protect you and effectively take you under our wing and protect you, then you don’t need to have guns here because we’re going to step up and do it for you.”

But anything short of that, that doesn’t really shift the burden to the government to basically say, “We’re adopting you for this limited period of time while you’re in our custody”—in a sense—yeah. Then it’s all fake. So you sometimes hear these theories like, “Well, it involves core governmental functions.” That’s utterly unworkable. That’s absurd.

What is a core governmental function? You think the blue states manipulate the Second Amendment law now. Wait until you see when they start talking about that core governmental functions is protecting wetlands. It’s protecting the post office, right? It’s educating kids. There’s no end to what might be a core governmental function.

And that’s why the way to understand -- and if you look at the three examples cited in Bruen of sensitive places, their courthouse is protected by bailiffs; their legislative chambers is protected by historically sergeants at arm; and their polling places are protected by a combination of sheriffs and constables all during the Founding.

The one thing that makes that common, the one common thread there is comprehensive security, that the government is providing people with guns to protect the citizens there. And in that case, they’re taking over your armed protection. But absent that, you’re on your own. You are your own first responder, and if you want to have a gun to protect yourself and your family under the Second Amendment, you’re entitled to it.

Prof. David H. Thompson:  And the other thing that’s common to those places is that you’re there for a finite period of time. They couldn’t say, “Well, this city where you live is now a gun-free zone because we’re going to have Chinese-style totalitarian security around the city.” That would not work. But if you’re going to court, it’s for a finite period of time. You’re flying on the plane, it’s a finite period of time. And so that’s another limiting principle.

Hon. Lawrence VanDyke:  Yeah, I think I would add to that.

Prof. David H. Thompson:  Oh, yes. This is a very -- I don’t want to let anyone cut the line, but it’s an important point, which is churches. And so at the time of the Founding, churches were sensitive in the sense of people knew they were a vulnerable spot because everyone went. And so there was nobody at home back then.

And so what did the Founders do? They required you to bring a gun to church, okay? And so even the state of New York, when we sued them and got a PI, sort of backed off and was like, “Okay.” So it’s now, I think, only Montgomery County is maybe the only place in America where you can’t bring a gun to your synagogue or your church to protect yourself. But most of the blue states have backed off on that.

Hon. Lawrence VanDyke:  Yeah. And something I just wanted to add. I haven’t heard much talk about this. But as a practical matter, one of the sort of problems with a sensitive area is—even the legitimate ones—is it actually often practically prevents people from being able to carry generally.

So, if your company you worked at said you can’t carry, which they may or may not be allowed to do, that’s going to prevent you from being able to carry most of the time because when you drive to your company, if they won’t let you park, and if you can’t -- if you couldn’t carry at church, you also aren’t going to be carrying after church when you go out to eat and such.

So I think, a lot of times, it gets lost as a practical -- and when I lived in Virginia but worked in D.C. and you couldn’t bring a handgun into D.C., it meant that you couldn’t have firearm in your vehicle, even though it was legal to do so in Virginia. You couldn’t because you’re driving from Virginia into D.C. And so they sort of—I don’t know what you’d call it—but these things reach beyond the actual area where they --

Prof. David H. Thompson:  Well, and Justice Alito made that point in decimating the New York Solicitor General in Bruen when she was suggesting that, “Well, we can’t have guns in subways.” And he’s like, “What are the janitors supposed to do who have to walk through a dangerous neighborhood after cleaning the big law office at 3:00 in the morning? If you don’t let them have a firearm on the subway, you’ve effectively disarmed them.”

Hon. Lawrence VanDyke:  Yes, precisely. All right. There’s a lot of agreement up here on that point, but I’m just a neutral moderator. [Laughter.] In the back.

Questioner 4:  Several panelists throughout this weekend have raised concern about the workability of the historical analysis in Bruen, partially due to resource constraints in the lower courts. So first question is, do you think that’s unworkable? And related to that, are challengers well advised even though they do not have the burden to show the historical record? Are they well advised to pre-argue and present the historical record so that the courts have a well-rounded historical record to go off of?

Prof. David H. Thompson:  I think the concerns are academic nonsense, okay? That’s the nicest thing I can say. I think it is a highly workable test. It is the best test. Sort of like Churchill, “The best democracy is the worst system other than all the rest,” okay? So it’s a very good test. It’s a workable test.

I’m not worried about the resources of the judiciary to be able to look at these statutes. And sure. As a litigator, you want to answer, even if it’s not our burden, if we have affirmative good historical evidence, we will absolutely put that forward. But as Mark was suggesting, you certainly don’t need to have a historian.

The other side wants to turn this into a battle of the experts. “Look how many leftwing academics we can bring into court who will prostitute themselves with a fanciful version of history.” In Bruen, there were zero experts. In Heller, there were zero experts. In Moore v. Madigan, there were zero experts. And in all of those cases, it was on a motion to dismiss, and summary judgment was granted by the appellate court.

That’s something I hope that all the appellate judges understand because it’s a little unusual, if we’re being honest with ourselves. But it makes perfect sense of, if you’re looking at the historical statutes, just go ahead and decide it. Why are you remanding it back? They didn’t do that in Heller, Bruen, and Judge Posner didn’t do that either.

Prof. Mark W. Smith:  And I just want to say it’s up to the parties to do the historical work. First of all, we’re not talking about ancient Rome here. We’re talking about the founding of this country, one of the parts of world history that has been studied the most. It’s only a couple of hundred years ago. The law has been there. It’s been studied for 200 plus years.

I don’t think there’s a lot of hidden meaning and all that. And the parties have to bring -- the Supreme Court said it’s up to the parties. And in the context of the Second Amendment, I can assure you there is no lack of resources on behalf of the billionaire funded anti-gun lobby.

What they’re whining about—and they are entitled to cheese with their whine perhaps—what they’re whining about is the fact that when they go back to 1791, it turns out that the text of the Second Amendment, which is now the right of the people, shall not bear arms, shall not be infringed, is that the text is corroborated by the lack of gun controls at the time, which makes a lot of sense if you think about it.

Why would you have a foundational Second Amendment in the Constitution itself and yet have a lot of gun control? It doesn’t make sense because it was viewed as a right. And keep in mind that if we were having a conversation about the burden of proof in a criminal case, where a person is presumed innocent and sits there and doesn’t have to do anything, and the entire burden is on the government to prove that someone committed a crime, we would not be crying about anything, right? That’s the burden of the government. In this case, it’s the same way.

You have a clear text. If it applies to a gun control law, the burden shifts to the government, just like it does in a criminal case, and tell them to prove it. And if they can’t prove it, they lose.

And as the Bruen Court said in a footnote—I think it’s footnote 14—where they’re talking about the Statute of Northampton and the Sir John Knight’s case, they basically say that if there’s a historical ambiguity in the historical record, the presumption is in favor of freedom. The presumption is in favor of the unqualified command of the text of the Second Amendment. So again, if the government can’t come forth and prove its history, it’s probably because there is no history of gun control in America because we fought a revolution over it at Lexington Green and beyond.

Prof. David H. Thompson:  Well, and in Bruen, too, that’s where we were able to show. Even though it wasn’t our burden, we were able to point to the fact that George Washington frequently traveled and carried with firearms, that John Adams brought a gun to school every day, that Thomas Jefferson wrote his 15-year-old nephew, “Let your gun be your constant companion.” And we went through and through. And so it wasn’t our burden to do that, but it just seemed prudent like, “Okay, it’s not our burden, but the evidence all goes our way. Let’s dump it on them and make the rubble bounce.”

Hon. Lawrence VanDyke:  All right. Well, we are at the end here. I don’t want to cut into our lunchtime, so thank you very much to our panelists. Thank you all for coming.

 

[Applause]

11:00 a.m. - 12:30 p.m.
The Injunction Function: Is IP Law Promoting Markets for Innovators and Creators?

2023 National Lawyers Convention

Topics: Intellectual Property
East Room
The Mayflower Hotel
1127 Connecticut Avenue NW
Washington, DC 20006

Share

Event Video

Listen & Download

Description

In patent and copyright law, injunctions are now a subject of significant policy debate. Innovators say they are unable to stop predatory infringement. Creators state they are unable to stop large-scale piracy websites. If so, this undermines the rewards promised by the intellectual property system and devalues the commercial assets that drive the global innovation economy in new technologies and creative works. Others state that intellectual property owners use injunctions to hold up innovation or chill legitimate commercial activity. This panel will discuss the role of injunctions in facilitating or constraining commercialization of patented technologies and copyrighted works, and what the current state of the law portends for the future, such as in the development of next-generation innovations like AI and its use of creative works.

Featuring:

  • Hon. John W. Holcomb, United States District Court, Central District of California
  • Prof. Kristen Jakobsen Osenga, Austin E. Owen Research Scholar & Professor of Law, The University of Richmond School of Law
  • Ms. Laurie Self, Senior Vice President & Counsel, Government Affairs, Qualcomm
  • Ms. Laura Sheridan, Head of Patent Policy, Google
  • Moderator: Hon. Ryan T. Holte, U.S. Court of Federal Claims; Jurist-In-Residence Professor of Law, The University of Akron School of Law

Overflow: Chinese Room

Speakers

Event Transcript

Andy Halaby:  I'm Andy Halaby. I'm a shareholder with Greenberg Law Firm, where I practice intellectual property litigation, among other things. I'm a member of The Federalist Society's Intellectual Property Practice Group, its Executive Committee. And I'm delighted to welcome you to today's discussion on "The Injunction Function: Is IP Law Promoting Markets for Innovators and Creators?"

 

Let me begin with a brief announcement on CLE. For those of you who are pursuing CLE, we remind you that to get credit you need to sign in and out each day, once per day. Signing in and signing out can be done by scanning the CLE QR codes. Thus, if you're pursuing CLE and you have not checked in, please be sure to scan the QR code on the back of your convention booklet or on the CLE poster. If you've already checked in via the QR code, there's no need to recheck.

 

Second, a word about the Intellectual Property Practice Group here at The Federalist Society. Among other activities, the Practice Group sponsors a variety of IP-related events, in person and virtual, throughout the year, coordinates publication of IP-related pieces in The Federalist Society Review and on the FedSoc Blog, and works with other Federalist Society Practice Groups on projects of mutual interest. If you would like to get involved with the IP Practice Group, please reach out to Nate Kaczmarek or another member of the FedSoc staff. 

 

Finally, I'm pleased to introduce our moderator and, as you'll see, resident polymath, Judge Ryan T. Holte of the United States Court of Federal Claims. Before ascending to the bench in 2019, Judge Holte served as the David L. Brennan Associate Professor of Law and Director of the Center for Intellectual Property Law & Technology at the University of Akron School of Law, and, before that, as a law professor at the Southern Illinois University School of Law.

 

Prior to entering academia, Judge Holte practiced as a litigation attorney with the Federal Trade Commission and is an associate with the Intellectual Property Practice Group at Jones Day and as a patent prosecutor at Finnegan. Before that, Judge Holte served as a clerk to Judge Stanley F. Birch, Jr. on the Eleventh Circuit and as a law clerk to Judge Loren A. Smith on the United States Court of Federal Claims.

 

Before law school, among other pursuits, Judge Holte worked as an engineer for Agilent Technologies, Hewlitt Packard, in Sonoma County.  He is a co-inventor on United States Patent number 9523773, "Systems and Methods for Countering Satellite-Navigated Munitions," which issued in 2016.

 

He is a widely-published researcher and author on intellectual property-related subjects, including, as pertinent to today's panel discussion, "Deep, an Empirical Study of Patent Entity Practices, as well as Application of Equitable Remedies in Patent Litigation.  He received his JD from the University of California, Davis, School of Law, where he served as a staff editor on the UC Davis Business Law Journal.  He received his BS magna cum laude in engineering from the California Maritime Academy, where he was a first-class graduate of the California Maritime Academy Corp of Cadets Third Engineering Division. Judge Holte.

 

Hon. Ryan T. Holte:  Thank you, Andy. Let me just make sure. Can everybody hear me?

 

Hon. John W. Holcomb:  I can hear you from my side.

 

Hon. Ryan T. Holte:  All right. There we go. Well, thank you, Andy, for the long introduction, which I think we emailed about cutting short yesterday. But I really appreciate everybody being here. I know that we're competing against the Second Amendment panel down the hall. For those who are in the room, obviously, they might have more fireworks than us. But we'll have to change that with a great discussion this morning on injunctions and patents and copyrights.

 

      So the plan for the program will be that I will read every speaker's introduction at the beginning of their remarks. I will then give them five to seven minutes for opening remarks. And we'll hopefully have at least 30 minutes at the end for discussion amongst panel members and questions from the audience. So, as Andy noted, this panel is about "Injunction Function. Is IP Law Promoting Markets for Innovators and Creators?"

 

      And, by way of brief introduction, I'll read our planned focus of conversation. In patent copyright law, injunctions are now a subject of significant policy debate. Innovators say they are unable to stop predatory infringement. Creators say they are unable to stop large-scale piracy websites. If so, this undermines the rewards promised by the IP system, and devalues the commercial assets that drive the global economy in new technologies and creative works. 

 

      Others state that intellectual property owners use injunctions to hold up innovation or chill legitimate commercial activity. This panel will focus on the role of injunctions in facilitating or constraining commercialization of patented technologies and copyrighted works and what the current state of the law portends for the future, such as in the development of next-generation innovations like AI and the use of creative works.

 

      Our speaker will begin with Laura Sheridan, the Head of Patent Policy at Google, to my left. Laura has shared her views on patent issues in numerous policy dialogs, including testifying before Congress on the intersection of AI and patents. Her patent policy work is shaped by years of private practice experience in both patent prosecution, litigation, due diligence, and post-grant practice, including counsel at WilmerHale. As an active member of the IP community, Laura is part of the Intellectual Property Owners Association delegation to IP5 Industry, a group that engages on procedural harmonization matters with the IP5 Offices worldwide.

 

      Laura also helped to form the New York chapter of ChIPS and is a member of the advisory board for the NYU Law Engelberg Center on Innovation Law & Policy. Laura studied mechanical engineering at Cornell University and received her JD from Fordham Law School. Laura will begin her remarks today with a discussion on AI development and how AI development is best incentivized through the patent system. We'll also examine the post-eBay data and innovations impacts. Thank you, Laura.

 

Laura Sheridan:  Thank you, Judge Holte. I'm honored to be part of this event and panel on the important topic of injunctions and how to make sure remedies in patent litigation serve the Constitution's explicit goal of promoting innovation. And I'm speaking from the perspective of a company that was a start-up in a garage only 25 years ago, and last year spent more than $39 billion in R&D. The importance of policies that promote innovation for companies of every size and at every stage of their development is deeply embedded within Google. 

 

      The starting point for this conversation has to be the Constitution, which establishes our patent system in Article I Section 8 Clause 8.  The Constitution says that "Congress shall have the power to promote the progress of science and the useful arts by securing, for limited times, to authors and inventors, the exclusive right to their respective writings and discoveries." With this language, the Constitution gives Congress the power to create a patent system for the explicit and sole purpose of promoting the progress of science and the useful arts, in other words, innovation.

 

      What's absent from this view is that patent rights represent natural rights or traditional property rights. On the contrary, patents are to be defined by statute, created by Congress as instruments of economic policy in furtherance of innovation. Justice Thomas explained this point in the 2018 Oil States case, stating that "Patents convey only a specific form of property right, and that is a public franchise, meaning one that's defined by statute, and not a core or a traditional property right."

 

      As Justice Thomas also explained in the 2017 Teva case, patents have a regulatory effect that restrains the actions of others and free enterprise. And you can think of each and every patent as a government regulation. If you're interested in this topic, I urge you to read Paul Clement's paper on this, called "Patent Rights v. Property, the Framers' Understanding of Patents." So, these fundamental principles should undergird our understanding of injunctions in patent litigation.

 

      So, let's fast-forward from 1789 to 2006, when the Supreme Court decided the eBay case, which dealt with this very issue. In a unanimous decision, Justice Thomas wrote that the well-established principles of equity that govern when a plaintiff can obtain injunctive relief applied equally to patent cases. The Court held that equity law did not support a rule of automatic injunctions following a finding of infringement, which the lower courts had been applying, to that time. To summarize, no special rules for patents when it comes to injunctions.

 

      So, let's momentarily go back to the Constitution and its reference to the patent system providing inventors with an exclusive right to their discoveries. That is something that's often pointed to in support of automatic injunctions. But what the eBay decision makes clear is that the exclusive right that is granted to inventors, just like the exclusive right in any type of property, must be evaluated and remedied in accordance with the principles of equity. And for patent cases, this still means that the large majority of them result in an injunction. But the Constitution's reference to an exclusive right in no way requires an automatic complete and immediate injunction, regardless of the circumstances and ignoring equity.

 

      So now let's talk about how the patent system operates. This will help make clear why the balance and flexibility that eBay brings is so important. Every year, there are over 600,000 patent applications filed in the U.S., and around 350,000 patents are granted. Patent applications are allowable unless the patent examiner can prove otherwise. But each patent application receives, on average, about 19 hours of time, from start to finish. These days, more than 50 percent of our U.S. patents are actually granted to non-U.S. entities. Huawei is at the top of that list.

 

      So, the reality for innovative companies is that the large number of active patents creates something called a "patent thicket." A smart phone and its use can implicate over 250,000 patents. These patents are held by thousands of different owners, many of whose claims overlap with one another. And because patent examiners are given relatively little time to do the very hard work of examination, in spite of the effort they put in, mistakes can be made. One study shows that, in software, up to half of the patents could be at least partially invalid. 

 

      So, you may be hearing that patents are akin to land. Aside from the Supreme Court's legal recognition that they are a public franchise, the reality of the patent system underscores how false this is. I personally would welcome changes to the patent examination process that bring us closer to that, with more reliability and clarity. And much of my own policy work is about proposing concrete improvements to move us in that direction. But it's not where we are today.

 

      So, with this understanding of the scope and functioning of our patent system, let's look at how things are playing out in litigation, and what has happened in the 17 years since eBay. The evidence shows that eBay is working in a balanced, flexible way that supports the Constitution's goal of promoting innovation. The large majority of infringement findings result in an injunction being granted.

 

      A study from 2019 comparing data before and after eBay shows a drop of just 4 percent, from 89 percent down to 85. And the decline was largely due to denials of injunction to non-practicing entities, or NPEs. These are entities in the business of patent monetization. The decline for NPEs makes sense. An NPE actually does not want to shut down a product. They want to maximize licensing fees. And the only reason the NPE seeks an injunction is to leverage that threat to shut down a product to extract more than the patent is actually worth. But if you're looking at operating companies, research institutions, and -- is that five, or seven?

 

Hon. Ryan T. Holte:  It was six, but you still have one more.

 

Laura Sheridan:  Excellent, one more minute. But if you're looking at operating companies, research institutions, and inventors, the impact of eBay was minimal. But beyond the impact at the case level, we also have data and studies on the broader economic impact. First, overall patenting activity has substantially increased since eBay was decided, suggesting no discouragement from using the system. In fact, we have more than double the patents today than we did in 2005.

 

      A study from 2018 found no evidence that eBay harmed American innovation. And that study looked at patenting as well, along with R&D, venture capital, and productivity growth. When it comes to encouraging R&D investment, right now we are focused on ensuring the U.S. remains a leader in critical areas like AI innovation, and that our policies support unlocking the tremendous potential of this technology. And a balanced approach to patent injunctions, as we have today, is one of the many ways our patent policy can support this leadership and growth. I look forward to this panel's discussion. Thank you.

 

Hon. Ryan T. Holte:  Thank you, Laura. And I know I already have a number of questions to follow up on. But we will roll through the rest of the panel, and perhaps get some of those addressed. Next up, to my left, is Laurie Self, the Senior Vice President and Counsel of Government Affairs at Qualcomm. At Qualcomm, Laurie specializes in U.S. patent policy matters at the federal and state level. 

 

      She's based in Washington D.C. and also supports Qualcomm's government affairs initiatives to promote strong IP rights in emerging markets. Laurie's particular focus is to ensure U.S. IP laws and policies provide the necessary protections and incentives to support the company's R&D-driven business model. Prior to her arrival at Qualcomm in July of 2012, Laurie was a partner at Covington and Burling, where she chaired the firm's IP practice group. She is a graduate of Duke University and the University of Virginia School of Law.

 

      Laurie will share her perspective as a member of a company that invests billions of dollars in R&D technology with patents being the driver of the investments. She will discuss injunctions. To what extent do we have remedies for users of technology to come to the table? And do we have a system of laws that provide adequate incentives for users of our technology in the United States and worldwide? Thank you, Laurie.

 

Laurie Self:  Thank you. So, if you know anything about Qualcomm and anything about Google's policy positions on patents over the last two decades, you know that I would take issue with a lot of what Laura was saying, other than where the intellectual property clause resides within the Constitution.

 

Hon. Ryan T. Holte:  At least we can agree on something.

 

Laurie Self:  But there is common ground. There is common ground there. But what I wanted to do is kind of take a step back and sort of explain the role that patents have played in Qualcomm's trajectory. And I think as you hear different points of view on these issues — and, of course, there are very strong divisions of opinion on these issues, and have been, really, throughout the history of our patent system — what speaks to those divisions often has to do with a company's business model and how they use patents within their particular business and the nexus between patents and that kind of R&D equation, if you will. 

 

      So, not to say that anybody's right or wrong. But this is one of those issues where you really have to understand the role that patents — from our perspective, a property right — play in driving investments in innovation. So, Qualcomm was founded in 1985. We were founded based on a theory of how wireless communications could be radically transformed, radically improved over previous generations of communications technologies, without a particular product in mind.

 

      Our founders were academics, consultants to the defense industry. Our founder was one of the leading founders of UCSD Engineering School. So, again, it was bridging that divide between the kind of basic research that you do at schools like MIT and the commercial sector, and finding technologies that would help transform a sector like telecommunications. So, we were essentially that quintessential startup that relied upon patents as really the only asset to drive venture capital investments.

 

      That is true for the startup economy today, at least for those startup sectors that are very R&D-intensive. And biotech is one of the lead examples in this modern day. But as we moved forward as a company, our mission was really to create transformative technology that would drive a mobile ecosystem. We did not have a product in mind. We did not intend to use our inventions to create a product space. What we were trying to do was create inventions, again, that would revolutionize mobile communications broadly.

 

      So, if you think about that business model, patents for market-based companies are really fundamental. And, again, if you think about the role of trade secrets or other forms of intellectual property, if you think about how we compete with companies in countries where there is large government subsidization of R&D, in a market-based economy, you really are relying on private sector investments in R&D, and an intellectual property rights system that will incentivize those investments.

 

      So, for each generation of cellular technology, you're talking about 10 years of R&D. That R&D leadership position leads leadership in standards, which, again — when you think about cellular standards — that is another platform for ongoing R&D, another 10 years of technological development. That 20 year trajectory, before you see full commercialization of a technology, can only survive if you have a patent system that justifies those investments at the outset, and allows a return on investment through the duration, if you will. And, obviously, the protection we see with patents is critical to that.

 

      We fund our R&D exclusively through patent licenses. We have global portfolios of patents. And when you talk about the so-called patent thicket, the way the market has avoided those concerns is largely through portfolio licensing, which occurs, again, on a global basis. We have about 140,000 pending and issued patents that we license globally. And that licensing ecosystem, and the stability of that licensing ecosystem is very much dependent on the remedies that underlie our patent system.

 

      So, we do not view the injunction as a kind of sword we hang over the head of potential licensees. We view it as an incentive that brings large companies to the negotiating table. Qualcomm is a large company. But our licensees tend to be much larger than we are. And the only way you can encourage those companies to come voluntarily to the negotiating table to secure a license on patents — which is, again, publicly available — in the standards ecosystem you're basically teaching the world about the capabilities of your technology, how to utilize your technology.

 

      That dynamic only works if you have rules and remedies that encourage companies to voluntarily license, as opposed to just, essentially, steal patented technology. Today, our key competitors in R&D are largely Chinese companies that do not have the same market pressures, the same systems of laws that we have in the United States, which, again, makes having a fair rule of law and a strong property rights system in the United States all the more important.

 

      The fact that we're able to secure license payments and agreements with Chinese companies, I think, speaks to the fact that they recognize that there are international norms at play, including remedies that underlie patent rights. That whole equation starts to break down when you make it impossible to obtain injunctions. And the data that we've seen shows that eBay has actually had a dramatic effect on the ability to obtain injunctive relief.

 

      So, it's not just a question of what we do in the United States and how that impacts litigation rates and remedies in the United States. It's how we maintain a global ecosystem of technology leadership where market-based R&D incentives are premised on patent rights. So, I'll stop there. Thank you. 

 

Hon. Ryan T Holte:  Thank you, Laurie. Next down the line is Professor Kristen Jakobsen Osenga, the Austin EEO Research Scholar and Professor of Law and Associate Dean for Academic Affairs at the University of Richmond School of Law. Now, I know Professor Osenga has much to say about what we've already talked about, but she will be transitioning into copyrights and trade secrets. Professor Osenga teaches and writes in all areas of intellectual property law, including patent law, antitrust, legislation and regulation.

 

      After law school, she practiced at the law firm Finnegan, Henderson, Farabow, Garrett & Dunner, where she worked on patent prosecution and litigation matters. She then clerked for Judge Linn of the U.S. Court of Appeals for the Federal Circuit. She then entered academia, teaching first at Chicago Kent College of Law, then at the University of Richmond, where she has served since 2006, and has also served as visiting professor at Emory University and William & Mary School of Law.

 

      Professor Osenga received her B.S. degree in biomedical engineering from the University of Iowa, master's degree in electrical engineering from Southern Illinois University, and a J.D. from the University of Illinois College of Law, where she graduated magna cum laude. Some of Professor Osenga's recent scholarship focuses on patent-eligible subject matter, patent licensing firms, standard development organizations, patent law reform, and claim construction. But, as I noted before, she will be focusing her, at least introductory, remarks on copyrights and trade secrets. With that, Professor Osenga.

 

Prof. Kristen Jakobsen Osenga:  Thank you, Judge. I'm going to tell you, the day we had the teleconference to decide who was going to talk about what, I missed the call.

 

Hon. Ryan T Holte:  Teach you not to do that again.

 

Prof. Kristen Jakobsen Osenga:  I am never, ever going to miss a planning call again. So, I have the topic that no one wanted to cover, even me. So I will do my best to cover it. There's a couple of recent academic pieces in this space, not by me, that provided some helpful information. And Judge Holte promised me later I can talk about what I want to talk about during Q&A. So, some of you may be wondering why, as Judge Holte framed it up, we're talking about patents and copyrights. I'm going to tell you. We're going to talk about trade secrets, but not trademarks.

 

      I'm going to cover trademarks very quickly at the end of my remarks because I think trademark also demonstrates a potentially viable path forward for some of the problems we're talking about today. But I'm going to start with copyright, and then trade secrets. So, not surprisingly, the eBay test has expanded out of patent law and is being used in all areas of IP and even other areas of law. Just like in patent law, the tricky part of applying the test is reconciling what is irreparable harm in any given situation, and, also, what is the public's interest, particularly in copyright law, which is built around the same right to exclude that Laura mentioned. 

 

      The inability to prevent ongoing infringement would seem to be an irreparable harm, and yet, when injunctive relief is denied, it's usually on this prong, and oftentimes in conjunction with the adequacy of money damages. While some folks argue that the public may have an interest in getting more infringing stuff more cheaply and more often, there's also a significant public interest in having a well-functioning, reliable copyright system. Trade secrets similarly rest on an ability to exclude other people, although that's a little more bound by the danger of reverse engineering. 

 

      So, let's start with copyright. And I'm going to talk about an article that Pam Samuelson published in 2022 in the William & Mary Law Review. I will also mention, Pam Samuelson called me, at one time, a patent maximalist, and thought it was an insult. It was not. So, she published this paper examining injunctions in copyright cases post-eBay, so I'm relying on her survey of that. I disagree fully with her assessment of what it means, that all is well, and eBay is amazing, but I will rely on her survey of the landscape. 

 

      So, copyright law, prior to Campbell v. Acuff-Rose in 1994, was pretty much like patent law prior to eBay. Upon a finding of infringement, an injunction would generally issue pretty much like the federal circuit prior to eBay. Courts thought copyright owners were entitled to injunctive relief, denying injunctions only in cases where there were other inequities, such as unreasonable delay in seeking relief, or the idea of de minimis harm against a backdrop of significant investment by the infringers, so, for example, an infringing picture or two in a book, where the real value of the book was the entirety of the text authored by the infringer.

 

      So, between Campbell — which was notable because of a footnote that suggested that if there's parity or fair use and it's a close case, you shouldn't get an injunction — and eBay, Professor Samuelson's paper noticed no dramatic shift. Injunctions would still, generally, issue. There were a few cases where injunctive relief did not issue. But there wasn't a groundswell following that note in Acuff-Rose. So, then eBay was issued, and — no surprise — things changed. But it wasn't quite as drastic or instantaneous as it was in patent law. Post-eBay and copyright, courts still generally issue injunctions in simple piracy cases.

 

      When injunctive relief is denied, it's most often because the copyright owner hasn't established irreparable harm or the inadequacy of money damages. Of course, the courts also consider the other two things: a balance of the hardships and the public-interest prongs. And those come up largely where the copyright claim and the injunction being sought is to protect a non-copyright interest, like somebody's reputation. "We don't want this to be published because somebody's reputation is at issue, so we're not going to enjoin that, because it's not a copyright interest being protected."

 

      So how is this working? Well, injunctions in copyright cases are seemingly working very well in areas of large-scale piracy, less good in gray areas. So, areas where we have parity or sampling or a small portion of a bigger thing — oh, my God, this sounds like patent law — those are the areas that are really tricky for getting injunctive relief in copyright. So, the status of copyright is probably very similar to what we see in patent law.

 

      As far as trade secrets, things are even trickier there because trade secret remedies were governed by state law, often informed by the UTSA and brought in state courts prior to the Defend Trade Secrets Act in 2016. There are now, after that, significantly more federal trade secret cases. And so, now, I rely on another professor who has not insulted me in public, Elizabethe Rowe. She published a study in 2020, an empirical study on injunctive relief in trade secret cases, both before and after eBay

 

      So, traditionally, injunctive relief was available in trade secret cases where the plaintiff could not show monetary harm. And that was pretty standard. It would just issue. Although neither the UTSA nor the DTSA require courts to apply eBay when assessing whether to enjoin a trade secret misappropriator, the factors that are raised by the courts, according to Professor Rowe's research, are very similar because they're just brought up as a matter of equity. Just like with all other areas of IP, the big split becomes whether there should be a presumption of irreparable harm upon a finding of trade secret misappropriation. 

 

      Courts, in general, are still accepting that trade secret misappropriation results in irreparable harm. But one of Professor Rowe's more interesting findings is that oftentimes, when an injunction doesn't issue upon a finding of trade secret misappropriation, it's because the trade secret owner didn't even ask. So, how are injunctions working in the world of trade secrets? Well, it would seem they would work a lot better if trade secret owners would actually seek them.

 

      Finally, we'll wrap up with trademark law, which, weirdly, is, at least in my mind, the least property rights-based IP, which may have actually just figured out the answer to eBay before all the other types of IP.  So, specifically, the Trademark Modernization Act of 2020 addressed a split in the circuits about whether a finding of trademark infringement created a presumption of irreparable harm, or whether the trademark owner actually had to go forth and affirmatively prove irreparable harm, along with the other eBay factors.

 

      And the TMA amended the Lanham Act to clarify there is a presumption of irreparable harm that applies upon a finding of infringement. Taking that factor out of the eBay test — whether we're in patents, copyrights, trademarks, trade secrets — we make it a lot easier to obtain injunctive relief. And I wouldn't mind seeing that adopted in all areas of law. And I will conclude my remarks there.

 

Hon. Ryan T Holte:  Thank you, Professor Osenga. Finishing up the panel with the other judicial pillar, at the end, we have Judge John Holcomb from the U.S. District Court for the Central District of California. Judge Holcomb was confirmed to the district court in September of 2020. Prior to his legal career, Judge Holcomb obtained a B.S. in engineering from MIT and subsequently served on active duty in the Navy from 1984 to 1989 with duty stations including the battleship U.S.S. New Jersey with home port in Long Beach, California, and Joint Staff at the Pentagon.

 

      After military service, Judge Holcomb attended Harvard Business School and Harvard Law School, where he earned a JD/MBA, served as a law clerk on the U.S. Bankruptcy Court for the Northern District of Illinois, and then practiced intellectual property law at Irell & Manella from 1994 to 1997, and Knobbe Martens as an IP litigator for the next 21 years. Immediately before Senate confirmation, Judge Holcomb was a partner at Greenberg Gross, where he focused on intellectual property and bankruptcy litigation matters.

 

      Judge Holcomb will show the perspective from the district court on the issues discussed and will also provide insight into copyrights in the context of trade secrets. Thank you, Judge Holcomb.

 

Hon. John W. Holcomb:  Thank you, Judge Holt. I'm delighted to be here. I do want to say happy Veteran's Day to my fellow veterans. Today is Veteran's Day. So, it's a little bit daunting to be on this panel with these pretty impressive lawyers, a judge, and professor. I was just a lowly IP litigator for some 25 years before I was fortunate enough to be appointed to the bench. And I think it would be helpful for me to explain what my perspective has been since I've been on the bench, and how I got to where I am now.

 

      As an IP litigator, looking back on my career, I tended, not by design, but I tended to represent more plaintiffs than defendants. So, I tended to be very friendly toward permanent injunctions and often couldn't understand why we didn't get a permanent injunction in my cases when I thought it was clearly called for. I was surprised when eBay came out in 2006. I think I speak for the patent community in general. We were very comfortable with the pre-eBay view of the federal circuit, which was very favorable to permanent injunctions. And it came as a bit of a surprise to learn that it wasn't something that was automatic, or nearly automatic, in patent cases.

 

      But that was -- well, let me put it this way. Some would argue that eBay was not a change in the law. It simply said we're not going to have an automatic rule, but apply the factors. And if one reads Chief Justice Roberts' concurring opinion, one, I think, would come to the conclusion that's essentially what he was saying, is this isn't that big of a deal. We're saying "textualist analysis." We're saying, "look at the statute." And it's a "may." Courts "may" grant permanent injunctions. But it's not an automatic. But that's fine. There's a long tradition of granting those injunctions.

 

      And then there was the Justice Kennedy concurrence, where he expressed a somewhat different view. Although he concurred in the judgment of eBay, he suggested there were some reasons why perhaps courts should not be so quick to grant permanent injunctions. And, as Judge Holte has written eloquently in several articles, there's certainly an argument to be made that courts, at least district courts, have improperly applied the Justice Kennedy concurrence and not looked more carefully at the actual holding in eBay.

 

      The actual holding in eBay was the district judge, Judge Friedman's, view was not correct. He had a categorical denial of permanent injunctions under certain circumstances. That's one holding. The second holding was the federal circuit's view, as I just said, of nearly automatic granting of permanent injunctions, that's not correct. The third holding was that Continental Paper Bag is still good law. And Continental Paper Bag — I don't know if you were going to talk about it — from 1908, is a holding that says, I'm paraphrasing, "It's perfectly fine for a patentee to not be practicing its patented invention, and yet obtain a permanent injunction." 

 

      So that was actually the holding in eBay, those three key points. Anyway, that was kind of my view, coming to the bench. And I remember, early on, having conversations with some of my colleagues about judicial philosophy and injunctions. And I expressed my view, coming from private practice, that they should be granted more frequently. And I got pushback from some very wise mentors. And one of the things that kind of resonated with me is if you grant a preliminary injunction or permanent injunction, you need to be ready to enforce it with force.

 

      You need to be ready, if necessary, to find a contemnor in contempt, I guess, a violator of the injunction, in contempt. And you need to be willing, if necessary, to put him in jail. If you're not willing to do that, think very carefully about whether you're going to issue a permanent injunction. So, I think that informs the view of many district judges when they approach permanent injunctions.

 

      The other thing is, I wanted to, kind of on the flip side, provide — as Judge Holte did in some of his scholarship — a bit of a defense of the district judge in eBay, Judge Freidman, in the Eastern District of Virginia, who denied a permanent injunction twice: once pre-cert, and once post-remand. One of the issues that Judge Friedman expressed was a concern about how his court was going to be affected if he granted a permanent injunction.

 

      He expressed a concern — and, again, I'm paraphrasing — that his court would be inundated with post-judgment proceedings about whether or not there had been compliance with the injunction. And he used that as a reason to deny a permanent injunction. And, again, I can tell you, from a district judge's perspective, that is a concern. We have very limited resources. People are often surprised when I say, "For your case, it's just me and one of my law clerks working on it. And I have about 399 other civil cases that I'm working on. So, we're pretty busy. We don't have a lot of bandwidth."

 

      That having been said, I don't think it's a proper concern to say I'm not going to grant a permanent injunction merely because it's going to keep me busy, going forward. And, again, I talked to one of my colleagues about this when I first took the bench. I'll wrap up really quickly here. It came up in the context of a motion to remand. District judges, you'll not be surprised to learn, love to remand cases, because they no longer have them on their docket. And there are some times when it's absolutely appropriate and required that you do that when you don't have jurisdiction.

 

      There are many cases that are kind of wobblers. Do you remand or not? And I remember having a conversation with a colleague, saying, "How do we think about this? I'd love to remand this case, just to have it off my docket. But I'm not sure that that's right, under the law." And this wise judge said to me two things. He said, "One, it's fine to note that and acknowledge it. You'd be crazy not to, and you'd probably be led astray if you didn't acknowledge that you would like to do that. So, acknowledge it. Put it aside. And then rule on the merits."

 

      So, I think that's the best way to view that issue, and the best way to view permanent injunctions. So, from a litigator's standpoint, I think, keep in mind that your request for a permanent injunction, the judge is probably going to be thinking, "If I grant this it's going to be, potentially, a lot more work down the road." And keep that in mind. Do all you can do to help the judge by recommending language for the permanent injunction that makes it clear what is permitted and what is not permitted. All right. Thank you.

 

Hon. Ryan T Holte:  Thank you, Judge Holcomb. It's always great to invite judicial colleagues on the panel. They do a wonderful job of summarizing previous work and writings that I've done. So, I appreciate that. Much better than academic colleagues from my previous life where they just spend the whole discussion disagreeing with you, as Professor Osenga mentioned other academics in her work.

 

      So I wanted to begin with allowing the panelists brief comments on other opening remarks that were made. And we'll begin with Laura. And I wanted to begin each comment process by posing a bit of a question. And, with that, Laura, you, I think, had strong head agreement with Judge Holcomb's points related to Chief Justice Roberts' concurrence in eBay that the decision was no change to the standards of patent law.

 

      However, I think, as you noted in your opening remarks, the statistics seem to show otherwise. I was wondering if you could share your perspective on any of the remarks that were made, and, specifically, any commentary on Chief Justice Roberts' concurrence in the eBay decision.

 

Laura Sheridan:  Thanks. It's a great question. Yeah, I read eBay. And that concurrence is really standing for a simple message. And the whole decision itself, the main decision, is just five pages. So, it's really just saying, "Show your work." It wants the district court to demonstrate that the principles of equity have been applied in that case, and that the eBay factors have been gone through so that you are showing how, in this very fact-specific situation, the remedy makes sense. 

 

      And that really resonates. Because that has been the main takeaway for me from eBay is you just need to make sure that you are showing the work for your particular situation. And so, looking at the way this has played out, the data has shown not much of a drop, from 89 percent to 85 percent, in terms of the grant of the injunction. But what is really important, when we're thinking about an injunction, this isn't an on-off switch. And that ties into what Chief Justice Roberts was saying about showing your work. This is not, "Yes, you get an injunction. No you don't."

 

      It is, "Maybe the injunction needs to be delayed somewhat. Based on the specific facts of this case, maybe we need to tailor it in a certain way to allow the sell-off of all these cars that are already on dealer lots around the country." There is tailoring of these injunctions that happens that, thanks to eBay, it was a reminder to say, "You just need to show us that this remedy is tailored to your specific case." So, I think that's a very important thing to take away from eBay, and just generally in the 16 years since.  It's about tailoring the remedy to the case that's before you.

 

      I think one other point — and maybe we'll get a chance to talk more about this later, because I could go on for a while — but this idea of parties not wanting to come to the table since eBay. It just makes bad business sense to not come to the table. We will pay more if there is a litigation. There is a study that shows the ongoing royalty rate that a company will pay if they end up having that infringement finding in litigation is 70 percent more than what they would pay if a deal could have been reached before litigation. And, in the Eastern District of Texas, where a lot of these cases are found, it's 76 percent more. 

 

      You have every incentive to avoid that situation, if at all possible, because that doesn’t even include the $5 million in lawyers' fees and discovery costs that are associated with the litigation, not to mention all of your engineers saying, "Why am I being deposed and prepping for trial?" So, we want to come to the table. We want to do deals. We have a team dedicated to doing deals. It just makes good business sense to do so. And I expect we'll get to talk more about that dynamic later in the discussion.

 

Hon. Ryan T Holte:  One note of clarification, Laura. I'm not sure what you mentioned, but, from my academic work on empirical numbers, my statistics showed that before eBay, district courts were granting injunctions between 94 and 100 percent of the time, with no difference between the type of entity, including non-practicing entities.

 

      After eBay, the statistics, for a 10-year period after, showed a general grant, across all plaintiffs, of 72.5 percent, and for non-practicing entities, down to 16 percent. Does that cover the numbers that you mentioned? And it seems to me that that shows that there is significant impact on the eBay decision, despite only a direction of, "Show your work."

 

Laura Sheridan:  So, I am looking at a 2019 study that was looking at the impact of eBay on what it calls high-volume plaintiffs, before and after. And that was showing, I think, that's sort of how it's trying to get at what is an NPE, and the impact there. But the 2019 study did show just an 89 percent to 85 percent. I think the data, depending on exactly how it's sliced and diced and when it was taken, I think there is some variation.

 

      But just briefly on the NPE point, I think this is an important one, too. I think that the good thing about eBay is we really shouldn't try to put plaintiffs into buckets all that much, because it doesn't help. And eBay, because it is a flexible framework where the district court judge is allowed to look at the facts of the case and make a remedy that makes sense, calling an entity an NPE or something else is just not helpful.

 

      It's about what is that particular plaintiff in your court doing with the invention? Have they been licensing it? Are they a startup? Are they winding down? Who are they? It's not a black and white, NPE/not NPE. So I think that probably some of the variation in the data is just not always that helpful anyway to try to qualify or classify these entities.

 

Hon. Ryan T Holte:  Great. Thank you, Laura. Moving on to Laurie for some comments on other opening remarks that were made. And I'll just tee up, perhaps, a first question for you, in addition to your opening comments. I believe that there's been some recent public discussion on, perhaps, a legislative "fix" to eBay that has come out of the Senate. Do you believe that there are legislative solutions that might be necessary in order to continue encouraging innovation?

 

Laurie Self:  Yes, there is. So, just to take a step back. And, first of all, on the point about data, I think it's really, as we talk about data and statistics, you really have to drill down to the details of those empirical studies to really understand what they show. The research that we've seen most recently shows a really precipitous drop in injunctions. And, again, it's not so much the result of Justice Thomas' decision, per se, which, I agree, did not endorse categorical rules, either in favor or against injunctions. It was meant to be a flexible framework.

 

      Now, I think, for the scholars in the room, they would argue that Justice Thomas got the case law wrong, in terms of understanding what preceded eBay, in terms of how courts historically granted injunctive relief. And one of the key points that has been made is that, prior to eBay, if you were successful in establishing the validity of your patent and infringement by the defendant, that there was a presumption in favor of injunctive relief. What we're seeing being proposed, in terms of legislation, is legislation that would restore that presumption. 

 

      Now, the presumption is just that. It leaves discretion with the court. But at least it creates a greater opportunity for plaintiffs to receive injunctive relief in situations where the court deems it appropriate. And that, in fact, is why we're seeing less effect in the context of trademarks, because there has been legislation that affirmed that presumptive remedy in the context of trademarks. And we do support that legislation, by the way.

 

      I think what has been so challenging, post-eBay, is the way in which district courts have interpreted eBay. They have interpreted eBay as a kind of categorical rule. They have drawn clear distinctions between what they perceive as so-called non-practicing entities and commercial competitors. I think that is a real disservice, if you will, to the foundations of the patent system, which was meant to create incentives to specialize in innovation.

 

      In other words, it was meant to create a kind of grassroots opportunity to participate in our invention ecosystem to give rise to entrepreneurship, to give rise to R&D specialists, to give rise to a diversified technology ecosystem. And that has really been, I think, a core strength of the U.S. innovation economy, relative to other countries that have very different forms of intellectual property rights. So, what we've seen, in terms of the post-eBay application by district courts of the Thomas opinion, is what I think is so problematic and really needs to be remedied through legislation.

 

      The only other point I'd like to make — just to respond to the Judge's comment about this perception that if you grant an injunction, you could be sending someone to jail — I first started working on U.S. patent policy. I had been an intellectual property lawyer for my entire career, but these issues around patent reform became hot and heavy in the timeframe when — if you remember Blackberry, when Blackberry was king of the hill, in terms of devices — there was a district court decision in which the court was threatening injunctive relief against Blackberry. 

 

      And there was this fear that everybody on the Hill was going to lose their Blackberry. And it created this kind of fear, if you will, around the impact of an injunction. What was really happening in that case was the court was trying to do everything possible to incentivize the infringer to come to the negotiating table and resolve the matter without resorting to an injunction.

 

      And I think that is the role of the injunction, to create appropriate incentives to avoid litigation, to ensure that parties who refuse to license are not allowed to continue making use of the patented technology, and to create a dynamic where owners of patented technology actually have the right to decide how to use that technology. If you do not have access to an injunction, you are essentially positioning courts as arbiters of compulsory licenses and rate regulators.

 

      You are allowing the court to displace the role of the market in determining the role of patented technology. And, by the way, as we all know, litigation takes years before a verdict is reached and the damages remedy is available to a patent owner. If you're a small startup, it's almost impossible to survive that juggernaut. So, I just think there's a lot of nuance to the situation that we really need to understand to put these issues in appropriate context. So, I'll stop there.

 

Hon. Ryan T Holte:  Thank you, Laurie. Wonderful to have you summarize the rest of the academic scholarship that Judge Holcomb didn't have time for. And my article on that was "The Misinterpretation of eBay and Why," for anyone interested. Moving on to Professor Osenga, I promised you a great opportunity to talk about patents in your follow-up remarks. So, with that, I'll tee up. You have a recent published paper on efficient infringement. Could you possibly talk about your thesis there and how it relates to the eBay case?

 

Prof. Kristen Jakobsen Osenga:  I can. But first, I want to make sure you do it right. It's "efficient infringement." It is not efficient infringement. I did actually manage to get the Law Review to put it in scare quotes through the entirety of the article. And I'm very proud of that. In fact, I think I have a couple articles now. So, "efficient infringement," or, as I would like it to be called, but nobody ever takes my suggestions, "predatory infringement," is something that happens because of eBay.

 

      And so, just a quick explainer on the idea of it. One of the functions that injunctions serve is to deter infringement. You don't want to start down a path of infringing, tool up an entire factory, get a whole manufacturing and marketing system in place, and then find yourself to be enjoined. So, if an injunction is on the table, you will probably think twice about infringing. You will probably negotiate a license if it's available. You may design around if you can't get a license. There's a number of good things that come out of the idea of being afraid of an injunction. But deterrence is one of them.

 

      But if you aren't afraid of an injunction, you might have an entirely different mindset, which is, "If I just infringe now, I can pay later," which seems like a really good bargain if you're an infringer. And so, you might never get sued and infringe for free. You might get sued and get a lower royalty rate. To contradict Laura's point, there's actually some scholarship being done by Jonathan Barnett that says, no, actually in a lot of cases, when you go to court, the royalty rate set by the court is significantly lower than what would have been received during negotiation.  So you may not have to pay anything. You may have to pay a lot less. At the very least, you'll have to pay it a lot later. 

 

      And so, this is why some people call this "efficient infringement." It's actually really not a great thing. And so, my paper looks at this and also talks about, well, when would it be that you would be afraid of getting an injunction, versus when would you not be afraid of getting an injunction? So, again, to Laura's point, yeah, sure, injunctions are still issuing in 70, 80 percent of the cases. But, to Judge Holte's point, there's two particular cases in which injunctions are not being issued. 

     

      And there's empirical work on it. And there's theoretical work on it. So basically, eBay does set up buckets again. You don't get an injunction if you're a patent licensing firm. It's the 16, 20 percent, various numbers, depending on the articles you read. And you don't get an injunction if the patent that is being infringed is a standard essential patent, because of the FRAND obligation — the irreparable harm, blah, blah, blah — that the courts have decided.

 

      So, if you fall into one of those two buckets, you are unlikely to be enjoined if you infringe, which then sets up this mental mindset that it might actually be better for you to not negotiate, not take a license, and just go ahead and infringe now and pay later. And so that's what my article is largely about. And I'll stop there.

 

Hon. Ryan T Holte:  Thank you, Professor Osenga. Moving on for commentary on other folks' introductory remarks, Judge Holcomb, I'll just leave it to you to talk about whatever you want on what anybody else has brought up.

 

Hon. John W. Holcomb:  I contemplated about whether to talk about this case or not, because it sounds a little bit like I'm patting myself on the back. I really blundered into what I think was a pretty good result. So, I had this pretty complicated copyright and trade secret case involving software. The plaintiff had one customer, the defendant, and wrote software and supported it for 20 years. There was a falling out between the companies. Plaintiff sued defendant: long complicated litigation, copyright infringement claims, trade secret claims having to do with the software, contract claims. It was very messy, many other pieces, there were counterclaims. 

 

      So, finally, went to trail. It was almost a two-week trial. And the plaintiff won. Got a pretty resoundingly positive verdict from the jury, not all the damages the plaintiff wanted or was asking for, but significant. And so, I had many post-trial motions. I had equitable issues that I had to decide. I finally issued my decision in the judgment. And, in the judgment, I did grant a permanent injunction in favor of the plaintiff, which required the defendant to destroy all copies of the software. That's the simplest way to tee it up. And I gave the defendant 60 days to do that.

 

      Then there was a flurry of motions, ex parte applications on all kinds of issues. So I called the parties in to talk about all these post-judgment issues. Of course, the defendant was really not happy about the permanent injunction and had asked for a stay of that, etc. I got one of my colleagues to mediate the case. We came and we talked about what was pending. I got one of my colleagues to mediate the case. And, pretty quickly, over the course of an afternoon, the parties came to an agreement obviating the need for the permanent injunction and substituting money damages.

 

      So, again, I'd like to say that that was the design. But it just kind of happened that way. So I guess that causes me to think that permanent injunctions are okay. In a patent case, follow the eBay factors. In a trade secret case, follow the DTSA and the UTSA. And, when it's appropriate, issue the permanent injunction. Because there certainly can be post-judgment discussions and remedies that are agreed to, resolutions that are agreed to between the parties.

 

Hon. Ryan T Holte:  Thank you, Judge Holcomb. So, with that, we have a little bit less than 30 minutes left. I'll open things up to the crowd. I'll also open things up to the panelists to share any other short commentary first. Why don't we go back and forth, if there is. So we'll go to the audience first. And, if you could, state your name and your affiliation before asking your question. Go ahead, Professor Kieff.

 

Prof. Scott Keiff:  Sure. I'm Scott Kieff. I'm a law professor here in town at GW. I'm just curious, Laura Sheridan, if you could maybe amplify a little bit more. Are you trying to frame your conversation as an insight, or an empirical claim about how kind of pernicious the error rate and the intangible asset market of patents really is? And I'm trying to kind of get some context around that. So, for example, for a company like Google, you depend upon a lot of intangible assets: ads, personal privacy, software. 

 

      Are the error rates in those assets fundamentally powerfully lower? You don't patch. You don't offer to sell me the fridge you know I already bought. Are you claiming -- I'm a unique customer. I get a lot of bad ads. But most of the ads are really good. Is it an empirical claim? Or is it an insight?  So, when the stock market crashed, should we have stopped enforcing property rights in equity instruments? When the mortgage market crashed, should we have stopped enforcing property rights in the contingent liens? 

 

      When the debt market crashed, was President Biden mistaken in choosing to resort to emergency authority to not enforce student loans?  Because, after all, these are intangible assets, written instruments that are either, l guess, way more or less error-prone than patents. And he could have just simply said, "By the way, don't pay those, no injunctions." Are the property right insights in those other intangible markets different or the same? Or is it an empirical claim? Thanks.

 

Laura Sheridan:  So, I think, here, what is really important, and the way I kind of think about this issue, is rights and remedies. And we, of course, have the patent right, created by statute by Congress. And so, that is the patent right. And I have said, in my opening remarks, it's not a traditional property right. It is a public franchise, consistent with what Justice Thomas said in Oil States.  And then you have the remedies. And the remedies for infringement of that right have to follow the principles of equity. And that's eBay.

 

      So, there's no suggestion here that you are ignoring the rights, or not saying that those are, in fact, rights. It's just that the principles of equity apply to them. The point around error rate — and I think you might be referring to my factual discussion of what happens in our patent system — that's really just to understand the landscape of patents, in general. And, frankly, if we want to have the analogy where patents are like land — which, I think, legally, the courts have said they're not — but if we want that to be more true, then we need to get the patent system moving in that direction.

 

      Because you can't have a 50 percent error rate and analogize that right to a traditional property right like land. I really do feel like we should be working to move in that direction. That's a different policy conversation. That's "What is the agency doing, and how can it improve and bring down that error rate?" Because, frankly, we have 65,000 patents. And I want the error rate to come down for the reliability of those too, for that investment. But that is a different conversation than yes or no to eBay. It's "What should we be doing to make sure that error rate goes down?"

 

Hon. Ryan T Holte:  Thank you. Any other notes on that from the panelists?

 

Laurie Self:  Can I just?

 

Hon. Ryan T Holte:  Yep.

 

Laurie Self:  Look, I think this sort of age-old criticism of patents — that because there's the possibility of human error, they are not entitled to treatment as a property right — I think that is a fundamental misunderstanding of how property rights were envisioned by our constitutional founders. With all due respect to Justice Thomas, I think he got it wrong in the Oil States case. I think it was a misstatement of long-standing precedent, in terms of the treatment of patent rights.

 

      And, look, let's face it, if you look at the opportunities to challenge the validity of a patent now, through the courts, through the PTAB system, I would argue that by the time a patent reaches a judgment of validity and infringement, it has gone through so much of a crucible of survival that it is as close to bulletproof as any other form of asset we can imagine in our economy. So this notion that because there's the potential for human error in the prosecution system that somehow injunctions are inappropriate, or treatment as a property right is inappropriate, I don't think that's defensible.

 

Hon. Ryan T Holte:  Any other comments from the panelists? No? All right. Next question from the audience.  State your name and affiliation, please.

 

Ben Slivka:  Ben Slivka, retired monopolist. I worked at IBM, Microsoft and Amazon. So I'm going to ask about software patents. And, full disclosure, I was an engineer on MS.6. We got served for patent infringement, and trademarks got involved. And I later got involved in a suit with copyrights at Microsoft. So I've had in-courtroom experience on these things. So, I've got 20 years of experience investing in startup companies. And we're talking about innovation here.

 

      And the biotech firm's patents are super important, because it takes an incredibly long time to create and validate that work. The software companies, on the other hand, none of my software companies have any patents. And so, I wonder about software patents. And we didn't used to be able to patent software. That changed, I think, in the '80s. And I wonder if we should, once again, stop patenting software.

 

Laurie Self:  So, I want Laura to have an opportunity to speak. But I would just -- look, there's no question that different types of companies rely on different types of intellectual property. Some don't rely on intellectual property at all. Again, I think you really have to look at the business model of the company, how it generates revenue, to what extent it relies on patents to support long-term investment in R&D, and to commercialize that R&D. So we could have a day-long discussion on the different roles, the different types of intellectual property, including open-source.

 

      The one thing I would say about this notion of "Let's just preclude patenting for software" is that, in our sector, the semiconductor cellular sector, there is no bright line between hardware and software any longer. And that is true in the biotech sector. I would argue it's true in probably most technological sectors. You are seeing this sort of massive convergence between what we think about as traditional software development and hardware development in other forms of technological development. So, I just don't think that line exists in a clean way. So that's the only comment I would make there.

 

Laura Sheridan: And I'd strongly agree with that. I was going to make the same point around it's unclear what a software patent would even be today. And I think so much of what we are focused on in patenting that might kind of be in that vein is AI-related. And those are tremendously important. We have one of the fundamental transformer patents in the space. And we view that as an advantage and something that's a good thing to do. So, I think there's been a shift, especially with AI, quantum computing, and 5G, and this real focus on the high-tech sector and the realization that patents are important.

 

      They're important, also, for doing deals with your competitors. You want to enter into cross-licensing arrangements that you clear the risk of their portfolio while they give you fair value for yours, based on its relevance to their product. So, I hear discussion of that. But I think it's one of those things that's more theoretical. And then, when the rubber meets the road, nobody actually wants to do that.

 

Ben Slivka:  [inaudible 01:22:49]

 

Laurie Self:  Exactly.

 

Hon. Ryan T Holte:  Are there comments down there? All right, next question. And remember to state your name and affiliation.

 

Bill Wichterman:  Bill Wichterman at Covington & Burling. I'll give a question to Professor Osenga.

 

Prof. Kristen Jakobsen Osenga:  Not about copyright or trade secrets.

 

Bill Wichterman:  No, not that. I'm sorry.

 

Prof. Kristen Jakobsen Osenga:  Good. Okay, I'm ready.

 

Bill Wichterman:  So, there's been a suggestion — I think, actually, Laura.  I don't know if Judge Holcomb as well — that there's something of lesser value about NPE's patents than others.  And I want to argue with that. Because I think that, first of all, there's great NPEs in history, like Thomas Edison and others. I think it's a wonderful business model that we should be able to differentiate in an economy, rather than we just have everybody thinking things up and making them. And heaven knows how many inventors would be terrible at making things or setting up a distribution system. But they're great at inventing.

 

      That should be, I think, a sign of a maturing economy. But if we've devalued NPEs, the patents associated with NPEs, I want to suggest that that has an upstream impact on investment. Because investment is what provides nourishment for the whole innovation system. I actually am an angel investor on the side. I fully assume that 50 percent of my investments will go to zero. We are often NPEs, where you have a model of hoping to be bought up, purchased by somebody. If, suddenly, that's not available, and the same remedies are not available for infringement, that's going to have an impact on investment. And I'd love to have you just speak to that a little bit, Professor.

 

Prof. Kristen Jakobsen Osenga:  Okay. I can do that. As might be a trend, I actually don't want to call them NPEs. I would like to call them patent licensing firms. Because I think that's what they are. Let's not make it a derogatory thing. They do a good thing for the economy. They provide liquidity in a lot of different situations. You brought up maybe there's a good inventor but a bad marketer. But there's also companies that fail part way through because of -- I've actually written papers on this. So I could direct you to my papers on this.

 

      The way we're thinking about NPEs, especially when we're trying to say they shouldn't be entitled to injunctive relief, is treating them as a monolith when they are so very, very different. And there's all kinds of different patent licensing firms. And there's lots of reasons why people get into patent licensing. So we shouldn't treat them that way. But then, even putting that aside, the idea is that they do provide patent liquidity. They do provide markets, which is good.

 

      And then, the last piece, I will just highlight some future research of mine that's coming out, hopefully soon, not really my research, an essay written on somebody else's research, that what we're seeing in the post-eBay situation, at least, according to some studies, is an increase in non-exclusive licensing over exclusive licensing, which, again, really affects the value of the licenses. So, it's not just about whether or not we give injunctions to patent licensing firms or not. But all patents are now subject to devaluing when injunctive relief isn't available because it's affecting the negotiation in the market for all patents.

 

Hon. Ryan T Holte:  Thank you, Professor Osenga. Any other comments on this side of the table? All right, next question. State your name and affiliation, please.

 

Questioner 4:  Thank you for the panel. Judges, professors, thank you. Please forgive my ignorance. I am not a law expert at all.  My name is [inaudible 01:12:5726:30]. I'm CTO and co-founder of a startup called Flexy (sp). So, I'm no Amazon or anything. And I don't come from the U.S. I come from overseas. Our startup is based in the U.K. And, first, I'm really happy to see there are investors in the room.  We'll definitely have a chat with you later.

 

Hon. Ryan T Holte:  Welcome.

 

Questioner 4:  Thank you very much. And after a couple of exchanges with my patent attorney over the phone to relay what you were saying on the panel, and because it will concern us later, at the dawn of writing our fourth patent, I was wondering why it was pretty hard for non-American companies to get an injunction on an American company.

 

      And I was wondering if you believe, or you see, that there is some, maybe, protectionism over American companies and their patents, coming from abroad. Because the whole theme of this panel is promoting the market, promoting innovation for companies, maybe, inside the U.S. How are you seeing the situation from outside, and coming to get an infringement or an injunction on an American company?  Thank you.

 

Hon. Ryan T Holte:  Thank you. Any commentary on international protection with foreign companies?

 

Laurie Self:  I was wondering if the judges on the panel had any experience. Look, I would just say, I don't have direct experience. I would just say, as somebody who has worked on intellectual property policy issues across the world, it is a fundamental principle of the U.S intellectual property rights system rule of law that there is no discrimination based on the nationality of the owner of the right.

 

      To me, that is a really foundational principle. And if we start to deviate from that — and we have seen instances in other countries where you do see discriminatory practices — then I think that would be hugely damaging, in terms of the integrity and credibility of our system of intellectual property. So that's more of a policy position, as opposed to real-world experience. But, like I said, I think it's a fundamental precept of our system.

 

Questioner 4:  So how would you be able to explain the discrepancy in getting a judgment?  I would have to check, but --

 

Hon. Ryan T Holte:  We've got to have you on the microphone.

 

Laurie Self:  I was just going to say I haven't seen any data that sort of distinguishes between nationality. But it's an interesting question. I just haven't seen any data on the point.

 

Hon. Ryan T Holte:  Thank you.

 

Laurie Self:  I don't know.  Kristen, have you?

 

Prof. Kristen Jakobsen Osenga:  No.

 

Hon. Ryan T Holte:  Any other comments on that?  All right.  Go ahead.

 

Hon. John W. Holcomb:  Well, one quick comment. Now, this isn't necessarily directly responsive to your question, because you asked about patents. But I have seen, in the trade secret context, a greater willingness of a court to issue an injunction to prevent the dissemination of the trade secret internationally, sometimes, really depending on the nationality of the defendant. Because they're just a concern that once the cat's out of the bag, you can't get him back in the bag.  That's the wrong metaphor. But you know what I mean.

 

Questioner 4:  [inaudible 01:29:50]

 

Hon. John W. Holcomb:  [Laughter] Yeah. So, I think that is a concern, at least from the trade secret context, because trade secrets are so fundamentally different from patent rights. And patent rights, you necessarily — at least you're supposed to — disclose everything about the invention so that any person of ordinary skill in the art can make and practice the claimed invention. Trade secrets is just the opposite. It's necessarily something, a formula, a process, that's not generally known. So, I have seen injunctions in international trade secret cases more readily granted, because of that concern.

 

Hon. Ryan T Holte:  Thank you. So that brings up a question that we were going to have, I think, for all panelists, related to the growth in trade secrets and the strength in enforcing trade secrets. Is there any other commentary from the panelists on observations of a move towards enforcing innovation through trade secrets, and the likelihood of being able to receive equitable remedies in trade secret enforcement, as compared to patents?

 

Laurie Self:  I don't have a specific response to the enforceability question. I would just say that, just to build on the Judge's comments, trade secrets play a fundamentally different role than patents in our innovation economy. Patents are meant to not only incentivize research and development, but to enable follow-on innovation and to enable collaboration and building of commercial markets and sectors, and, to Bill's point, specialization.

 

      That is not, I will say, not easily achievable with trade secrets. I'm not even sure if it is achievable because, inherently, a trade secret is meant to protect the competitive and economic position of a particular company. And, obviously, it has to be kept secret. And I have heard certain people speculate, well, the patent system is broken, but you always have trade secrets. And, in our sector, which is built on systems-wide global communications platforms, you would see a collapse of that kind of global framework if you were having to revert to trade secrets. So, for what that's worth.

 

Hon. Ryan T Holte:  Thank you. Next question. And remember to state your name and affiliation, please.

 

Cole:  Hi everyone. Thank you for being here this afternoon. My name's Cole. I'm a law clerk. I'm down on the Fifth Circuit. I had a question relating to Judge Holcomb's point about judicial resources. And I've not been affiliated with the judiciary for very long. But I've already definitely seen kind of an incentive for trying to avoid actions that would, say, take one step forward and the three steps back, with respect to actually terminating the dispute, as opposed to granting an injunction and then having a flurry of post-relief actions.

 

      And so, to the extent that we think judicial resources would be a problem here, and also to the extent where, potentially, we're concerned about uniformity in how eBay is applied, I would love to hear the panel's thoughts on something that has been talked about in the academic literature about the creation of a unified trial court — obviously, we have the federal circuit — but a unified trial court for patent matters. And, of course, there would be Seventh Amendment logistical problems with juries. But it is something our country has done with the Court of International Trade. And it's something Europe did quite recently with the Unified Patent Court. And I'd love to hear the panel's thoughts on that.

 

Hon. John W. Holcomb:  Just real quick, it's a fascinating idea. I think we've got people here who clerked on the federal circuit. The federal circuit was created in the early '80s --

 

Prof. Kristen Jakobsen Osenga:  1982.

 

Hon. John W. Holcomb:  -- in 1982, for, I don't know if, precisely, this reason, but to make sure there's uniformity in the patent laws. And it's always fascinated me, as somebody who practiced in the bankruptcy area, and then later, in the patent area, how, in bankruptcy law, we have dedicated bankruptcy courts at the so-called trial level. And then the appeals go to the general regional court. And in patent law it's the exact opposite. I'm not saying that's good or bad, or right or wrong. But it's fascinating. So, you raise a great question. I have no idea where we are, in terms of potential legislation to address that.

 

Hon. Ryan T Holte:  I support national courts, coming from one, at least.

 

Laurie Self:  I mean, as a political matter, I can't imagine there would be a path forward for that. Whether it's a good idea or not, I just don't see a political path.

 

Hon. Ryan T Holte:  Thank you. Next question. Name and affiliation too, please.

 

John Farmer:  Hi, I'm John Farmer. And I'm with a small IP boutique in Richmond, Virginia. Let's talk about attorney's fees for prevailing parties. I believe that I'm correct in saying, under patent copyright and trademark, they each have an exceptional case standard. And so, you don't go into the case knowing that you're going to be able to cover your attorney's fees. And I can tell you that, especially with many of these small and mid-sized IP-rights owners, especially in the copyright and trademark space, that's really the game. 

 

      You talk to your client. They say, "What's it going to cost?" And you tell them. And you say "It's probably an investment in your IP because your chances of recovering your attorney's fees are not great."  And then they just say, "I'm sorry. It's just not worth it. I can't do it." And, of course, that flows backwards to the incentive to create those strong marks and those copyrights in the first place. Because if they can be infringed willy-nilly for free, then what's their value? 

 

      So, I think you're talking about legislation today because you're talking about whether the patent law ought to be amended to make the presumption of the availability of an injunction available, if I understand you correctly. And, as Professor Osenga pointed out, that's already been done in the trademark area. So, if we're talking about legislation, and we really want to encourage innovation, would you support making it mandatory that prevailing parties in IP cases recover attorney's fees? Or, if not mandatory, maybe there is a strong presumption of the recovery of attorney's fees. You can see trade-offs there, of course. But if you want to incentivize creation, that seems to be a very big practical hurdle.

 

Hon. John W. Holcomb:  One quick comment. I'm sure that my co-panelists have thoughts on this. In the copyright context for a copyright owner plaintiff who has registered the copyright before the alleged infringement began, there is supposed to be — automatic is probably too strong of a word — but presumption in favor of attorney's fees in favor of the prevailing party, even if it's the defendant who's the prevailing party. You're right. There's an exceptional case standard in the patent world, and something similar, I don't know that it's precisely called that, in the trade secret world. But I just wanted to make that one observation about copyright cases.

 

Laura Sheridan:  Maybe a more general observation too. This topic does come up. And I think it's more broadly coming up as sort of the overall expense of litigation, which you mentioned. And I think there was a push, maybe about eight years or so ago, to kind of look at the different way litigation gets very expensive and how some of those different aspects, like discovery and Markman, where you're having these very expensive moments in the case, and how can you phase them to kind of better manage costs. 

 

      That didn't go anywhere. There was a lot of conversation. And it didn't end up, of course, with legislation. But I feel like, from a policy standpoint, that's more where the conversation goes, just given our legal tradition being so different from one of paying the other side's fees based on the outcome of the case. It tends to be more just how can we streamline the process itself so it's cheaper for both sides?

 

Hon. Ryan T. Holte:  All right, next question.  State name and affiliation.

 

Marc Scolnick:  Marc Scolnick. I'm in private practice in New York City. I'm not an IP lawyer. But I was a student of Judge Holte when he was a professor at Akron. I never thought I'd be asking an IP question before a judge. But here we go. It's more of a practical question, going off of the ideas for a statute or legislation or fee-shifting burden. It sounds like, in my practice in New York, there's the Southern District of New York's standing order for FLSA cases to have compulsory mediation upon the filing of the case. It's actually ordered by the magistrate judge, once it's assigned. 

 

      When I was hearing everybody talk about how everybody seems to think that mediation is something to at least consider, if not a good idea. For the districts that have a lot of cases filed — Judge's district, Eastern District of Texas — could the judges — you don't require legislation for this; the court just has to make its own rules within that district — knowing that these cases are going to be filed, set up some sort of program similar to that, anticipating that injunctions are going to be filed, that these motions are going to be argued?

 

      There are several in the Fair Labor Standards Act world. A lot of lawyers in New York, who are happy to be the mediators, they're certified by the court in order to handle those cases. I'm sure there's a lot of patent litigators, semi-retired or of counsel, who would be interested. And, since COVID, a lot of these are being done virtually. And so, the parties don't even have to meet at a specific location, and the mediations can be done with multiple parties. So, I just thought about bringing that up and seeing what the panelists thought about it. Because when I was hearing everybody talk about mediation, it sounded similar to what New York's done with labor cases, because there's just so many filed. Thank you.

 

Hon. Ryan T Holte:  Thank you Marc. And I'll also give a shoutout to my fall intellectual property class tuning in online on this Saturday, so I appreciate that.  Comments from the panelists on the mediation question?

 

Hon. John W. Holcomb:  Sure. I'll start quickly. My court requires mediation in all civil cases. For a patent case, for an IP case, it's up to the judge precisely when that happens. The judge will require one of three paths. One is a magistrate judge in the court will mediate the case. Second is you go to private mediation, pick who you want, and pay him or her. The third is we have an ADR panel in the Central District of trained mediators. I used to serve on the panel when I was a lawyer.

 

      And, of course, of the, I don't know, 50 or more panel mediators, many of them had IP experience. And that's free. For your first half-day, it's free. So that is encouraged in my court. Rule 16 requires, suggests strongly, to district judges at every scheduling conference, status conference, talk about mediation and the prospects of settlement. And then you've got Rule 1 of the federal rules, which calls on the court and all parties to seek a resolution that is just, speedy, and inexpensive. So, all of those things counsel toward mediation and seeking resolution outside of full adjudication.

 

Hon. Ryan T Holte:  Any other comments? No? All right. One more question. Maybe one more, after this.  Go ahead. State your name and affiliation.

 

Keaton Blazer:  Hi. Keaton Blazer. I'm a Berkeley law student. Judge Holcomb, I was reflecting on your remark that there's some hesitation to impose an injunction out of fear of potentially a lot more work down the line. That got me thinking about venue shopping and how you can select your venue with the goal of obtaining that injunctive relief. Thinking about the ITC, of course, that's pretty much the only remedy available, is that injunction. 

 

      And I was wondering if the panel had any thoughts relating to a potential alignment of the standards under which that sort of relief would be granted. I know, of course, that there are standards relating to domestic economic activity, and things like that, in ITC. But it strikes me as somewhat different from what is there at a district court, and would it be possible to align that, I guess? Would it be politically feasible, perhaps, a less ambitious version of the unified patent court? Thank you.

 

Laura Sheridan:  I can tackle -- that's a great question. I think there has been talk of that kind of alignment between ITC and the district court. I think that would be a very, very, very hard thing to do, although I think a lot of folks feel strongly that that would make sense. I think what we experience, from an ITC standpoint is, because it has the injunctive relief, it is part of pretty much every litigation campaign that we face.

 

      So, even though you have a district court case filed against you, you will have an ITC case for that very reason, for the leverage that it provides. So, I think a lot of the talk about alignment is because of that very issue, where you see a sort of duplicative litigation between the district court and the ITC that, frankly, is just kind of wasteful. But I think, politically, that would be a very, very difficult thing to do.

 

Laurie Self:  Can I just also say — and maybe this is sort of self-evident to you. — but the statutory construct of the ITC and eBay are fundamentally different. There are no monetary damages at the ITC. So, Laura's right. Of course, this has been a longstanding kind of policy discussion in Washington. But, to me, I'm not even sure how you would import eBay into the ITC without fundamentally changing ITC rules, remedies, etc. I think it's also worth noting that if you look at the number of cases brought in the ITC, it's still very, very small, relative to district court litigation.

 

      And it's obviously an in rem proceeding. It's meant to address situations where you have infringing products entering the market, and where there is not kind of an efficient mechanism to address that situation through district court litigation. So, I just think you have to be very careful about conflating two very different systems and potentially weakening an ITC that performs a very important role. 

 

Hon. Ryan T Holte:  Thank you. So, I think we're two minutes over. But, my retired colleague, Chief Judge Braden, a quick question?

 

Chief Judge Braden:  I don't have a question. But I have a comment on Miss Sheridan, which is -- and there's not been any differentiation on the panel between preliminary injunction standards and permanent injunction standards. It seems to be blended. No small company is going to request a preliminary injunction unless they really think that they have a valid patent. Because of the federal rules, you have to post a bond. And you have to post a bond to cover any -- in the event something's wrong. 

 

      If people have faith enough to approach a federal district court judge to ask for a preliminary injunction, the judge really needs to take a look at that quite seriously. Because they're saying "Trust me because I'm putting up all of my capital, basically, to protect my intellectual property protection." So that's one important thing. The second thing, basically, is Judge Holte's article really ought to be required reading in the baby judge school, because --

 

Hon. Ryan T Holte:  This is why I gave closing comments to Chief Judge Braden.

 

Laurie Self:  Well done.

 

Chief Judge Braden:   — and if you call this number now, you get that in a statement. I sure hope so — because the district court judges have the power to continue to issue injunctions. And, particularly, they need to have that power to stop efficient infringement, which is a rational and a perfectly valid business strategy. I don't fault the companies that are doing it for doing it, because they've been allowed to do it. It's the federal district court judges that are required to stop that. And they have that authority now. We probably could get legislation, but we don't need it. You have that power. Use it. 

 

Hon. Ryan T Holte:  Thank you, Chief Judge Braden. Thank you to the panelists. I also want to say, as we close with a round of applause, to remind everyone of what Judge Holcomb had mentioned about today is Veteran's Day. We thank Judge Holcomb for his service. I'll also note that all of his kids or kids' spouses are currently active duty. 

 

Laurie Self:  That's amazing.

 

Hon. Ryan T. Holte:  We appreciate their service. We appreciate the service of all those in the room and those who are not here. And, with that, let's give a round of applause for our veterans and panelists. And have a great afternoon. 

 

 

12:30 p.m. - 2:30 p.m.
15th Annual Rosenkranz Debate & Luncheon

2023 National Lawyers Convention

Grand Ballroom
The Mayflower Hotel
1127 Connecticut Avenue NW
Washington, DC 20006

Share

Event Video

Listen & Download

Description

The 2023 National Lawyers Convention will take place November 9-11, 2023 at the Mayflower Hotel in Washington, DC. The topic of the conference is "Originalism on the Ground." The final day of the conference will feature the fifteenth annual Rosenkranz Debate.

RESOLVED: States Can Constitutionally Regulate the Content Moderation Policies of Facebook and Twitter

Featuring:

  • Prof. Richard Epstein, Laurence A. Tisch Professor of Law and Director, Classical Liberal Institute, New York University School of Law
  • Mr. Clark Neily, Senior Vice President for Legal Studies, Cato Institute
  • Moderator: Prof. Nicholas Quinn Rosenkranz, Professor of Law, Georgetown School of Law

Speakers

Event Transcript

Eugene Meyer:  Good afternoon. Good afternoon. I'm Gene Meyer, president of The Society, and I very briefly want to welcome you to our Annual Rosenkrantz Debate and express our gratitude to the Rosenkranz Foundation for supporting this event for more than the past decade. We love having this centerpiece on Saturday.

 

      Actually, Nick and I were just talking at the end -- Michelle were just talking about this as an intellectually sharp, one-on-one debate between two highly prominent legal theorists. It's been quite a distinguished series and been a lot of fun to have. And without further ado, I want to turn it over to Nick Rosenkranz to moderate it. Nick. 

 

Prof. Nicholas Rosenkranz:  Thank you so much. Thanks very much, and thanks for choosing to spend this beautiful Saturday with us. So our resolution today is "Resolved: States Can Constitutionally Regulate the Content Moderation Policies of Facebook and Twitter." As you may know, Texas and Florida have recently purported to do just that, creating a circuit split between the Fifth and Eleventh Circuits, and the Supreme Court has granted certiorari.

 

      You'll note that we didn't cite either the case or the statutes in the resolution. The debaters are not bound to get stuck in the weeds of those particular statutory schemes; they're going to debate the proposition more generally, I believe. This is our favorite sort of debate because it, in addition to being an enormously important and alive issue, actually seems to split The Federalist Society. It's a bit of an intramural debate for us. Indeed, as you'll see, even the libertarian wing of The Federalist Society doesn't quite agree on this one.

 

      Next, I'm going to introduce our debaters. I'm going to be very brief. You all have much longer bios in your programs and online. Arguing the pro side is the great Richard Epstein to my left. He is the Laurence A. Tisch Professor of Law as well as the director of the Classical Liberal Institute at NYU, where he generously made me a fellow.

 

      He's the Peter and Kirstin Bedford Senior Fellow at the Hoover Institution and the James Parker Hall Distinguished Service Professor of Law Emeritus and Senior Lecturer at the University of Chicago. I last introduced Richard to the Georgetown chapter of The Federalist Society, I think, about 12 or 13 years ago when he was given a Lifetime Achievement Award. I don't actually understand how this is possible, but it seems that he has achieved more since his Lifetime Achievement Award than I have in my entire life.

 

      Richard, in effect, accepted this invitation some 25 years ago. I was a student at Yale, and our Yale chapter invited Richard to speak, but then we later decided it would be more fun if he would perhaps do a debate. So we called him and asked, would you consider doing a debate instead of speech for this event, maybe with a Yale professor or something? And Richard said, "I will debate anyone at any time on any topic." So he may not have known he was making a lifelong pledge at that moment, but as you see, we are still putting that to the test, and he has never disappointed.

 

      Arguing the con side, to my right, we have my colleague, Clark Neily, Senior Vice President for Legal Studies at the Cato Institute. He's the author of "Terms of Engagement: How Our Court Should Enforce the Promise of Limited Government," widely published in law reviews and op ed pages. He also served as co-counsel in the Seminole Second Amendment case, D.C. v. Heller, and he also teaches as an adjunct at University of Texas School of Law.

 

      So our format as usual will be that each of our speakers will have ten minutes to make their opening remarks and then seven minutes for reply or rebuttal, followed by a more informal give and take, during which I'll try to prompt them to engage with the most difficult parts of the other side's arguments. And then, time permitting, we will open up for audience questions. So arguing that States Can Constitutionally Regulate the Content Moderation Policies of Facebook and Twitter, I give you Richard Epstein.

 

Prof. Richard Epstein:  Thank you very much. Can you hear me, all? I can't see any of you because the lights are blinding, but hello to all of my friends and fellow Roman lawyers. Because, of course, this is a topic which goes a little bit beyond that, but I'm in the very odd position of being somewhat doubtful in my own mind about the abstract principles but having little doubt about the way in which I think this case, what ultimately has come out.

 

      And so the question then is, why is it is, generally, when you have something like the First Amendment, which seems to say categorically, "Congress may pass no law abridging the freedom of speech," I'm coming here as somebody who's saying that I think some degree of regulation with respect to speech is necessary.

 

      I think the first thing that one has to do is to abuse themselves to the proposition that there's anything about the First Amendment which is absolute in terms of the prohibition that it imposes. We also believe in freedom of action and freedom of contract, but every time you're talking about freedom, there are always going to be serious limitations with respect to the way in which it works.

 

      And one of the things that you have to worry about is, of course, assault, defamation, and fraud, but something else that's also on the list is monopoly or things that are close enough to monopoly that you think they may give you some concern as to what is going to happen. And the basic argument here is kind of an anti-trust like argument, which says that there's one or a very small number of people who can engage in certain kinds of activities. If they decide to exclude you, there's going to be no ready competitive alternative which is going to be able to pick up the slot.

     

      And so, essentially, the question you start to deal with on regulation of common carriers and so forth is, how do these alternatives appear? As an abstract matter, most people would think—and I would agree with them—that would seem pretty obvious for somebody to get into the kind of business that Twitter and Amazon and YouTube and so forth engage in, but it turns out, the theory is not borne out in practice; what we see in practice is exactly the opposite, that three dominant companies, or maybe four, are sitting there in the particular market, each with a high market share, each of which purports to say that we can regulate the kind of content that we're talking about.

 

      So if you start looking back to the traditional common carrier, the issues are actually, in many ways, more complicated than they are here because, with the traditional common carrier, you must take all comers, but you're allowed to charge them money, and you can charge monies at different levels, depending upon the cost of service for different kinds of groups.

 

      In this particular case, we're not worried about any of those complications. It's more or less positive that what you can post, you can post for free, and the issue is not the question of how you're going to charge what's going on but how it is you, quote unquote, to use the most generous term in this debate, "moderate" the content that they have, or they can monitor it, as including the right to totally exclude.

 

      Now, if you go back to the physical common carriers and ask this first question, it turns out when you say there's a uniform duty of service at fair and reasonable prices, like everything else in the world, it is subject to an important exception, and this is reflected in the Communications Act and so forth; namely, you don't have to take people on the train who are going to scream, they're going to yell, be abusive, be exhibitionist, and so forth.

 

      Essentially, what you can do is engage in the kinds of situations where you regulate against that form of misbehavior, and it certainly seems to me to be appropriate that, when you're starting to talk about the internet, you could do so as well. But if you start looking at what the kinds of things that count here are, it turns out it's a very dubious list indeed. All of the initial things on the list are, of course, gold letter things for regulation, harassment, violence, abuse, screaming, whatever it is, but they all say content which is otherwise objectionable.

 

      And so the question then is, objectionable to whom and what? And if you start looking at the command that comes on the Twitter situation, it turns out that they give a very broad definition of the kinds of things that they should be able to eliminate, and that includes any kind of public speech that undermines the confidence in our public institution or our electoral process. The last phrases basically said, "Don't you dare defend Donald Trump on our network because we all know he's guilty as charged."

 

      But the first part is, in many ways, even more obnoxious in terms of the way in which it goes, because I will tell you that I am a veteran of being silenced by the media; in this case, YouTube. And why was I silenced? Because I thought that it was important to say that the situation associated with COVID is sufficiently serious; that if you, in fact, adopt a very dangerous vaccine, the modified RNA vaccine, you are likely to cause many more deaths than you do the other way around; and if you follow the more cautious protocol of doing nothing in the abstract but using something like ivermectin and HCQ, when things emerge, it will be vastly safer than otherwise.

 

      This was thought to be against the public interest, and the reason it was thought to be so is that the recommendation that I gave is probably a million times safer than the course of action that the government recommended. And for my particular pains, Berkeley posted this thing on the website somewhere, and then they took it off and said, "We're sure you agree with us because we're only interested in the public safety." This is the kind of intellectual claptrap that takes place on all of these kinds of sites.

 

      And so the question is, given the fact that they have this sort of market dominance under the circumstances, is one prepared to say, "Look, in the name of free speech, what you're really trying to do is to treat as objectionable anything that disagrees with the overt and rather blatant political preferences of the particular party who runs the network in question."

 

      And so I think, in effect, even in the simplest case, you start to think, "Well, maybe something is deeply wrong with what is going on if they can't distinguish between a Richard Epstein special on the one hand and pornographic content on the other." I'm able to do so. I know which is more dangerous to the established authorities. Pornography never upsets the power, but criticism, it turns out, really does.

 

      And so you're seeing here, in effect, that kind of suppression that starts to take place. And so if you think, in effect, these things are monopoly-like parties, you're going to do it. So what are you going to start looking at? Well, the first thing you're going to start to look at is, how does this compare with other kinds of businesses.

 

      And the way I like to put it, in very simple fashion, we know that network industries are extremely different, say, from employment contract, because the last time I went online, I did not have to present my resume to somebody in order to post. And when I took my plane flight, I did not have to present my resume to get a ticket.

 

      On the other hand, when you're taking a job, it is not done on a first-come, first-serve basis. And so the reason why we are reasonably confident that we could take people in these network industries is what is demanded of the individual is sufficiently small, that pretty much, you could take on anybody who could pay the freight, and then at the back end, if there's some kinds of problems, figure out how you can eliminate those people by having a strong-arm person take them off the airplane when they start to misbehave.

 

      And at this particular point, there are many airlines. And there's a great question as to how many does it take to make a monopoly and so forth, but the intuition in many of these industries is, so long as you have that particular character, it doesn't matter whether there are two or three. The cost of having [inaudible 00:13:18] exclusions in these cases is going to be very, very high because serious information content will not be presented, or whereas the dangers of abuse and throwing people off is something that you can genuinely control.

 

      It is sometimes said by the networks when they do all of their stuff, "Well, we have a billion people that we have to probe all the time. How can you possibly supervise that?" I said, "Why don't you spend your time doing better things than chasing after me? What you have to do is, you have to find me, hunt me down, look at the thing, and then send me one of these dismissive letters saying, "Your content is too dangerous. I'm sure you're relieved about the fact that we've taken it off the website."

 

      And the behavior at the individual level, it's scandalous. And then what's going to happen? And Clark is much more learned than I, and he will tell you, scandalous things are often perfectly legitimate when they come under the First Amendment because that's what we want to do.

 

      And these guys is speakers like anybody else, and sometimes they're just platforms, and sometimes they do editorial content. But whatever it is, unless they're engaged in something like defamation, which they were in this case, we're going to let this thing go, more or less, as it sees fit.

 

      Well, that's the case that I'm talking about, which is the hard case. There's also an easy case on this situation because what we have to do is to understand full well that, when we're doing these kinds of things, we have another problem that we have to face, which is namely the problem of collusion.

 

      And there are two sorts of collusion here. One, I think, that is now established beyond a reasonable doubt that all the carriers have common policies agreed upon in some kind of fairly informal, but nonetheless valid way. And if you have those kinds of policies, you've now got an antitrust violation, and the collective refusal to deal is at least as important here as it is with respect to chickens and tomatoes.

 

      And the other thing, which has also become frightfully clear under this case, is the government is not sitting there as a neutral arbiter, trying to make sure that they enforce the rules of the road without doing anything to upset the nature of the content that's involved. And so what is it that they do? They do all sorts of terrible things.

 

      And essentially, they strong-arm people and they coerce people and they bribe people and so forth. And so, if you follow the kinds of stuff that took place in a case like Missouri v. Biden, you see that you have the government full square on this. And if the state action definitions that normally apply carry over to this case, then it's no longer private action; it turns out to be state action.

 

      So the weak form of my argument—which I think is perfectly sensible, but not utterly persuasive—is that, standing alone, each of these guys are sufficiently dangerous that you want to put this kind of restriction on them, a nondiscrimination decision, and collectively, it's really worse. But the thing that you don't want to do is to subject them to securities law like regulations on disclosure of this, that, and the other thing.

 

      Philip Hamburger said, "Well, it's no different from what you see under the Securities Act." And that's exactly my point. It's not different from the kinds of abusive and crazy behaviors that you see under the Securities Act, and so what you want to do is to pick a remedy which is essentially relatively self-enforcing without any serious administrative abuse.

 

      And whereas I don't trust the state to do many things whatsoever, I do think that you can have a system of private complaints backed by public oversight to make sure that all content that is relevant to public debates can be accessed to every member of the public. Thank you. Am I on time?

 

Prof. Nicholas Rosenkranz:  Perfect.

 

Prof. Richard Epstein:  Thank you.

 

Prof. Nicholas Rosenkranz:  Arguing against the resolution, Clark Neily.

 

Clark Neily:  How many of you really thought he was going to stop at 10 minutes? Come on. I'm speechless. Let's be clear: No sane person would volunteer to debate Richard Epstein.

 

Prof. Nicholas Rosenkranz:  Or moderate.

 

Clark Neily:  And I did not volunteer; I was drafted into it. I assumed that Gene was looking for somebody smart enough to do it and stupid enough to say yes, which he obviously found. At least he offered me the opportunity to be on the right side of the resolution. I appreciate that, Gene. Josh, the answer's no. Thank you.

     

      So, look, even the torrent of Richard's erudition cannot change three immutable facts. First, social media platforms are private property. There are some countries where that doesn't matter, and we're not one of them. Second, these are not just any private companies; these are private companies in the business of speech, of facilitating it and of curating it. That means providing a particular kind of experience. And third, you simply cannot take the very large and very square peg of the social media industry and pound it into the very round hole of common carrier doctrine or monopoly theory or regulated utilities, or whatever the hole looks like when you shove those all together in some kind of soupy status Melange because it doesn't work.

 

      These platforms are the private property of those who own them, and they have a First Amendment right to determine what goes on to those platforms, what stays off of those platforms, and again, most importantly, how the material—and let's not call it material—how the speech that occupies those platforms is presented to the people who use them. And there are very good reasons for that, as we'll get into in a moment.

 

      Or we should do this. Like any good Federalist Society member, we should start with first principles. And I want to start with an illustration from something that really happened at the beginning of COVID. Like most of you, I suspect, my family and I were homebound and got some cabin fever, so we bought one of those little lending libraries. Hopefully most of you know what I'm talking about. It's this little box that you build, and then you paint it, or in my case, I let my kids paint it. Come by sometime; it's psychedelic. And then we put it up in our yard, and you put books in it, and other people put books in it.

 

      And we live in a unique location because we're just a stone's throw from the local elementary school, and about half of the kids who go to that school walk up this path next to our house. They walk right past this lending library. And you better believe that my wife and I determine what goes into that lending library and what doesn't, partly because I think some things are appropriate for those kids to see and some things are not, and partly because I think there's so incredibly stupid ideas in the world.

 

      And I don't care to have material in there about transitioning kids, for example. I don't care to have material in there about Hamas and colonization, and it doesn't go in there, and that's my choice. And if the state of Virginia came along and said, "Well, those kids are getting a very one-sided view of the world. You seem to be some kind of a libertarian. Where's Eva McKend's work? Nothing in there about the 1619 Project," and I'd say, "You're damn right there's not, and not by accident."

 

      And if they said, "Well, you're altering the public discourse in a way that we don't approve of, so you need to put those materials in there," I would tell them, "Molon labe;" come and get it. And if necessary, I would burn that lending library to the ground before I would let the state of Virginia tell me what goes in there or tell me where to put the things that are in there. "Oh, that you can't feature Richard Epstein's book, the Classical Liberal Constitution." Very good book, by the way. That's going front and center. And if they tell me it has to go in the back or it just has to go randomly with whatever other garbage they're telling me to put in there, the answer's no, and you he force me to do it, I'll take down the lending library.

 

      And that's the country we live in. Thank goodness. Yes, you can clap. Now, if it was nearly anybody else, we'd have to have a ridiculous stupid discussion about the applicability of the First Amendment, but it's Richard, so we don't. He's honest. It applies. The question is, is there a sufficiently persuasive exception to the First Amendment in this case? And it must be an extremely persuasive exception, and there isn't.

 

      Before we get to the explanation why there isn't, I want to start first with what I think purports to be Richard's strongest point, which is that there's something about the way these social media companies do business that makes them look something like a common carrier. By the way, you want to talk about disagreement among libertarians, you should check out the disagreement among people opposite us on this issue. Eugene Balak says they're not common carriers. I get the impression Philip Hamburger thinks they might be. I'm not sure where Richard is, but they're not, and let's explore why that is.

 

      Classic example of a common carrier would be a ferryboat service that takes you from here to there, perhaps also with your car. They don't particularly care who it is that goes and purchases a ticket. As long as you've got a car that will fit on the boat and you just want to go here to there, fair enough. And you don't particularly care which ferryboat service you take. You're not signing up for this one over that one because, "Oh, they've got better popcorn on Ferryboat Service A, and I have a better experience there." No, you just want to get from here to there, and that's a common carrier.

 

      At the other end of the spectrum, there's another kind of boat that takes you from here to there, and that's called a cruise ship. And they curate that experience for you. In fact, I looked up a few. Did you know that Virgin actually has a cruise ship now? Virgin Voyages. And they don't let kids on that ship, and if anybody's ever been on a cruise, you understand why. And they use that word. "We provide a curated experience."

 

      European River Cruises has a curated experience, and they have historians to tell you about what you're going to see or what you're looking at. Same thing. By the way, I didn't know the Ritz Carlton apparently has a curated cruise ship experience. I assume that involves a lot of foot massages and somebody peeling grapes for you.

 

      But these are curated experiences. It matters a great deal to you which cruise line you choose because they're providing you with different experiences. You want to be drunk for three days and graze at the buffet? That's Royal Caribbean. You want to get a look at where the Treaty of Ghent was signed, why it's significant, that's European River Cruises.

 

      And that's what social media companies provide. They don't just provide an indiscriminate lawn sprayer of content, just tick, tick, tick, tick, tick, tick, tick, tick; no, they provide a curated experience. You open up Facebook, and you know you can do that around your kid. Maybe you don't if you're not on Facebook, but trust me, you can open up Facebook around your kids. Twitter used to be safe; a little dodgier now, but they're providing different experiences.

 

      And I think Judge Newson used exactly the right verb in his opinion when he struck down the Florida law. He said, "The right verb to use here is curation." They are curating an experience. It's been said sometimes that the problem here is that these social media platforms, they're the modern town square where people come to debate and discourse. I haven't done that in a town square, have you? No, you haven't. Most of you haven't.

 

      The thing about a town square is it's a government fixture. They built it. There's a courthouse on one side. There's City Hall on the other. People show up to transact business with the government. They run into other people there. They have a conversation, but it's all government. That is not the right analogy for a social media platform. It's not a town square. It's a food court. It's a food court. You come for the cat memes. You stay for the conversation.

 

      If your local mall has a selection of foods that you don't care for—maybe you're not that into Sbarro and Arby's and you want better food—well, you go over where near where I live, Ballston Mall, and go have yourself a Little Lou's Hot Chicken. Highly encouraged, by the way; not the hottest one, but a nice spicy chicken sandwich. That's a curated experience. That's what social media platforms provide. They're not common carriers.

 

      And anybody can sign up, yes, but anybody can sign up for a FedEx account. As far as I know, anybody can sign up to be a member of The Federalist Society, but I believe you curate these experiences, right? I haven't heard anybody ranting at Judge Duncan in this room. Pretty curated experience to me. I suspect most of us prefer that experience.

 

      I don't want for anybody to treat, for example, The Federalist Society as a common carrier. There's a lot of important discourse that occurs here, and there are network effects here. My goodness, have you guys been out in the hall? Network effects. Oh, yeah. Yeah. And by the way, if you want to talk about a monopoly, as far as I know, The Federalist Society has a monopoly on the only sane conversation about legal policy.

 

      And I'm sure we can think of a lot of people who'd like to have access to that conversation for a variety of reasons, including some that would be a bit nefarious. And you know what we say to them? We say, "Thank you, no." We have a curated experience. We have a free speech right to provide that curated experience, just like social media companies do. I stand against the resolution. States cannot constitutionally moderate the content of social media companies. Thank you.

 

Prof. Nicholas Rosenkranz:  Richard, you have seven minutes.

 

Prof. Richard Epstein:  Well, it will take longer than that to espouse all of my disagreements, but let me start with just a couple of them. First of all, a lot of the world works by a battle of analogies. And on the one hand, you have these social networks with worldwide penetration and disagreement, millions of users. And it turns out, as far as my worthy opponent says, Mr. Clark Neily, that just like the little lending library he puts up on his lawn, which is visited by four people, and, of course, we know, given the difficulties of entry into this market, there are only three people in the world who thought of what he has done, there are thousands of these things.

 

      And the central point about the monopoly argument is that when they're viable alternatives that can take place, then competitive forces always outperform non-competitive forces. And so it has always been that the common carrier exception has been a permanent, durable, and grudging exception to the basic rule.

 

      But all of the examples that we see on the other side are cases where it's perfect competitive situations and where content [inaudible 01:27:57] is very important. So I said, the reason why it is that you could do easily on a common carrier is, all you have to do is to let these people post. Don't put any restrictions on there. Post your own stuff.

 

      And it turns out The Federalist Society not only has worthy competitors on the same time of the political spectrum—I'd never heard of the Cato Institute before that, but somehow or other, I suspect that it's in the same line of business as we are here—and then there are other places down the block which have rather different points of view.

 

      This is a market and information production and so forth, which is deeply competitive, and everything that Clark about it is completely true in the way in which these particular markets work. Well, then he talks about the ferry. And this is an interesting question. Suppose you have two ferries. Are they common carriers?  You have to ask that question. Suppose that there was a way that you could take a boat across the thing one way or another, or walk around it and save two miles but not more?

 

      These are all very tricky questions, but the basic intuition is you're supplying transportation on a raw basis. That's what you're doing. A cruise ship is not just simply getting you from here to there; a cruise ship is a total experience with food, cuisine, recreation, guides, tours on the land, and so forth. It's a different industry. And once it's a different industry, it's subject to different rules.

 

      And the last thing I would want to do is to have the common carrier exception carried so far and so broad and so wide that it turns out it swallows up everything. On the other hand, within the common carrier exception, the rule has always been fair, reasonable, and nondiscriminatory race and conduct. So on a common carrier, if you try to discriminate on the basis of race, given the classical situations of this, you're not allowed to do so. You are basically going to have to supply with those sorts of things.

 

      And it turns out, I'm very much opposed to the idea that you're going to have a viewpoint or racial discrimination rules with respect to fraternities, clubs, and other kinds of places. But I think in effect, unless you can see that there are two poles—a competitive pole on the one hand, and a, shall we say, monopolistic pole, on the other hand—you can't even enter into this debate. And I don't think that Clark really thinks that these structural issues matter as much as I happen to think they are, and there's at least 500 years of common-law history, on my particular side by libertarian judges, for the most part, who always recommended this.

 

      There's also another feature which I didn't mention before. They're not just taking down my content; what they're doing is they're announcing that I'm unsafe. One of the things that rather bothers me is that's an outright act of defamation, as far as I'm concerned, knowing falsehood, reckless disregard, stating those kinds of things.

 

      I don't want to sue those guys. That would only bring further attention to the nefarious deeds, but I do think that one want to be aware of the fact that, when they start excluding you and announcing that you're not fit for human consumption or vegetation, it's a much more serious thing than if they simply say, "We don't take stuff from libertarians."

 

      So what happens is they want not only to get an exemption from the common carrier rules; they also want to get an exemption from defamation rules in any form. And again, if you listen to what I said, the reason why this case is easier is because it turns out there's collusion amongst the various common carriers, and there's government support and coercion for and against them.

 

      And the state action doctrine and the antitrust law cover those cases. It's a per se offense to have a collective refusal to deal under the antitrust laws because whatever ambiguity you have about the structure of the market is simply going to disappear if it turns out that all the relevant players in the thing get together, and they make sure that you can't get on any of their particular networks.

 

      And again, the proposal that I made on this stuff is, I don't want to sue on defamation, but I want people to be well aware of this as an important anchor. But the way in which I like to think about this, as a business matter, if you can actually show a viable competitor to these four miserable companies that run this system and it has a different point of view, then I think the monopoly argument is weakened, and the competitive argument is straightened.

 

      And so I'm willing to be empirical, which Clark is not. And what my empirical element on this case is, if I see the competitors' situation emerging, what I will do is I will simply back off of anything having to do with the way in which you measure monopoly power. But at this particular point, the particular cases are very, very easy because we're not talking about the pure common carrier case in practice. What we're talking about are combinations and government restraints.

 

      And the government gets itself involved in this argument, and when you start having those things together, there has to be some counterweight. The reason I suppose that the regulation was put in terms of the states is that the federal government is so hopeless with respect to anything that it's the enemy. And it turns out I do agree with Clark with one thing: If the current administration was regulating the network for these miserable companies, I will take the companies over the government every time.

 

Prof. Nicholas Rosenkranz:  Clark, seven minutes.

 

Clark Neily:  Well, a wise man once said, "It is a fair response that rapid turnover in internet companies counsels strongly against any intervention." You won't be surprised to hear that wise man is sitting next to me up on the stage. That was July of 2022, and it was only three months later that Elon Musk purchased Twitter and completely changed the policy to that organization, invited Donald Trump to come back on the platform. He said no. Not sure why that is; probably because he's running a grift with Truth Social right now and needs to keep it capitalized.

 

      But he also reinstated Jordan Peterson and the Babylon Bee, kicked off a bunch of Antifa. Does that sound like collusion to you? By the way, did you know that Mark Zuckerberg and Elon Musk are still talking about whether they're going to have a cage fight? Maybe they can talk about collusion in the locker room when they're showering. I don't think so.

 

      I don't think there's any collusion between Boomer book and, whatever it is, the Bronze Age pirate, Elon Musk. Those two platforms are different. They're a lot different. And whether or not Elon Musk is going to be able to get Twitter back in the black, who knows? But he's changed the policies of that platform, and the content is much different than it used to be.

 

      And both credible and not credible people have abandoned Twitter as a result, and who knows what's going to happen with Bluesky or Mastodon or Tumblr? I don't know. That's not my thing. But then we've got other social media that's just blowing Twitter and Facebook out of the water, particularly TikTok, a very scary company, yes, but also a dominant player in the space. YouTube is huge.

 

      And one of the challenges when we try to sort of shove this square peg of social media platforms into the round hole of content moderation governance is, how do you define the industry? That's incredibly important for determining whether you've got dominance in a market or a monopoly. What is the industry here?

 

      I think the industry is literally just companies that start with an F and a T that allow moderated conversation and pictures on it. Well, yeah, that's Twitter and Facebook. Okay, fine, but you've stolen a base. If you define the relevant industry so narrowly, there is a tremendous amount of competition in this space.

 

      And maybe the people in this room, I would say, are probably somewhat exceptional, but the average American doesn't get their news primarily from social media. Teenagers do, but I can't tell they're getting any news from anywhere. But there's a whole variety of inputs that people have, including mainstream media, which remains a significant source of political opinion, commentary, and news for people.

 

      So I just reject the idea that there's this market dominance with the kind that would justify such an extraordinary incursion on fundamental constitutional rights, including the right of editorial discretion, which has been affirmed in case after case after case by the Supreme Court. It's worth keeping something in mind.

 

      I don't know that I necessarily agree that this is true, but it's been said that there is no new thing under the sun. I think Twitter and Facebook are somewhat new, but fair enough that people have been making this argument that this Company X is so big and so influential that, if we don't require it to give equal time to both sides, then it'll work the debate.

 

      In fact, the Supreme Court, in a key 1974 case called Miami Herald v. Tornillo, which was a case where the issue was, if Miami Herald ran an editorial in favor one politician, does the opposing politician have the legal authority or legal right to have their response published? The Supreme Court said, "No, you can't force them to do that." And Florida was trying to force that equal time. Supreme Court said no.

 

      And they noticed that one of the arguments was to place in the hands of a few people the power to inform American people and shape public policy, and public opinion is dangerous because these are newspapers. And then we heard the same argument in another case called Pruneyard, which is sort of the bedrock of the Fifth Circuit decision upholding the Texas version of forced content moderation.

 

      Pruneyard involved discourse at a shopping mall. Do you remember what a shopping mall is? That's where you go to get parachute pants and the latest Bangles CD. And the argument was, "Oh, if we allow owners of shopping malls to close it off to equal discussion, people won't be able to participate in dialogue and discussion." Nobody goes to a shopping mall anymore, unless you're going to the food court. Unless you're going to the food court, right? That's not where we have discussions and discourse.

 

      And none of us can know what's coming down the pipe. Maybe social media platforms will be relevant in 10 years. Maybe they'll be irrelevant. How ridiculous will we look if we allow the camel of government regulation into this tent when we could have kept it out safely? And I think we can keep it out safely.

 

      And I think it's incumbent on all of us to remember the following: This is how you lose a constitution of limited government, one exception at a time. We used to have a federal government of enumerated powers, and we gave that away. We used to have a contracts clause, and we gave that away one step at a time. And you never get it back.

 

      Anybody remember where automatic paycheck withholding came from? Good friend to liberty named Milton Friedman. Well, that was just an emergency measure during World War II to make sure we could fight that war. Well, we never got rid of that, did we? Make no mistake, my friends. This camel comes as a camel. Don't let it in. Don't let it in the tent.

 

Prof. Richard Epstein:  It's a very old camel; I'm talking about a set of exceptions that run back 500 years. I'm trying to talk about them in a way in which you scrupulously skill off the monopoly situation from the non-monopoly situation. I'm worried about all sorts of situations where the level of government intervention is too high, which is why I was quite explicit in saying that the proposal that Philip Hamburger put forward you giving securities regulation to this stuff is utterly inconsistent with the First Amendment.

 

      But it's a relatively low system of intervention to apply a nondiscrimination principle, which is much a part of the constitutional law of the United States as is the freedom of expression principle that one starts to develop. And I think all we have to do is to understand, in this particular case, it's a relatively model situation, and then ask the question, are we really going to be better off if you have major outlets which controlled millions upon millions of people, which has systematically devoted themselves to one side of the argument and then denounced the other side of the argument of not being worthy of that conclusion?

 

      So I don't like this any more than anybody else. I said at the beginning; I'm kind of nervous about all of this. But if the theory is we're giving up all liberties one of the time, well, you better look at the federal government and look at the antitrust laws because everything that these networks are doing are is in violation of that.

 

      So what you're hearing in many cases on these networks on key issues is government speech, which is a real danger to our particular liberty, and what you're seeing in many cases is a collusive refusal to deal. And so if you think that the antitrust laws are completely misguided—as some people at the Cato Institute unfortunately do—and if you think that the state action doctrine doesn't really matter, then you want to be on the other side of it.

 

      But the moment you realize that these guys are not innocent characters, just simply like the Miami Herald with a very small circulation in a competitive market, these guys have dominant kinds of positions. They form very critical alliances with government sorts of agencies and amongst themselves. And all I'm asking to apply to this standard antitrust law, standard first action of equal protection, state action doctrine, and so forth.

 

      I'm not trying to get rid of all liberties. In fact, I'm trying to preserve them against the federal government, which is why I think the way the announcement was put that the states could do something—because it's quite clear that our federal government is so hopeless and beyond repair—that it will do nothing at all.

 

Prof. Nicholas Rosenkranz:  Would you like to respond to that? So both our debaters are lawyers, and unsurprisingly, they reach for and think about these questions in terms of analogies, and you've heard them argue in favor of their preferred analogy against their opponent's analogies. Let me ask both of you if you'd like to say more about why your analogy is correct, why your opponent's analogy is not. And let me invite you to consider, are none of these analogies satisfying perhaps? So is this actually something new, and do we have to think about it in a different way?

 

Prof. Richard Epstein:  That's good.

 

Clark Neily:  So I don't think it's something new, to be honest. People have been gathering and having conversation since time immemorial. People have known, for example, that you can make money if you provide a congenial environment in which to do that. Some people would call that a bar. That's a fun place to do it.

 

      My wife and I were in London over the summer, and I discovered this thing called the Soho Club. I don't know if anybody's heard of that. It's for younger people, but it's for creatives. And they have clubhouses all over the world, and you have to apply to get in. And I don't know what that looks like; we were guests of somebody, but it's a deliberate effort to create a space that facilitates a certain kind of conversation with a certain kind of people.

 

      I don't think that's newmake and I think it's quite desirable to ensure that people who want to create spaces or platforms where certain kinds of conversations can occur and are encouraged to occur, I think that is laudable. I think the idea that Twitter or Facebook or Instagram or any of these other platforms would look essentially the way they do if they had been subjected to regulated utility constraints or common carrier requirements is fallacious. I'm not saying that's Richard's position, but I don't think that's what they would look like.

 

      I think there's a really good reason why Florida and Texas have not teamed up to purchase one of these platforms. I think they probably know. I'm from Texas. Twitter is on sale right now from what I hear. I think it's down 65 percent in market cap. I think you can get it for under $20 billion. Pretty sure Governor Abbott would look for $20 billion in change if it got behind the couch cushions in his office.

 

      Why haven't they bought it? Because they know they'd wreck it. They know they'd wreck it. They don't know how to run a social media platform. They don't know the secret sauce that makes it work. I happen to think, to a high degree of certainty, the secret sauce that makes a social media platform work is curating the discussion and the presentation of information in a way that is congenial to its users.

 

      That is one of the reasons people are abandoning Twitter and advertisers are abandoning Twitter. Other people are getting on. Great. Hopefully he can right the ship, maybe he can't, but there is competition in this space, and there will continue to be competition in this space.

 

      I'm old enough to remember when Microsoft got sued for antitrust because they were bundling that Internet Explorer with their operating system. Well, Internet Explorer is the butt of a joke now, and so is AOL, and so as Myspace. So it's not new. It just happens to be a shiny new thing right now.

 

      And again, to make an exception to the basic default constitutional value of free speech and respect for property rights simply because Twitter and Facebook misbehaved—and they did misbehave, but simply because they misbehaved in the past—would be a grievous error. And I share, by the way, Richard's concern.

 

      I'll just give one more quote here. He's terribly concerned about who would run this thing. If you put the put the ability to impose certain content moderation requirements in the hands of government, who then ends up exercising that power? Well, I'm going to get my up on my libertarian soapbox right now and say I don't care which side they're on. It won't be anybody good, and it won't be anybody who should be interested to come within a mile of that power.

 

Prof. Nicholas Rosenkranz:  Richard, what's the right analogy here, or is no analogy quite right?

 

Prof. Richard Epstein:  Well, I think there are analogies. The first thing we do when we worry about regulation, is content discrimination versus content-neutral regulations. If this is, as I think it was in many cases, it may not still be. It's probably not in the lower industries. But to the extent that you have that, what you do is you have government intervening on the side of one party or another. Most of the cases in which you see [inaudible 00:46:17] coming off is all people who like to play chess in one way or another.

 

      And it's a subject matter kind of restriction. It's not essentially a viewpoint kind of restriction. Those are completely harmless. But if you go back and look at the ways in which various things have been done, the amount of damage which has been done by these various networks with respect to the COVID issue on shaping public opinion, I think, is really enormous.

 

      And the amount of effort that was done by individual government agents, in order to try to perpetuate that, I think what we have to do essentially is to remember that the appropriate analogy is that private institutions can be taken over and governed through regulation by governments.

 

      And so, at that particular point, the model is not free speech that you're worried about; the model that you're worried about is government domination of these various kinds of activities, and that is, to me, a very serious kind of problem. The defamation problem is, I think, also serious. They're not just keeping me off. What they're doing is they're telling the rest of the world that I'm worthless and dangerous. I don't think that that's an appropriate function that you want to have, particularly if they do that in a way which makes it impossible for you to engage in any kind of counter-speech.

 

      They're completely preemptory with respect to this, and I think the inability to find a forum of equal size and importance in dealing with them is, I think, again, very, very troublesome. So, as I said to you, I'm extremely unhappy about the position that I have taken because I do subject that it is realized that the underlying dynamics, the framework is correct. It's unchanging. Monopolies are subject to regulation that private parties that are not monopolies are not subject to. That's been around for a very long time.

 

      That government intervention to control private parties is essentially state action activities, which takes you out of the private sphere. Both of these things are at work in this place, and in fact, what's so clear about it is you could do this in the following way: If it turns out that the government leaves one side are completely alone and it goes after another guy with this jawboning and overtaking it, then in effect, the suspect network is the one that ought to be subject to the greater discrimination.

 

      And the non-discrimination provision, which is relatively modest in terms of what its scope is, just let these guys talk is not going to hamper discourse. It's not going to result in a massive government takeover of everything that's going on. So Clark and I live in different worlds. I live in a world in which there are two kinds of errors: overregulation and under-regulation. I'm not really sure which is dominant. He's in a world in which he knows what the answer is, and if there's only one side to a debate, well, we're never going to regulate.

 

      That's not the First Amendment law. When you deal with defamation, it's complicated. You deal with trade secrets, it's complicated. When you deal with threats of assault, it's complicated, and so forth. What we have to do is to recognize that, if we're going to try to get to the right solution, you can't stand on the corner and simply say that every counterexample is irrelevant and say that we will somehow be able to work this out in the long run. We may, but in the long run, we may also be dead, and in the interim, the question is, what are we supposed to do?

 

Prof. Nicholas Rosenkranz:  It appears that companies like Facebook and Twitter have the power—seem to have the power—to affect election results. Is that relevant? Does that change the analysis?

 

Prof. Richard Epstein:  Well, that's what's so annoying about the announcement that one saw on Twitter in the bad old days, is that we're not going to allow any bad information or bad elections to come on our site when they were doing all sorts of bad things themselves. And so it's very, very troublesome when you have somebody who's wants to be a publisher and a platform at the same time to be able to exert its influence in ways by silencing the opposition and over-promoting its own stuff, and then say, "Oh, well, we're also independent of all the campaign finance laws," which indeed, I suppose that you want.

 

      But no, I am very, very worried about this kind of concentration of private power as combined with government disinformation. So let me give one illustration. We had this totally bogus statement, which said, "Well, we really think that the Russian disinformation was responsible for what Donald Trump did in the election in 2020," and this stuff gets amplified on then Twitter or then Facebook or then somebody else.

 

      At that point, the amplification of falsehoods by government agencies without [inaudible 00:50:43] chance of counter-election, that's enough to swing an election. And if it's enough to swing an election, you got to worry about what other things that these characters are doing. And so just the simple precaution that I'm trying to say is, let somebody on the side who disagrees with that particular analysis seems to me to be both non-intrusive in a really deep way and it could correct against a major abuse.

 

      If you ask me whether any solution I propose is 100 percent safe, I'm saying you're in the wrong universe. Everything I propose has a disadvantage to it, but everything that he proposes has bigger disadvantages to it. And what you're trying to do when you're dealing with regulation is to ask this question: When there are two forms of error, over- and under-regulation, which in which context is going to be more appropriate?

 

      That's what I'm trying to do. That's why I reject many forms of internet regulation. But why it is, unfortunately, in this particular case, "Oh, you have to attack the hypocrisy of a bunch of people who announced that they're in favor of free and fair elections, they're trying to get rid of disinformation," and then they lie through their teeth on matters of really important public issues in which thousands of lives are at stake, political fortunes are at stake. And they basically have managed to have a license to print falsehood with impunity, and that's a very dangerous state for us to be in.

 

Clark Neily:  Well, social media platforms certainly do have the ability to influence an election. The question is whether they have the ability to dictate the outcome of an election.

 

Prof. Richard Epstein:  Too strong a word.

 

Clark Neily:  That's an important distinction. We all have the ability to influence elections, some more so than others. Take a class from Richard Epstein; you'll never vote Democrat again. That's influence. Fox has the ability to influence elections. MSNBC, I don't know how, but they do, apparently. The Federalist Society. You remember when it was being bandied about that The Federalist Society had managed to secure a commitment from a certain presidential candidate to do certain things on the Supreme Court? I don't know if that influenced the election, but I suspect it did. Most people suspect it did. Good. Good.

 

      That's what the First Amendment is for, is to create a space for that kind of competition, frankly, the push and pull of the political process. And the idea that just because you have the number one news network—I think Fox is still number one—that somehow, "Oh, well, that's going to constrain your First Amendment rights." No, no, no. That's been a consistent theme in the Supreme Court, and thank goodness for that.

 

      So as Judge Newsom said in the Eleventh Circuit opinion, the idea that somehow you begin to lose your First Amendment rights just because you create some new way of affecting public discourse or even the political process, just because you hit it big, no, absolutely not. That is utterly alien to our tradition. And we have confidence—or at least, historically, we've had confidence that the system will achieve a kind of equilibrium.

 

      Sure, one side gets the upper hand from time to time, but then equilibrium reasserts itself. Eight of the 10 most popular and most engaged pages on Facebook are conservative. Conservatives dominate Facebook in some ways, at least at the very sort of political tip of the spear, notwithstanding the overall hostility, which I agree, there is a kind of overall hostility to those viewpoints, but even Facebook isn't able to sublimate that.

 

      And, of course, Twitter changed hands last year and now looks like a completely different platform than it did before. This is equilibrium reasserting itself. We've had faith throughout the entire history of this country that, generally speaking, if you're not exactly sure how things are going to turn out, the best bet is to keep government out of it, whatever it is. Hear, hear.

 

Prof. Nicholas Rosenkranz:  We're going to open up for audience questions in a moment. There are mics here and here. If you would like to ask a question, please start to move to a microphone? And would either of you like to say anything else before we do that or respond to anything that's been said? Okay. Sir.

 

Prof. Richard Epstein:  Where are you?

 

Prof. Nicholas Rosenkranz:  Over there.

 

Prof. Richard Epstein:  Oh, now we got you.

 

Prof. Nicholas Rosenkranz:  Can we turn on the house mics?

 

Paul Kaminar:  Are the house mics on? There we go. Thank you. Paul Kaminar. Enjoyed this debate very much. And, Clark, congratulations for daring to go against Professor Epstein here. I'd like if both of you can maybe discuss how Section 230 of the Communication Decency Act affects your argument, 230 giving immunity to the tech companies for content posted by third parties, in terms of Professor Epstein, you wanting to sue for defamation, and Clarke with respect to just private property, but doesn't it have this government protection and change the analysis?

 

Prof. Richard Epstein:  This is a very troublesome issue. They've given the total exemption for these people on this assumption that they're platforms, not editors. And now, of course, what we're doing is we're seeing them becoming very much more editors. And so you wonder whether or not the exemption ought to apply.

 

      And, in addition, it turns out, the way the sections work, you have to do this in good faith when you shut things down. And so I think it's a very real question of whether you're acting in good faith when you shut down one side of the debate and you leave the other side of the debate open and then don't give any reasons as to why it is that you're doing it.

 

      So the position that I've taken, in general, is even if you don't get rid of Section 230—and I have mixed emotions about this for all sorts of other reasons—that, in this particular case, in these kinds of situations where you play favorites, you're not entitled to the particular immunity.

 

      Now, I would never sue anybody for defamation in my life, but I have to tell you, that's the way, in fact, I believe that they have characterized what I've done. And the defamation argument does not depend upon market power. It just depends upon something saying, "Well, whatever you said in this particular election, we've taken down because it's a pack of lies." You don't have to have market power for that to be wrong.

 

      And so what I really think is going on in this particular case is that it's very difficult to get private plaintiffs to do this, but I think if a government agency were to show that there were enough cases in which this kind of selective behavior was taking place, that you should, in fact, lose that kind of immunity. And if the immunity is gone, the willingness of people to sue may be very different from what it is.

 

      The big difference between Clark and myself, I think there are bad actors out there for whom free entry will not correct. And the assumption about the law of defamation is that it is not the case that the truth will always catch up with a lie before it rules other people, which is why you need to have some kind of countermeasures.

 

      And so thinking about it in this particular way, I've become much more upset about the way in which we think about 230. The original versions, they were like a lending library. They're not going to be responsible for the thing that they trend on because they're not expected to read every single word, but they're not behaving that way. The only reason they bounced somebody like myself is because they didn't read every word, and they decided that they didn't want it. So I don't think they're entitled to 230 immunity under those circumstances.

 

Clark Neily:  Well, I've recently learned from painful experience that it takes about an hour and a half to do justice to the Section 230 question. I don't think we have that time, but I can do it in maybe 20 seconds, and it's this: You simply cannot bootstrap your way around constitutional rights or constitutional values by legislating and conferring certain prerogatives or taking certain prerogatives away from a private business.

 

      And if you want to look at what that might -- or if you want a taste of what that might look like in another industry, think about the fact that Congress has conferred immunity upon manufacturers of firearms, the Lawful Commerce in Arms Act. Is the idea then going to be that they enjoy a different scope of Second Amendment protection for their business because Congress has decided to confer some form of immunity on them? To hell with that. And the same thing here. Now, it takes longer to do it right, but that's a taste.

 

Prof. Richard Epstein:  Are you on my side or the other side?

 

Clark Neily:  They have a second amendment right to produce firearms and not have that right constraint simply because Congress has conferred immunity on them for product liability lawsuits. Congress does not have the ability to affect the size or the shape of somebody's constitutional rights through legislation, period.

 

Prof. Nicholas Rosenkranz:  Whoops. But I think you're agreeing, actually, Richard, is Section 230 actually relevant to the constitutional question?

 

Prof. Richard Epstein:  Let me put it to you this way. My view is that what you start to do is to eliminate it, and then once you eliminate what is relevant, it's New York Times v. Sullivan. And New York Times v. Sullivan is not a position which says you have absolute immunity. It rejected the Black-Douglas position. And so then you have to ask the question of whether this is not malice in the constitutional sense.

 

      And I think, given the fact that they are in reckless disregard about thinking what other people say when they disregard them, this is in fact something where they could be exposed. And if they could be exposed to private suits, it's a much more complicated question to ask whether or not you could use some public regulation to take place when private suits are not, in fact.

 

      So the one case that I've always thought was a constitutional horror story on this was the stolen valor case, where it turns out you have guys engaging in systematic fraud all over the place, you can't figure out which particular person is injured, and so saying that we can't identify the particular plaintiff, we don't let the state come in and bring the fraud action.

 

      I think the correct view is there. We've established the fraud, and you show that private actions are ineffective to deal with it. A direct form of government regulation turns out to be appropriate because, otherwise, what happens is, you are so privileged in private rights of actions when the transaction is cost-prohibitive, that guys like that fella get away with all sorts of things that they should not get away was.

 

      So I do not think that we want to say the world is such a place, if you can't make the private action going, the state regulation is inappropriate. If there's systematic forms of fraud, it seems to me you could do it. If there's systematic protections that you could put into place—say you're dealing with an abortion clinic and you're worried about whether it's going to be persuasion of force—I think the legislature is not only within its rights but it would be to duty bound to give an area of safe protection on the one hand, which isn't so large, to prevent people from speaking.

 

      But if there's a hard line to draw between persuasion on the one hand and coercion on the other, you don't want to say, "Well, we'll decide this ex-post after the fact that in litigation." There's a book I wrote called "Simple Rules for a Complex World." And I think this is a case where we need a simple rule which draws a line instead of making ad hoc determinations.

 

      So that's a longer answer than you would -- but it turns out that defamation is a very tough topic to deal with. And a per se rule under the First Amendment that it's just fine doesn't begin to get at what the problems really are.

 

Prof. Nicholas Rosenkranz:  Take a question over here, please.

 

Katherine Urbanek:  Hello. My name is Katherine Urbanek. I am clerking for the Honorable Joshua Mize on the Florida Sixth District Court of Appeal. Clark, I had the pleasure of meeting you three years ago at The Federalist Society Student Leadership Conference in Amelia Island. Hello.

 

      My question for you both -- And I don't think it's been addressed, but I would just like to read this briefly. "The Virality Project was an initiative undertaken jointly by big tech universities and NGOs to combat 'anti-vaccine misinformation.' SIO responded to Taibbi’s Twitter Files by claiming that his findings were "inaccurate and based on distortions of email exchanges in the Twitter Files." But new evidence shows that Stanford lied about the scope of the Virality Project and that its censorship efforts were undertaken on behalf of the U.S. government.

 

      "As Public reported on Tuesday, new documents shared by the House Judiciary Committee revealed that the Department of Homeland Security created the Virality Project’s predecessor, the Election Integrity Partnership to censor protected speech. Explains the committee, "EIP reconstituted as the Virality Project" and continued working with the federal government."

 

Prof. Nicholas Rosenkranz:  We're going to need a question.

 

Katherine Urbanek:  So my question to that is, where there is evidence that is showing that the federal government is colluding with big tech to censor speech from various voices -- And so I haven't really seen that addressed where we have seen the government that has worked hand in hand with Twitter, with Facebook to censor speech, and if you could please address that.

 

Prof. Nicholas Rosenkranz:  Thank you. It's to you.

 

Clark Neily:  So my regards to Josh, by the way. I haven't seen him in a while, but good to see you again. So this is a very significant elephant in the room, standing right next to the camel, and it's jawboning. And what the federal government appears to have done—and perhaps to still be doing—in terms of attempting to influence, and perhaps even coerce, social media platforms to make content-based decisions is absolutely disgraceful and indefensible.

 

      But the idea that the best way to address it is to put more power in the hands of government officials, I think, is deeply misguided. Loren Spiewak at the Phoenix Center has an article on this topic, and he points out that regulation does not widen the gap between the regulated and the regulator; regulation brings them closer together.

 

      And that is not something you want to do here. What we should be doing instead is identifying the officials who engage in this conduct and going after them with a meat ax. Get rid of qualified immunity. You knew I was going to say that, and sue those officials into the poor house. So you could make an example of them so it doesn't happen anymore.

 

Prof. Richard Epstein:  Basically, he wants the meat axe; I'm quite happy to use a hammer and tongs. But the real question is, we live in a world of the second best. These guys have all sorts of immunities. They leave government. They're going to be passionately defended by government lawyers for what it is that they do. And it turns out, the direct remedy doesn't work, and so now what I hear is we're not allowed to try to take second-best remedy.

 

      And the nondiscrimination view which gets her on the platform and overcomes that and lets the government then write something by way of refutation seems to be a better world than one in which we wield in the sky our heavy artillery which we're never able to fire or to land the blow on the government agency.

 

      So that was the point that I had made to begin with. If one hears, as he has said, that this is obnoxious behavior, vicious behavior, terrible behavior, oh, but there's nothing we can do about it because of the First Amendment, and we can't sue these guys directly, this is the part about accommodations.

 

      If the first-best remedy is not available to you, the second-best remedy starts to become something about this. And this is not a case where the second remedy simply makes the first one worse. You can't look at regulations on a retail basis, not on a wholesale basis, to figure out whether they're making the situation better or they're making it worse.

 

      And I suspect what happens to you happens in many places. And interestingly enough, my guess is, when they push their influence, they're not only going to do it on the friendly nations; they're probably going to pay an odd visit to somebody at Twitter as well. And so you're dealing with a situation in which the government essentially brings the entire industry together as one.

 

      And if they do that, all these antitrust definitions of what counts as a market pass by the wayside. So I'm going to stress it again: I think the common carrier push is philosophically an extremely interesting one, and the way I decided Monday, Wednesday, and Friday, take one position; Tuesday, Thursdays, and Saturday, the other; and on Sunday, I rest.

 

      But in this case, you can't rest on this particular issue. And it turns out that the question you have to ask is not is regulation good or bad, but is the regulation that's being proposed going to make the situation at the margin better or worse. And in this case, it makes it better. And so, therefore, it seems to me that you want the states to do this and you want to take the federalism model, government against government.

 

      There are going to be some states like New York and California where they'll compound the felony, but in a federalist system, if Florida and Texas—most notoriously blue states, I'm sure we all know—if these states want to come after it, I think we ought to encourage them. And then, in fact, we can have a much more principled debate.

 

      And why is that going to happen? Because you start doing these depositions and so forth, it's going to be a strange world. What's going on with Missouri v. Biden where this whole thing is taking place? It's just shocking the level of perfidy that's starting to take place and how it affects people and their lives and losing positions and everything else, and we need to have more stuff like that.

 

      And the enforcement of a nondiscrimination regulation, which is relatively nonintrusive, will, A, stop a lot of this stuff from taking place, and B, will allow us to understand how to make it fair. And once we make it fair, then in fact, public opinion is going to change the way in which the game works. So I regard myself as a good government man, much as I hate that phrase.

 

Prof. Nicholas Rosenkranz:  Let's take a question over here, please.

 

William Trachman:  Hi. Will Trachman from Mountain States Legal Foundation. Clark, what do you do about the idea that so much of official government conduct occurs on social media? So, obviously, school board meetings where you can comment in the Facebook page. My kid's kindergarten class has a Facebook page. And so if a content moderation policy prevents me from either having an account or freezes my account or suspends me even for a minute or two, my access to official government conduct is lessened, and so I have less of a voice in that public square.

 

 

Clark Neily:  Yeah, great question. I appreciate it. I think, hopefully, all of us in this room, except for people who professionally can't say what I'm about to say, thank goodness that I don't have to answer that question officially. That argument and Supreme Court was a mess. The question over whether government officials can mute or block or take other action vis-a-vis constituents because we're dealing with a situation here where, in effect, all of us are empowered to corner, our local representatives in the grocery store and harangue them about whatever it is that we're upset now.

 

      We don't even have to lift a finger. You don't have to go outside your house to do this. You just have to pick up your phone and get on their Facebook page or their Twitter feed. So I don't think that there's an obvious answer to this question. It's a hard question. And I think the idea, to go back to something that Richard said, that the first question is, does the regulation make the situation better or worse, I disagree with that. The first question, always, is whether the proposed regulation does or does not violate the Constitution. Thank you.

 

      And the question of just exactly how much prerogative a government official has in setting up a social media account to determine who comes onto that account and says what and how much leeway a social media company has to make that decision for them, these are very difficult questions. I just don't have a clear or short answer; no one did at the Supreme Court. That argument went on forever, and they basically ended up back where they started. So Richard, I'm sure, is going to have an extremely thoughtful, somewhat unconvincing, but nevertheless fascinating response to your question.

 

Prof. Richard Epstein:  Government speech is a huge problem, the first thing that we have to understand is that you cannot have a world in which government officials are not able to speak when they hold political office and, to some extent, is moderated because you have a president, but there are people from the other party who get a chance to get speaking as well.

 

      So there's at least some element of counter-speech that's involved in these cases, but if it turns out that the speech we're dealing with is not public statements on behalf of COVID or one thing or another, but the kinds of things that were said before, under the radar with heavy precedential influence, with the threat of behavior, at that particular point, it seems to me that sunlight is a very good disinfectant and the point of a nondiscrimination rules it gets this thing from.

 

      I disagree with Clark when he says the first thing is it's constitutional, not whether it's better. The reason is the Constitution sets a presumption in favor of free speech, and the question of whether or not you could override it depends upon whether the proposed regulation is going to make things better, as it does if you stop securities fraud, as it does if you stop vicious defamation, as it does if you stop somebody threatening you with murder, and even yelling fire in a crowded theater.

 

      So if it turns out that the regulation, in effect, is designed to stop government abuse, then it seems to me you have to allow it. And this is what makes our profession a high-income profession: These questions are hard. The justifications are always a little bit unclear. The uncertainties create a fog of war, but what you have to do is you have to pay people to give an analysis, not of black and white, but of the relative uncertainties and the relative benefits of various pieces.

 

      That's why I mentioned the stolen valor pieces situation. I thought it was an utterly bizarre opinion to say that, since you can't identify the victims of fraud particularly, but you know there are huge numbers of them, perhaps an entire society, there's nothing that you can do. The answer is there's a lot you can do; you can basically punish the fraudster for the kinds of wrongs that they make, and the world will be a better place for that kind of regulation.

 

      And the Supreme Court, as far as I'm concerned, it has never mastered two things. One is the relationship of public to private law and how you start to think about what things you can and cannot control. And, tow, it has never figured out, when you're doing a balancing test, how it is that you organize the various presumptions to get a little bit of the chaos out of the ultimate situation.

 

      In the end, you could always find individual cases that will stump even somebody as clever as Clark or as unclever as me, but the point is, can we clear up enough of the underbrush so that the error is in 5 percent of the situation, not 95 percent of the situation? And again, the appropriate test here is not perfection; the appropriate test here is if you get an improvement, and I think some of these regulations do improve things. And when I hear the kinds of things that start to happen—that is, presidential speech in private where counter-speech does not really work—that's the area in which you need to have the disinfectant.

 

Prof. Nicholas Rosenkranz:  Thank you. Let's take a question over here, please.

 

Dan Greenberg:  So when I was a young man -- Sorry. My name is Dan Greenberg from Competitive Enterprise Institute. I'm going to try to emulate my favorite professor that I ever had the University of Chicago by speaking very rapidly when he taught. I recall that, when I was a young man, I worked at a newspaper in South Arkansas. It was my very first job, and this newspaper at a very interesting feature in that it had had a Letters to the Editor page in which there were many letters from many people who talked about many matters of public import.

 

      And the editorial page editor would often make comments about letters that were published and were not published, also in the paper would criticize people, both the writers that were published and the writers who were not published for their lack of ability to communicate and their mistakes that they made. And this this newspaper page, this Letters to the Editor, it was not much of a factor when I was working there, but it was a very strong factor in public life back in the 19th century when it began because it was really the only area, the only forum in that part of the country where public matters were discussed in print in mass media.

 

      And I do wonder whether there are some analogies here in that, in fact, it really was a kind of monopoly, an actual monopoly, in a way that I think competing social media companies are not. And I want to commend Professor Epstein on his analysis of, we really have to look at the factors and the facts and the way that common law is developed. But does it trouble you that your arguments are really applicable to newspapers in the 19th century which are uncompetitive public forums and solely monopolistic public forums?

 

Prof. Richard Epstein:  Everything troubles me. That's the point of this discussion. I think, in effect, when you're dealing with an ordinary newspaper, the counter-speech arguments are probably going to be more difficult, particularly in the context of the 19th century. And in fact, if I'm answering the question, I'm much less worried about the public speech by a government monopolist than I am by the secret private speech that they have in order to influence somebody to say things on the network without disclosing that they've been either promised something by the government or coerced.

 

      And that's exactly what has been done on these platforms with respect to COVID, and I've studied this far enough to realize that the single greatest public health discretion disaster in the history of the United States has been the way in which we handled COVID. You go back to 1918 when we had a much more serious flu and we had much less knowledge, we did a much better job then than we do now.

 

      How do I know that? Well, one simple observation is, how long did it last? Six weeks at that time, three years and counting today, and it's all because of muddleheaded people who don't know what interventions make sense and what don't. And so I'm much more concerned. The secret talk that I've heard that, to me, is the most powerful argument that is made in this particular case. And Clark agrees that he doesn't have an answer, but I'm not so sure.

 

Prof. Nicholas Rosenkranz:  I think we have time for one last audience question over here, please.

 

Ilya Somin:  Ilya Somin, Scalia Law School at George Mason University. It seems like central to the argument for regulation here is the idea that there's a monopoly. And so my question is, where is that monopoly? Because, to be honest, I don't see it. Lots of evidence shows that most Americans get their political information not primarily from social media, but elsewhere.

 

      And lots of evidence also shows that all this stuff that supposedly can't be said—anti-vaxxer viewpoints, claims that Trump won the 2020 election, right-wing viewpoints and so on—you see them all the time, including on America's biggest most watched TV network, Fox News. Indeed, if this really were a monopoly, we wouldn't be able to say all the time, as we do see all the time, attacks on the social media companies themselves.

 

      It seems to me a real monopolist could at least suppress the formation of a massive public movement to attack and criticize the monopolist itself. So it seems to me like, at the very least, there has to be a strong presumption against regulation and burden of proof to show that this supposed monopoly actually exist.

 

      And you just look around, you see the overwhelming evidence that it doesn't, but perhaps there's some kind of more hidden evidence of some sort that shows that all this stuff I really see, the speech, saying the very things that are supposedly suppressed, that somehow that isn't actually out there. So that's my question: Where's the monopoly?

 

Prof. Richard Epstein:  Well, it turns out high concentrations in a social media network can be a recognized argument, even if there's another news argument out there. That's the first point. The second point is, if you listen to the way in which the discussion has evolved, I was less concerned in many ways that I was about monopoly than I was about government coercion, which is illegal as far as I'm concerned in a monopoly or a non-monopoly situation.

 

      So my own view about this is, when you're attacking stuff, I want to go after what I think is to be the easy stuff first and the hard stuff later. And so I'm going to go with what I thought and I said in the paper. I said, this monopoly stuff is very difficult. The stuff about secret behavior and coercive behavior by the government is not very difficult. And the nondiscrimination rules are designed to expose that, and they're not going to hurt anybody else in a competitive market.

 

      So I think, in effect, you always go after your strongest case first and then worry about the rest of it. And in this case, I think the strong case is there. I take Clark is saying he agrees with that. And then saying, "Well, I don't know what the remedy is," well, if you have a systematic wrong of massive proportions, you better find a remedy, and nondiscrimination is about as good as it comes.

 

      So let's have a compromise. What we do is we go after all the secret government speech, regardless of what the structure of the market is, and wait perhaps for another day to see whether or not you're right or wrong about the monopoly, whether Twitter is going to be a competitor, and so forth. What I wanted to do is to make sure that we move on the court cases, and that means, in effect, at some level at least, you have to have some form of government regulation to moderate what these creeps can do and the way in which they run their networks

 

Prof. Nicholas Rosenkranz:  Clark, do you want to speak to that?

 

Clark Neily:  This is a nice point to end on. It's going to take me back to something I said before. One could credibly say that there is, in a sense, a monopoly on platforming effective discussion of legal issues because there's only one group that's doing it coherently and, therefore, the Federalist Society has a monopoly on that and that is false. The Federalist Society exerts a disproportionate influence in the space because it does it better than anybody else, not because it has a monopoly. So it is with social media platforms.

 

Prof. Richard Epstein:  So it is with social media platforms, unfortunately. 

 

Prof. Nicholas Rosenkranz:  There's a lot of terrific programming coming up, so please stick around. The next showcase panel starts at 3:00, I believe. And please join me in thanking our debaters.

 

     

 

 

2:45 p.m. - 4:30 p.m.
Showcase Panel IV: How Originalist is the Supreme Court?

2023 National Lawyers Convention

Topics: Constitution • Supreme Court
State & East Rooms
The Mayflower Hotel
1127 Connecticut Avenue NW
Washington, DC 20006

Share

Event Video

Listen & Download

Description

Featuring:

  • Prof. J. Joel Alicea, Co-Director, Project on Constitutional Originalism and the Catholic Intellectual Tradition, Assistant Professor of Law, Columbus School of Law, The Catholic University of America
  • Prof. Randy E. Barnett, Patrick Hotung Professor of Constitutional Law, Georgetown University Law Center; Founding Director, Georgetown Center for the Constitution
  • Prof. Richard H. Fallon, Story Professor of Law, Harvard Law School
  • Prof. Stephen E. Sachs, Antonin Scalia Professor of Law, Harvard Law School
  • Moderator: Hon. Neomi Rao, U.S. Court of Appeals, District of Columbia Circuit

Speakers

Event Transcript

Dean Reuter:  We're going to resume, if we could, please. It's a very obedient -- you guys would be terrible protesters. I'm Dean Reuter, the Senior Vice President and General Counsel of The Federalist Society. Thank you all for being here. As we head towards the conclusion of this year's convention, I want to take a moment. And you'll have to clap loudly, because none of them are in the room, really, but I want to take a moment to congratulate and thank the mighty Federalist Society staff for their extraordinary efforts for the past months.

 

      I try to do this every year. And every year, of course, they're outside working. But maybe they'll watch it on a video. Now, as we did last year, we are going to have a special gift presented through a drawing from the Remnant Trust. The gift is provided to us by the Remnant Trust. People might remember this from last year. And I've held this up earlier during the convention. This is a leaf from a first-edition Federalist Papers 1788. 

 

Chris Talley with the Remnant Trust is responsible for bringing the rare documents that we've all been able to view upstairs. I hope you had a chance to visit with those documents and interact with them, touch them, have your picture made with them, etc., etc. Last year, we were able to give away one of these. And we were gifted one of these from the Remnant Trust. The Federalist Society was gifted one. So, to say a word or two about the organization, and then lead us through the drawing, we welcome Chris Talley. Chris.

 

Chris Talley:  Thank you. A special thanks goes out, not only to the staff of The Federalist Society, on behalf of the Remnant Trust, but to Dean Reuter, and particularly Erika, for having us and hosting us again this year. We're very appreciative. And, from the bottom of our hearts, we say thank you. And to all of you, those of you who have participated in our exhibit, it's on the second floor, in the South Carolina Room. We'll be there for another two hours. 

 

We would be delighted, if you haven't been there, to host you for an experience through time with original documents that support the idea of individual liberty and human dignity through the ages and supports this notion or this spirit of originalism that's been prevalent these past three days. So, thank you again, Dean. Thank you again, Erika. I'm going to turn it back to you.

 

Dean Reuter:  Let's do the drawing, Chris. If you had been upstairs, you were able to drop off a business card. We're now going to do the drawing and see who is the winner of this handsomely-framed leaf. You need not be present to win.

 

Chris Talley:  Here we are.

 

Dean Reuter:  That's weird. For the second year in a row, it's me.

 

Chris Talley:  No coincidence, by the way.

 

Dean Reuter:  The winner is Paul Seby of GreenbergTraurig. If Paul is here, you can come forward and claim your prize over here. Otherwise, we will be in touch with Paul and make sure he gets this. Looks like he's not in the room. But thank you so much, Chris, for everything.

 

Chris Talley:  My pleasure. 

 

Dean Reuter:  Thank you. Now we welcome our final showcase panel of our convention, which asks "How originalist is the Supreme Court?" We've once again put together a first-class panel to explore this topic. Of course, the phrase first-class reminds me of a brief but true story. And I hope you haven't heard it before. This story happened in an airport and at a time when I was working for the federal government. My children, now grown, were tiny. I was a single parent with custody of my kids.

 

So, I kept my travel to a minimum, but this time I had back-to-back trips. And I was trying to get home between two trips for the overnight, just to see the kids. But I had severe delays, landing after midnight at Dulles Airport, near my home. I was supposed to have arrived in time for dinner, and to tuck my kids in. Instead, I peeked in on them, climbed into my bed, and set the alarm for an early-morning flight out. My kids never even saw me as I headed back to Dulles Airport the next morning before daybreak.

 

At Dulles, I was in the check-in line — and this is 25 years ago or so — that next morning, waiting in line. I was at one of the budget airlines, which I will describe charitably as a younger airline. It no longer exists, having died before it reached puberty. I got to the front of the line, and I saw an impossibly young man behind the counter to greet me. He looked like he should be catching the bus to middle school. But there he was. I was wearing a suit. I had a well-worn trench coat, a somewhat battered wheel case, and a well-used briefcase, looking a lot like the stereotypical business traveler.

 

So I was a little surprised when this young man-boy, way too happy for that hour of the morning, cheerfully asked me, "Is this your first time flying?" I was a bit confused, but I sort of ignored that. But, having landed at that very airport, just a few hours before, after midnight, that same morning, I was able to reply, somewhat snarkily, "This isn't my first time flying today." Of course, that remark went right over his head. Anyhow, I was worn out from my travels and I thought I'd use my own money to get the extra legroom.

 

And so, I asked this boy, "Do you have anything in the economy plus section?" "No, sir," he replied. Now, I was ready to plunk down some real money and upgrade to first class.  "Do you have anything available in first class?" I asked. And without pausing, almost as if he anticipated the question, he said, "Sir, all our seats are first-class." And I said "Of course, they are," totally defeated. But our panel, though, is truly first-class. And I'm very pleased to introduce our moderator, as I've done in the past. I will be brief with this introduction, undeservedly brief.

 

Neomi Rao served on the D.C. Circuit Court of Appeals, often recognized as the second most important court in the country. By often recognized, I mean by most everyone other than judges on other circuit courts. Judge Rao is a great friend of The Federalist Society and brings a tremendous amount of experience and insight to our inquiry today. We're very privileged to have her with us today. Please join me in welcoming Judge Rao.

 

Hon. Neomi Rao:  Thanks so much, Dean, I think. I'm not sure I've ever been introduced as comparable to the seats of a budget airline. But we'll go with that. So, it's amazing we have this fully-packed room for what is the last showcase panel of what's been another wonderful conference on timely issues, and lots of good fellowship. And I commend you all on your stamina on making it to this panel. So, it's great.

 

      So, our topic today is "How originalist is the Supreme Court?" That we're even asking this question, I think, shows how far things have come in the American courts. And if you think about when The Federalist Society was started, some 40 years ago, there would have been no need for such a panel, or the panel would have been very short. You could just have a bunch of people saying, "How originalist is the Supreme Court? Not at all." So, the questions that would have been more appropriate back then would have been something like, what is originalism anyway? Will judges actually use originalism to interpret the Constitution? What would it mean to have judges and courts that are, in fact, originalist?

 

      But things have changed a lot. Today we have a Supreme Court on which a majority often self-identifies as originalists, at least in some form. It's a court on which all of the justices have sometimes used originalist methods to interpret the Constitution. And so, I guess it's unsurprising that now we can have many more granular discussions of what originalism is and how it's actually practiced on the high court. And so, to do this, we have a really great panel, a truly first-class panel of legal scholars to consider this question from a variety of perspectives.

 

So, with us today, and just in the order they're going to be speaking, we have Professor Randy Barnett of Georgetown Law School. And then we'll hear from Professor Joel Alicea of Catholic University Law School, and then Professor Richard Fallon of Harvard Law School and Professor Stephen Sachs, also of the Harvard Law School. They've all written extensively about originalism, legal interpretation, and the Supreme Court. And it's a real pleasure to have them with us today. Thank you.

 

Prof. Randy Barnett:  Thank you, Judge Rao. And it gives me no small pleasure to call you Judge Rao. The topic of the panel today is "How Originalist is the Supreme Court?" So, those who know me know that I don't mince words. So, my unequivocal answer is "it depends." If you mean, do a majority of the justices identify as originalist, then the court is pretty originalist. If you mean, whether a majority of the Court uses originalist reasoning to reach results because the results are dictated by or consistent with the original meaning of the Constitution, then the Court is not very originalist.

 

Finally, if you mean whether a majority of the Court uses other modalities of legal argument to reach results or outcomes that are consistent with the original meaning of the Constitution, then the Court might be originalist. But, because there is a serious problem of knowledge in reaching that conclusion, we can't really be sure. So let me examine each of these alternatives in turn. Quite obviously, a majority of the Court identifies as originalist.  On the originalist side, Justice Thomas has long both talked the talk and walked the walk. And, I would say, the originalist talk and the originalist walk. 

 

Justice Alito began identifying himself as a "practical originalist” sometime around the death of Justice Scalia. And Justices Gorsuch, Kavanaugh and Barrett all identified as originalists at their confirmation hearings and continue to do so. Chief Justice Roberts has never identified himself as an originalist, but he sometimes employs originalist arguments. To be an originalist, however, you must do more than discuss original meaning along with other modalities of constitutional analysis like stare decisis.

 

To be an originalist, original meaning must take priority over all competing modalities of constitutional analysis. Treating original meaning as just one among other modalities of constitutional analysis is actually a form of living constitutionalism that law professors call "constitutional pluralism." I fear this is often how several of our self-identified originalist justices treat original meaning, as just one factor among many, but not dispositive. Even though they consider original meaning, they are actually operating as conservative constitutional pluralists.

 

To my mind, a genuine originalist Court is a Court in which the majority of justices use originalist interpretation to reach its results. But now these criteria must be qualified. Many cases that come before the Court involve statutory construction and do not rely on the meaning of the Constitution at all. And even when the Court is engaged in constitutional analysis, most of what it does involves applying what Dick Fallon has called "implementing doctrines." These are the Court-created doctrines that are used to implement the meaning of the Constitution, rather than interpreting the Constitution itself.

 

Examples of implementing doctrines are the substantial effects doctrine of U.S. v. Darby, and the aggregation principle of Wickard v. Filburn. These doctrines purport to implement the Commerce and Necessary and Proper Clauses. Another is the imminent lawless action test of Brandenburg v. Ohio, which purports to implement the freedom of speech. That doctrine succeeded the bad tendency test that the Court had previously used to implement the freedom of speech.

 

The subject of constitutional law mainly consists in the study of these implementing doctrines. Of course, implementing doctrines are not to be found in the text of the Constitution. They lie within what some originalists call "the construction zone." Whether they are originalist or not will depend on your theory of constitutional construction. At a minimum, to be originalist, such implementing doctrines must not contradict or conflict with the original meaning of the letter of the Constitution's text. But Evan Bernick and I have argued that to be originalist, such doctrines must be more than consistent with the original meaning of the text. They must also be faithful to that meaning.

 

It is not enough that a doctrine does not contradict the letter of the Constitution. It must also be true to its spirit. By spirit, we mean the original ends, the original objects, the original functions, the original purposes of the clause, or the problems for which the various clauses were adopted to solve. On this view, when the Justices invoke the doctrine of stare decisis to adhere to Court-devised implementing doctrines that cohere with both the letter and the spirit of the Constitution, they are acting in an originalist fashion.

 

However, when they invoke the doctrine of stare decisis to adhere to implementing doctrines or constitutional constructions that conflict with either the letter or the spirit of the Constitution, they are acting as non-originalists. So, determining whether the Court is being originalist when it adheres to its own implementing doctrines as a matter of stare decisis is a complicated question that must be answered doctrine by doctrine. If these doctrines conflict with the original meaning of the text, or do not cohere with its original function or purpose, then the Court is being non-originalist when it applies these doctrines in particular cases.

 

For example, in my view, Darby's substantial effects doctrine and Wickard's aggregation principle are not faithful applications of the original meaning of the Commerce and Necessary and Proper Clause. Nor is the conceivable basis scrutiny of Williamson v. Lee Optical faithful to the original meaning of the due process of law. These precedents should be limited or reversed. And an implementing doctrine that is faithful to the original meaning of the text should be devised and adopted.

 

Now, of course, sometimes the Court is called upon to decide a case that is not covered by an existing doctrine. How originalist the Court is will be shown by how they handle cases when their own implementing doctrines do not dictate an outcome. For example, in Timbs v. Indiana, the Court had to decide whether the Eighth Amendment's bar on excessive fines was applicable to the states. In Timbs, Justices Thomas and Gorsuch both said the case was properly governed by the original meaning of the Privileges or Immunities Clause.

 

But Justices Alito, Kavanaugh, and Roberts joined Justice Ginsburg and the progressive Justices in applying the Court's substantive due process doctrine that asked whether the right was deeply rooted in the nation's tradition or history. This was especially unfortunate because the excessive fines clause was one of the last opportunities the Justices had to get the meaning of the Privileges or Immunities Clause right, in the context of an enumerated right. It presented a golden opportunity to straighten out the Court's implementing doctrines concerning fundamental rights.

 

Finally, let me turn to a Court that reaches originalist outcomes and results. Suppose that each of the originalist-identifying justices believes a particular outcome would follow from the original meaning of the text, but he or she then manipulates a mixture of stare decisis, judicial restraint, or some non-originalist doctrine to reach the right originalist result, what they think is the right originalist result. Under these circumstances, what I call the gravitational force of originalism is operating in the background to affect the outcome of the cases the way the gravitational force of an invisible black hole affects the movements of the visible stars in its vicinity.

 

A Court that consistently reached the right originalist outcome by applying non-originalist doctrines would be far preferable to one that doesn't. But that's not good enough. That's because we have a serious problem of knowledge. In the absence of originalist reasoning, we simply can't be sure what the right originalist result is. These justices would be doing what Larry Solum and I call "off the books originalism." They would be deciding cases based on their own notions of what the original meaning of the Constitution requires.

 

But they don't show their work, nor subject it to scrutiny. And this renders their off-the-books originalist opinion subject to error. Knowing the right originalist result requires us to identify the original meaning of the text, and then to assess whether or not an implementing doctrine is faithful to that meaning. This is a discovery process that involves both good-faith research and proper vetting, or peer review, if you will, by others who are knowledgeable about that particular clause at issue.

 

      When I read what I think is a persuasive piece of scholarship about the original meaning of a clause on which I am not expert, I reserve judgment until I hear what a knowledgeable critic of this scholarship says. Think Will Baude versus Micheal McConnell. When I read Will Baude's article, it sounded very plausible. But I had to hear what somebody else who thought about it said. And so, I wanted to hear what Mike McConnell said. And it turns out that was really important to do. 

 

      Our opinions about originalist outcomes need to be tested by an adversary system operating among both scholars and among judges. Over the past 40 years, this society has made remarkable strides in advancing the idea that the original meaning of the Constitution should govern those who govern us. But until we have a majority of justices who use originalist reasoning to decide cases and to evaluate the Court's implementing doctrines, we have a ways to go before we have an originalist Supreme Court. Thank you.

 

Hon. Neomi Rao:  Thanks.  Joel.

 

Prof. J. Joel Alicea:  Thank you, Judge Rao. And thanks to The Federalist Society for inviting me to be on this panel. Let's start with the most straightforward approach to the question, "How originalist is the Supreme Court?" You would just take a look at a particular term, look at all the constitutional cases in that term, figure out how many of them used originalist methods to get to originalist outcomes. And if it’s a high percentage, then it's an originalist Court. If it's a low percentage, it's not a very originalist Court. We'll call this "the simple thesis," for purposes of my remarks.

 

      I think that simple thesis has a lot of intuitive appeal. And I think it's how a lot of people think about this question. But I'm going to suggest that, actually, it's misguided. Because it overlooks the legitimate role that the party presentation principle and stare decisis could play for an originalist Supreme Court. So, I'm going to begin by talking about the ostensible conflict between these principles and originalism, then describe why I think that the ostensible conflict is based on a conceptual mistake, and then discuss the extent to which you could argue that both party presentation and stare decisis are reconcilable with originalism.

     

      So, starting with the ostensible conflict between party presentation principle and stare decisis on one hand, and originalism on the other. The party presentation principle generally says that courts should not decide cases based on arguments that the parties haven't raised. And stare decisis generally says that courts should adhere to their precedent, at least presumptively, even if it is incorrect, unless there's some special circumstances to justify departing from it. And those circumstances might exist, as in Dobbs, where the case was overwhelming for overruling that particular precedent.

 

      But if you're an originalist justice who adheres to both of those principles, it has a particular effect. Because much, if not most of current Supreme Court doctrine, I think it's fair to say, is at least in tension with originalism. And so, if you are only reconsidering non-originalist precedents when you're asked to do so — and a lot of times parties won't ask you to do so, and even if you are asked to do so, you presumptively at least adhere to those precedents — then, in most cases, as an originalist justice, you will be deciding cases based on non-originalist precedents.

 

      The simple thesis would say that that result is inconsistent with originalism. And the argument to support that generally goes like this. Originalism is, among other things, a theory of identifying what is the Constitution. It's the original meaning, right? That's the Constitution. Application of party presentation principle and stare decisis will sometimes require the Court to say that something that is not the original meaning is the Constitution. And, therefore, you have a conflict between what originalism is and what these principles, stare decisis and party presentation, might require.

 

      I think that that argument rests on a conceptual mistake at the second premise, in that it assumes that party presentation principle and stare decisis are about identifying what the law is. And they are not. They're actually just adjudicatory rules for figuring out how to decide particular cases under particular circumstances. And you can adhere to them without asserting that non-originalist precedent is what the Constitution really is. So, think about the party presentation principle first. And think of Haaland v. Brackeen, Justice Barrett's majority opinion in that case.

 

      So, in that case, Justice Barrett, writing for the majority, upholds the Indian Child Welfare Act, applying what most originalists, I think, would say are non-originalist precedents about the scope of Congress's power to regulate Indian affairs. But the reason that the Court did that in Haaland, or in Brackeen, rather, was because, at least according to Justice Barrett, Texas had not asked the Court to overrule these non-originalist precedents. Now, let's bracket for a second whether that's a fair characterization of Texas' litigating position. I'm sure my friends in the Texas SG's office would disagree with that. But let's just assume for the moment that that is, in fact, an accurate description of Texas' litigating position.

 

      Then the party presentation principle rightly dictated that the Court adhere to the non-originalist precedent in resolving that case. But that's not an assertion that those non-originalist precedents are correct or are, in fact, what the Constitution requires. It's, instead, an assertion that, under these circumstances, the party presentation principle required adhering to non-originalist precedent, treating it as if it were the Constitution. And the same is true for stare decisis, although we often don't think of stare decisis this way.

 

      Stare decisis is an adjudicatory rule that says, under certain circumstances, such as where a precedent has built up a lot of dependence and reliance interests, you treat that precedent as if it were what the law is, what the Constitution says, even if it's not actually what the Constitution says. So, in McDonald v. Chicago, when Justice Alito, for the plurality, declines to overrule the slaughterhouse cases, it's not an assertion that the due process clause actually contains the incorporation doctrine. I can't imagine that Justice Alito actually would think that.

 

      It's, instead, an assertion that, under the circumstances of this case, including, for example, the uncertainty about the original meaning of the Privileges or Immunities Clause, it would be better to treat the due process clause as if it did contain the incorporation doctrine. So, both of these principles are just asserting that somebody of non-originalist precedent is going to be treated as if it were the Constitution, for purposes of resolving the case, while still remaining open to the idea that the real Constitution is out there and could be applied in a future case.

 

      And, therefore, to the extent that the simple thesis rests on this conceptual confusion that these adjudicatory rules are, in fact, asserting what the Constitution is, then the argument against those rules falls apart. But there is still an open question about, well, how do you justify this? How do you justify this fiction of treating something that isn't the Constitution, that isn't the law, as if it were the Constitution or the law?

 

      And here, I think it just comes down to whether originalism, the original meaning of Article III, and the judicial power at least authorizes, if not requires, adherence to these adjudicatory rules like party presentation and stare decisis. And here we have a real disagreement among originalists on the Supreme Court. You have Justice Alito, who has argued that both party presentation principle and stare decisis are rooted in the original meaning of the judicial power that when Article III was ratified, it did not create ex nihilo, the judicial power. But it was instead relying on a prior understanding of how judges adjudicate cases. And that included party presentation and stare decisis.

 

      And so, that was just part of the original meaning baked into Article III's conception of the judicial power. Justice Thomas takes a different view of the original meaning of Article III. He has argued that stare decisis, at least in any robust form, is inconsistent with the original meaning of Article III's judicial power. And, in his own practice, and his own jurisprudence, at least, Justice Thomas has embraced a much weaker understanding of the party presentation principle than Justice Alito. He's much more willing to depart from party presentation than Justice Alito is.

 

      And, in my own work, I've argued that if you just pay attention to those two principles, they will explain the vast majority of the disagreements between Justice Alito and Justice Thomas in any given case where Justice Thomas might be applying the original meaning and Justice Alito is applying some non-originalist precedent. It is almost always because of one of those two principles or both of those principles coming into play. But notice that the disagreement between Justice Alito and Justice Thomas is a disagreement about the original meaning, the original meaning of Article III, and is, therefore, an inter-originalist disagreement.

 

      So, to the extent that you think that it's plausible to argue that Justice Alito is correct about these two principles being rooted in the original meaning of Article III, then it's also plausible to think that an originalist Supreme Court might adjudicate most cases that come before it in any given term under non-originalist precedent and be faithful to originalism in the process.

 

      So the simple thesis is just overlooking some very important distinctions and some important conceptual points and historical points that have to be taken into account as part of evaluating whether the Court is being originalist or not in any given term because these two principles are at least plausibly supported by the original meaning. Thanks very much.

 

Prof. Richard Fallon:  So, thank you very much, Judge Rao. Thank you very much to The Federalist Society for inviting me to be here today. I am not somebody usually associated with The Federalist Society. I expect the reason that I have been invited is because I've got circulating, on SSRN, a paper that will be out soon on what I call "selective originalism." So I've been thinking about the question to what extent is the Supreme Court an originalist Supreme Court?

 

      And at a time when the Supreme Court is more conservative than it has been at previous times during my lifetime, I've also been concerned with to what extent is the Supreme Court more conservative than originalist. To what extent is originalism actually driving what the Court does? And, as I set out to work on this paper, I've learned an enormous amount. And I've learned an enormous amount thanks to people who are here on this panel, from Randy Barnett, both what he's written and what he's communicated to me orally, Joel and Steve Sachs as well. 

 

      So, with that, by way of background, let me say when I set out to write the paper, I set out with a somewhat simpleminded thesis, as Joel would characterize it — not uncharitably, I think — the simpleminded thesis that if somebody is an originalist and a justice of the Supreme Court, the originalist justice is somebody who thinks that the Supreme Court should decide all or nearly all of its constitutional cases based on the original meaning of the Constitution. And to explore whether that was the way that justices actually went about their business, I pursued the simpleminded methodology that Joel signaled as a possibility.

 

      And that was, with the help of a research assistant, I looked at all of the Supreme Court's cases for its 2021 term. The Court decided 60 cases. Most of those did not involve constitutional questions, as Randy says we should expect. He's very right about that. But twenty-two of them did. And, of the twenty-two that did, only five of them contained what seemed to me fairly describable as an originalist rationale for decision. And there are other high-profile cases: the recent Harvard affirmative action case, where you see that the justices of the Supreme Court in the majority pay almost no attention to the original meaning.

 

      So, at that point, I would have been -- before I was educated, as I have been educated by Joel and by Steve, I would have been prepared to say, "Well, we have a Supreme Court that's much more conservative than it is originalist. And so, what are we to make of all this originalist talk? How much restraint does it have?" But now I am persuaded by Joel and by Steve — I think Steve made the point to me before Joel did, so fair credit to Steve for helping me with this — that it's perfectly consistent with some versions of originalism for somebody to say, "I'm an originalist, but I also believe in stare decisis. And I also believe in the party presentation principle."

 

      And I didn't have a good methodology for gauging to what extent the individual justices are faithful to their own versions of originalism, which would give an either greater or lesser role to the party presentation principle and stare decisis. But I must say, my own instinct is to think — instinct supported by some reasons I'll try to sketch briefly — that there is some element of convenience in the way that the justices invoke -- some of the justices. I will certainly agree that Justice Thomas is more consistent than the other justices, and I'm inclined to think Justice Gorsuch second-most.

 

      But I think there's some degree of convenience in the way that they are invoked, with respect to stare decisis. Because stare decisis actually is a weak restraint on the Supreme Court when they want to overrule cases. And it is very, very rare that you find justices of the Supreme Court following precedent and saying, "Stare decisis made me do it." So, if we were just talking about stare decisis, I think we could see a lot more overruling by justices of the Supreme Court than we see. But, of course, it's not only stare decisis. There's stare decisis, plus the party presentation principle.

 

      But then, when we think about the party presentation principle, we know that there are a number of cases in which the Court, including its originalist justices, don't adhere to the party presentation principle. They rewrite the questions that have been posed for cert. They ask the justices to brief issues that haven't been briefed by the parties. And I am inclined to think that when the justices abide by the party presentation principle, most of the time, it's because they're happy enough with the way that the issues are being presented to them under the circumstances.

 

      As Randy points out, extensive originalist research is really hard to do. Answers to questions may not have emerged yet. And there may be a variety of reasons of prudence to observe the party presentation principle most of the time. But if the justices don't want to observe it, they don't have to, and they don't. And originalist justices could observe it a great deal less often than they do. So I think we've got a Supreme Court that, for the time being, is more methodologically pluralist and conservative than it is originalist.

 

      But — and I will do this very quickly, because I don't want to run over my time — there are other possibilities about what's going on with the Supreme Court. As Randy says, there's a knowledge gap. We can't know exactly what they're thinking. Certainly, one possibility — and I think this may be an idea that I've taken from Joel as well — one possibility is that the conservative originalist justices may be doing something like trying to manage a transition to originalism. And one of the things I learned in the course of researching this project is how terribly difficult good originalism is to do.

 

      And the idea that there could be what Larry Solum has called "an originalist big bang" would seem to be a crazy idea from the perspective of sensible judicial administration. So, maybe what's going on is an effort to work out some sort of transition principles on the fly, in a situation in which there is not, that I am aware of, much good articulation of what those transition principles would be, so that we would know whether the justices were actually pursuing that in a faithful way.

 

      And another possibility is that the justices really just are more conservative than they are originalist. But I don't want to rule out the transition hypothesis. And I see I'm at nine minutes and thirteen seconds. Thirteen seconds over. Thank you for your attention.

 

Prof. Stephen E. Sachs:  Thank you to Judge Rao, to The Federalist Society for having me, and to all of you for coming to listen. "How Originalist is the Supreme Court?" In my view, the answer is "more than you might think." And it's getting better all the time. So, I will not deny, in presenting this sunny outlook, that in many cases and in many areas, the Court's decisions have strayed from what originalism might otherwise require. I think that's true in the Fourth Amendment area, in the area of the Sixth Amendment, of the Eighth Amendment, of the Fourteenth Amendment, of all the other amendments, of Articles I - VI, maybe VII. I don't know.

 

      But what I do want to point out is that, despite all of these departures, as Judge Posner, no particular friend to originalism, wrote decades ago, "Originalism was and is the orthodox mode of legal justification. And, in fact, even in practice, the justices are doing better than one might think. But to see this, we need to recognize four distinctions. First, the difference between reasoning and results. Second, the difference between a rule and its applications. Third, the difference between pursuing the original law and merely the original meaning. And fourth, the difference between originalism as a standard or as a method, as a destination or as a route.

 

      And when we draw these distinctions, we can see that originalism is not only central to the activities of the Supreme Court, but they're really no worse at it than they are at everything else that they do. So, like the person who is a vegetarian, not because he loves animals, but because he hates plants, I take this view not because I am an optimist about originalism, but because I am a pessimist about everything else done by the courts.

 

      So, let us start with the sense of departure from originalism. You can think that there are occasional denunciations of what might seem like originalism, even from the justices of the Supreme Court. I'm thinking, in particular here, of the joint dissent in Dobbs, which strenuously criticized the attempt to look to the 19th century, or even as far back as the 13th century for the rules governing our current rights. But, even the Dobbs dissenters gave originalism its due. In a crucial passage they argued that the framers, both in 1788 and 1868, understood that the world changes.

 

      So they did not define rights by reference to the specific practices existing at that time. Instead, the framers defined rights in general terms, to permit future evolution in their scope and meaning. Note the claim being made here. Not that we, today, define rights in general terms, but that they did. That is a historical claim. Indeed, that is an originalist claim. If, as an original matter, the due process clause was not defined to permit future evolution in its scope and meaning, then the argument of the Dobbs dissent is wrong. In other words, the dissenting justices' reasoning made them vulnerable to history, to refutation on historical grounds.

 

      And, indeed, one sees this throughout the jurisprudence of the Supreme Court, even in cases that are not particularly thought of as originalist. One sees it in Obergefell. One sees it in confirmation testimony. One sees it across both sides of the judicial aisle, so to speak. And the idea that the Court relies on originalist reasoning of this kind does not mean it does so well, or that it reliably arrives at correct originalist results. But looking to originalist reasoning is, indeed, the first step.

 

      Now, I recognize that these attempts to look to original reasoning might sometimes point us to claims about allowed means of change, that the founders wrote language capable of growth, and so on. But that idea is hardly surprising, once we distinguish between a rule and its applications. As Chris Green has pointed out, beyond the First Congress, the original Constitution did not spell out how many representatives each state would get. Instead, it made that depend on a future enumeration. And it didn't fix the size of the Senate. It said to take whatever the number of states turns out to be and multiply by two.

 

      In other words, it laid down fixed rules which were to be applied consistently over time to changing facts, until the rules themselves might be amended. This is not a license for judges to depart from whatever rules are fixed in the Constitution. It is a decision to fix particular rules that may or may not allow for particular degrees of lawful change. And that is how it is understood. So when Justice Kagan differentiates between occasions on which the Constitution lays down broad principles or specific rules, that is making an original claim about the nature of the rule laid down and whether it applies broadly to current facts or in a more restrictive way.

 

      And today it is common ground among judges of virtually all stripes that you cannot go into court and "Yes, Your Honor, our position is contrary to the rule that the original Constitution laid down, but we added a constitutional amendment in 1937 that just changed everything." You cannot admit that the rule in the original Constitution is against you, that the rules laid down back then do not allow for the outcome you want, even as applied to modern facts. Now, sometimes, of course, the Supreme Court does not base its decision on the rules laid down back then in the text.

 

      Sometimes, as Professor Alicea has noted, it bases its decision on rules found outside the text, like precedent, or waiver, or res judicata. But that does not mean the justices are being bad originalists. They may be. But that doesn't mean that. There's a difference between the original meaning of the text and what originalists really ought to be after, which is the original law. After all, what makes the text of the U.S. Constitution relevant, and not the text of the Articles of Confederation or the Virginia Plan or the draft of the Committee of Detail, or whatever else, is that it was actually part of the law back then and remains part of the law today.

 

      But there are a lot of things that were part of the law back then. And they may not outrank or override the Constitution. But they may coexist with and help define the scope of its legal rules, things like the doctrines of the common law or the principles of equity or the rules of admiralty in maritime jurisdiction and so on. And all these doctrines and rules and principles can matter in constitutional litigation. So, if you have a knock-down originalist argument about the original meaning of the First Amendment, that does not matter in our legal system if you forgot to raise that argument in the district court.

 

      And that is not because the judges are breaking the law or being non-originalist. It's because they are obeying the law. And the law contains a common law rule of waiver, which requires you to present your arguments at the earliest opportunity. Likewise, you can have an excellent originalist argument, but lose because of res judicata or because of issue preclusion, having previously brought and lost another case. And you can also lose because of another common law doctrine of stare decisis, which, sometimes, under certain circumstances, instructs courts to leave past decisions in place.

 

      So I, here, am borrowing from Caleb Nelson, who argues that the rule of stare decisis, as it existed at the founding, and as it seems to have continued, in large part, until very recently, is that it was an epistemic rule, that if the evidence is 51/49, and a prior court, also made up of smart people, went the other way, you should let it go, even if you think they were probably wrong. But, if they were demonstrably wrong, if you can explain the nature of their error and show what the correct answer ought to be, then you may have to apply the correct rule, and not what past judges have said about it, unless, according to the common law rule, certain specific considerations of reliance apply. 

 

      If all this is right, then it's much easier to understand what's going on in the majority opinion in Dobbs, which has been criticized for its lack of consistency with originalism. It does not toss substantive due process into the dustbin of history. It does not revive the privileges or immunities clause. It simply keeps on going with the Glucksberg history and tradition test. And that is partly because, in Dobbs, both sides acknowledged the authority of Glucksberg, and neither side asked the Court to overrule it.

 

      So, it is hardly surprising, given all of these common law rules, which are also part of our law, that the Supreme Court might have dutifully gone ahead and Glucksberged. That does not mean that precedent is more important than constitutional rules. It merely means that when the Court sits down to decide a case, there are lots of legal rules in play, all of which can be consistent with the original law, and lawful changes thereunder, even if they might direct a court away from discussing the original meaning of the text.

 

      Now, of course, a court can still get the original law wrong. And maybe courts do that quite often. I would say that courts very often adhere not to the Constitution of the United States, but to a much higher and more powerful law, Sturgeon's law, which is that 90 percent of everything is crap. Judges, like everyone else, find it easy to slip into motivated reasoning, to assume that what the answer is and what the answer ought to be are the same thing. They do this with the Constitution. They do this with statutes. They do this with treaties. They do this with common law. They do this with the nature of public policy issues, and so and so forth.

 

      And if you have read any law reviews lately, or have not, I will let you in on a secret. Academics do this too. But our errors are easy to ignore because they go into law reviews, which drop stillborn from the press, whereas judges' errors decide actual cases. And, especially when you have lots of precedents on the books and lots of discretion on which cases you take, it is easy to avoid confronting your errors. So how do we deal with this? The answer, I think, is to recognize that originalism is a standard and not a method, a destination and not a route.

 

      If James Madison quotes could ward off constitutional error like garlic wards off vampires, then we would want to see opinions littered with Madison quotes everywhere. But if citing the right sources does not guarantee that you're using them well, if the devil can cite Publius for his purpose, then we can't tell from the number of Madison quotes who the good originalists are.

 

      But if we think about originalism as the destination, and not the route, we can see the glass half full. We can understand and forgive the human frailty in reaching incorrect conclusions, of which judges are no more guilty than anyone else, but still pursue the goal of correct original analysis. We know, for instance, that juries make lots of mistakes. But we don't think that's an excuse for them to throw up their hands and say, "I don't know. He looks guilty to me." Likewise, we know that judges make mistakes. But that doesn't give us a reason for them to do anything other than grit their teeth and say, "Maybe next year." So, with that hope, thank you.

 

Hon. Neomi Rao:  Great. Thank you all for your comments. Maybe we can begin where Professor Sachs left off about error costs in originalism. And I'm wondering — and this was touched on in a number of the remarks — but how do the concerns about the possibility of error affect whether the court becomes sort of fully originalist or truly originalist? Is there just an epistemological problem? Like, if we could just know the original meaning, then everyone should be an originalist? 

 

      A frequent criticism is that the court is doing originalism wrong, they're getting the history wrong. There's been a lot of discussion about Bruen, for instance. Maybe we can talk about that. But I guess I'm just interested in the other panelists' thoughts about how the reality of error and the fact that we're all human, judges too, does that undermine originalism? Does it make it harder to practice? What do you think about that? Randy, maybe we'll start with you.

 

Prof. Randy E. Barnett:  Sure. Well, we're all imperfect. And every methodology has error costs. So, originalism isn't special in that regard. The question, I suppose, if you're going to pose the question in terms of error costs, is how high are the error costs associated with trying to identify the original public meaning of a document at a particular point in time is, as compared with how to, on the fly, devise a better Constitution that a particular judge or justice might want to see implemented?

 

      I would think that assuming that the meaning of the original Constitution is good enough to be legitimate — which is a separate subject — I believe that depends, in part, on the substance of what any particular Constitution says, as well as how it's adopted. Assuming that's true, I think the error costs of trying to stick with that meaning, trying to identify that meaning, is not as high as trying to allow judges to devise their own meaning, or to do it on the fly. But I want to complicate it by the kind of analysis I presented in my talk, which is to say, I think the way you implement original meaning is to devise implementing doctrines. And they, themselves, are not part of the original meaning.

 

      And that's a more difficult enterprise, developing constitutional doctrines that will guide lower courts and guide administrative agencies, guide together branches, etc., and guide future Supreme Courts as to how to decide cases. And there are errors that are going to be happening at that level. But that's not at the level of identifying original meaning. It's identifying what's faithful to original meaning. And, again, I would say, that's a more doable, less error-prone task than trying just to devise implementing doctrines that the justices or judges themselves think are going to lead to a better society. 

 

Hon. Neomi Rao:  Joel?

 

Prof. J. Joel Alicea:  I think that originalism does pose a particular challenge in this regard because, when faithfully applied, it is easier to tell when an originalist opinion is just doing it wrong, than a non-originalist opinion because it's based on historical facts and interpretation of historical documents. And so, you should be able to call out an opinion as being good or bad originalism easier than a non-originalist opinion that is often based on considerations that are not as readily identifiable.

 

      So, in that sense, it makes originalism more vulnerable to this objection, notwithstanding Randy's correct point about all methodologies are vulnerable to this objection. That tendency, I think, is ameliorated or exacerbated, depending on a methodological question, which is what standard do you have, as an originalist, of proof before you're comfortable adopting a view as the original meaning?

 

      So, John McGinnis, Michael Stokes Paulson and others have argued the duty of clarity at the founding that it’s part of the judicial power, part of the understanding of Article III, where you can only adopt a particular understanding of the Constitution when it is clear that that's the understanding. So, I don't know what that percentage would be, 60 percent or 65 percent evidence, as opposed to 51/49,

 

      But Michael Rappaport has argued that 51/49 is the right way to think about it. Well, that makes Michael Rappaport's view a little more vulnerable to this problem than, say, John McGinnis's view, because he's just less likely to be proven wrong in a subsequent case. So, I think there are methodological questions that are tied into how significant this problem is.

 

Prof. Richard H. Fallon:  At this point in our constitutional history, it seems to me the way that originalism most often operates is as a ground for overruling precedent. If you think about the historical origins of originalism, a lot of the original impetus for the development of originalism was to develop a theory that would explain why a number of liberal precedents that had arisen — beginning in 1937, and then under the Warren Court — weren't necessarily written in constitutional stone, more or less in perpetuity.

 

      So, the impulse behind originalism, and the way that originalist arguments are most often wheeled out before the Supreme Court, is to provide a basis for departing from precedent. So, in response to when Randy says "Originalism compared with what? With just making it up?" I think the realistic answer to "Originalism compared with what?" is either sticking with or tinkering with precedent, in some minor way.

 

      So then, I fear I'm repeating myself here, but what an originalist decision is most likely to do, as a practical matter, is to affect some substantial change in the law from the way that it was before. And substantial changes are riskier than changes that are less substantial. And it would provide a reason, to my way of thinking, even for originalists to be cautious about saying "We've got it all figured out," one of the issues that Randy has raised a couple of times.

 

      But, yes, I think that's what's distinctive about originalism, in practice. It usually is asking for constitutional innovations measured against the baseline of the current day. The changes are risky. They might turn out to be terrific. They might turn out to be terrible. And that would be a reason to be more cautious about going forward with originalist reasoning — absent strong, strong, confidence — than might be the case with precedent-based reasoning, which I think is the real alternative.

 

Stephen E. Sachs:  What I would say is that judges make two kinds of decisions. They make decisions about the law. And they also make decisions about political morality or, sort of, what somebody in their position, with their kinds of powers and their contacts should actually do. So, if you think about something like how should I structure my docket, sometimes there are legal considerations there, like the law says you have to put criminal cases first.

 

      But, often, there are no legal considerations. It's just a question of how do you best use that space on your docket? How much time should I take? How many briefs should I read? With what level of detail? How many times should I go over them? How much independent research should I do? All of these are questions with no particular legal answer. The law just is whatever it is. And yet, the human beings who occupy the role of judge or justice have a lot of other considerations at hand that they've got to figure out.

 

      I see error costs as in that second category, that there are questions about what somebody in their position should do, overall, as a matter of political morality. The existence or non-existence of error costs doesn't change whatever the law is. If there's some really obscure provision in the Constitution and it has some historical meaning, whatever it is, that doesn't change depending on the error costs. But it might be that error costs might advise the judge to use their discretion in various ways, or to spend more or less time worrying about something in a particular way.

 

      It may be that a doctrine includes some sense of error costs. It may be, for example, that stare decisis doctrine cares about reliance, in some way. But that would, in some ways, be fortuitous. It would be lucky for us. I mean, it would be not accidental. But it would be nice if the law considered that, in some way. But there's no guarantee that it will, or that the true legal answer is not something that would have enormous error costs if you get it even slightly wrong. Or, for that matter, if you get it correct. 

 

Hon. Neomi Rao:  I have a number of other questions. But if you would like to ask questions of the panelists, you can start to go to the mics. So, the Supreme Court, in some cases, seeks to implement originalism by asking whether some type of modern regulation has a historical analog or a common law analog. We saw this is Bruen, of course, with the Second Amendment and in TransUnion, with respect to standing, whether Congress can create an injury, whether that has a common law or historical analog. So, I'm wondering what you think about that particular approach. Is looking for a historical analog a good way of doing originalism? Is it appropriate? Helpful?

 

Prof. J. Joel Alicea:  Randy's pointing at me because I've defended something like this in writing.

 

Prof. Randy E. Barnett:  Mister historical analog.

 

Prof. J. Joel Alicea:  So, I do think it depends. And my own thinking on this is still developing, but I do think it depends on what the context is. So, I am a defender of original expected applications in identifying the original meaning of the Constitution.

 

      And that does mean that, insofar as you have some sort of extant phenomenon at the time of ratification, and you have reason to think that those, at the time, would not have considered this part of the right, either because they affirmatively prohibited the thing in question, like Dobbs, affirmatively prohibiting abortion in widespread fashion in 1868 and in the immediate aftermath of that, or because they choose not to incorporate something into the right through protections, and you have reason to think that that was based on some sort of constitutional consideration, as opposed to social factors or something. Then, that seems like pretty powerful, if not dispositive evidence of original meaning.

 

      I think the strongest argument against a historical analog test is when it's used in a situation where you could plausibly explain the absence of a historical analog, not based on constitutional concerns or a conception of the right but based on some sort of just social factors or other political theory reasons. So, this came up just this past week in Rahimi, when there was a discussion about whether the absence of any sort of analog of restrictions on domestic abusers having the right to keep and bear arms, is that because there was a conception that that was somehow a violation of the Second Amendment?

 

      Or, perhaps more plausibly, was it, because of the social dynamics at that time, a conception of the government's role in intervening in domestic relations in that way? And so, if it's the latter, well, then, the fact that there wasn't a law on the books at that time specifically relating to domestic abuse doesn't really say very much about the meaning of the Second Amendment. So, I think that it's a more nuanced question than just should we look for historical analogs or not. I think it depends a lot on what the context is in which you're asking the question. 

 

Prof. Randy E. Barnett:  I have mixed feelings about the historical analogs test. Let me begin by saying I'm a gun owner, and I'm a concealed carry permit holder, and in the state of Florida, I will say. I did, actually, used to have my D.C. carry permit. But since I don't live here anymore, and I'm not going to carry here, I don't have my permit here anymore. So, any doctrine, any implementing doctrine that makes it harder to deprive me of my right to keep and bear arms, I'm for. 

 

      And, to the extent that the historical analogs test seems to have that effect, it makes it harder to sustain gun laws. On policy grounds, I tend to be in favor of this. But I'm ambivalent. There's actually an ambiguity as to what function the historical analogs test is being used for. If it's being used and it's the way Joel just defended it — properly, I think — if it's being used to identify the original contours of the right to keep and bear arms, based, in part, on evidence provided by original expected applications, then I think it's being used properly. 

 

      In the earlier panel today on the Second Amendment here, that is how it was being characterized. And I think that's right. For example, if the original right to freedom of speech did not include the right to defame somebody or the right to commit fraud, that tells us something. And early legislation confirms that, or the common law. That tells us something about the original scope of the right. I'm all for that. 

 

      But, however you define the original scope of the right, whatever the conclusion is, I do believe constitutional rights can be regulated. I hesitate to say, "reasonably regulated" because the devil is in the details of reasonableness. But I'll just say regulated in good faith. That will maybe get us one step closer. And because of that, historical analogs could be playing a second role. It could be playing the role of an implementing doctrine.

 

      Rather than telling us what the original scope of the amendment is, it's the way, given the scope of the amendment. Here's a rule that will more faithfully implement the doctrine, if you have to find a legislative analog. You have to find a legislative example. And that's where I'm a little more ambivalent. I'm a little more ambivalent about whether the presence or absence of a particular kind of regulation, of the right to keep and bear arms at the founding, is dispositive about whether such a regulation might be appropriate today, given the state of technologies and other things that may have evolved ever since.

 

      I'm ambivalent. I'm prepared to say, "Yes, for sure, if it actually is going to the original scope of the right, and "maybe yes" and "maybe no" as an implementing doctrine in an effort to enforce or apply the original meaning to a particular statute that is being proposed.

 

Hon. Neomi Rao:  Do you guys want to respond?

 

Prof. Stephen E. Sachs:  I just want to quickly -- some of the thoughts. I think it matters tremendously what the analog's being used for. So, I think what you do not want is to be in the position of saying, "Well, the founders didn't ban chewing gum between the hours of 7:00 and 9:00 on Tuesdays, ergo there is a Constitutional right to chew gum between the hours of 7:00 and 9:00 on Tuesdays." And, honestly, I think that some of the amicus briefs in Dobbs sounded a lot like that. 

 

      The problem is that what we're trying to capture here is the content of an unwritten rule. And for that, we want to know not just what did or didn't they do, but what did they say about it? Why did they do, or not do? When they talked about why they were doing or not doing a particular thing, were they invoking constitutional rules of one kind or another, other considerations that, as we understand it, would be constitutionally relevant? So, I think that the search for historical analogs can be very important. It's how we understand the content of the common law, as of a particular time, for example.

 

      Sometimes we have to do that even with modern cases. So, if we're trying to do an ex post facto analysis, like, what was the law of Florida as of 1957, sometimes, we kind of need to look at a lot of cases that don't clearly spell it out. But we should be looking for the analogs, not for their own sake, but to try and fit them into a more general picture of what were the legal rules in operation at the time? And what status did they have?

 

Hon. Neomi Rao:  Okay. Did you want to jump in, Richard?

 

Prof. Richard H. Fallon:  Yeah. I would just say quickly that I think I agree with nearly everything that has been said. But I have some skepticism too, about whether, in the long run, it's prudent or even possible to abandon some standard along the lines of strict judicial scrutiny.

 

      I think that, in thinking about what the historical analog is, the appropriate question may often be is something that the government is considering regulating now analogous in the scope or seriousness of the threat it poses to something that would have been accepted as permissibly regulable at some point in the past, even in the absence of relatively fine factual similarity? And I am fearful about the way the test is often talked about, that the focus is too much on fine factual similarity and insufficiently on comparative gravity of the danger posed.

 

Prof. Randy Barnett:  I just want to add one thing, because I'm very sympathetic to what Dick just said. But I think it's really important, in suggesting that strict scrutiny is appropriate, to deny the claim that strict scrutiny equals interest balancing. I don't want this panel to devolve into a debate about that. But it could conceivably be done in an interest-balancing way. But it doesn’t have to be. It could be just a means of smoking out pretext by finding an insufficient fit between means and ends, in which case, it might be an improper regulation. So, I just want to suggest that just equating strict scrutiny with interest balancing is a questionable move. 

 

Hon. Neomi Rao:  Great. Okay, we'll take a question from the front mic to start. If you can all just keep your questions as actual questions, that would be great. Thanks.

 

Questioner 1:  Thank you to the panel for an excellent discussion. Professor Fallon, you spoke of the concern for managing the transition to originalism. And I'm curious if the panel thinks that the Court might become more boldly originalist if they could — especially as concerns overturning erroneous precedent — stay or delay the implementation of their decisions for a certain period of time, say, to give states and Congress the opportunity to adapt past laws protecting reliance interests, or, a crazy idea, revive the Article V amendment process. 

 

      For example, if the Court were willing to overturn Miranda but delay implementation for a year to give states the opportunity to preserve the Miranda Warning under state law. Professor Barnett, I think you've written on this topic. Do you think that this is a constitutionally valid maneuver? And, if so, is it an advisable one?

 

Prof. Richard H. Fallon:  So, I think John McGinnis has proposed this. And so, it's out there to be debated about, as among the possible ways to transition to originalism. My own view would be the, perhaps, very often, the best reason to delay a transition to originalist results — for somebody who otherwise was firmly committed to the idea that our Constitutional law should be originalist — would be the idea that we want to be very sure we've got the original meaning right before we destabilize something that hasn't been disastrous, replace it with something totally new, at risk, that, in two or three years, other scholarship is going to reveal that this was a misstep.

 

      And so, I take it that the proposal that you're floating is one that a court would implement upon having reached a careful, considered, "We're just about as sure as we can be that this is the right rule. But we think we're going to allow a little bit of time to implement it." I don't know, totally, what I think about this. And I'd actually be very curious to know what Steve thinks about this, in terms of what Steve thinks about this from the perspective of original law, and so forth. 

 

      It does put a court in something that people once would have been very quick to deride as a quasi-legislative role that we're going to say this is what the rule is, but we're going to hold to ourselves the responsibility to make a quite other rule about when the real rule that we think, ideally, would be governing, actually ought to be put into practice. Can we postpone it for a decade? Can we postpone it for five years? Can we postpone it for a year? Can we postpone it for two?

 

      So, I think I'm a Burkian conservative by disposition. And this makes me a little bit nervous. But if I knew more about it — and that's why I say, genuinely, I'd be curious to know what Steve can tell me about the history and so forth — I don't regard myself as having an utterly closed mind to it.

 

Prof. Stephen E. Sachs:  So, I can't say that I have any particular expertise. What I can say is that if one thinks about stare decisis as a common law principle, then there are two things to observe. One, courts have common law powers over their own docket. So, Marathon Pipe Line happened. You could imagine the Supreme Court saying, "We think this is the correct rule, but we are just holding our mandate for two years. And any case we get, we're going to hold that one too. And we just think that this is a good way of doing it."

 

      Maybe they have. Maybe that would be a proper exercise of their existing powers. I'm not sure. What I do know -- well, I can't say "know," but what I don't suspect is that, with regard to common law or statutory stare decisis, it would surely be within the powers of Congress to say, "If this is just a common law rule, we can override it by statute." And, whereas constitutional stare decisis might — John Harrison has written about this — maybe it would be a little bit less amenable to congressional sort of monkeying.

 

      But they could definitely say, in a statutory case, if the Supreme Court thinks they have misread our actual statute, "Then do the Marathon Pipe Line thing. Here's a procedure to follow." Announce that you'll hold the result for two years. And we'll have an election in between. And we'll figure out if we care about it enough. And, if not, the actual statutory rule will then take over."

 

       Honestly, I'd rather see that than Flood v. Kuhn. I think that it would be better, in certain ways, for a court to say, not, "We are going to preserve, inviolate, something the Congress never enacted. But, rather, "We will actually follow the statutory rule on the books. And we have various powers over the transition period." But I think the easiest, cleanest case would be to see Congress actually pass some procedural statute saying, "Here's what should happen in such a case."

 

Prof. Randy E. Barnett:  I just wanted to say something about transitioning: the fact that how to transition to a more originalist practice would be a separate panel and should be a separate panel at some future Federalist Society conference. And it's a difficult question.

 

      But this brings us back to the party presentation point made by both Steve and Joel earlier. If the parties are looking at a Supreme Court at which one, two, or possibly three Justices are prepared to question precedent on the basis of original meaning, they're not likely to present much originalist argument to that court because, as one experienced Supreme Court litigator once told me, "When originalism is for my client, I'm an originalist. When originalism is against my client, not so much."

 

      So, when they are looking at a Court that is not going to entertain reversing precedent, then they're not going to present the Court that argument. And, therefore, you're in a vicious circle. Party presentation is fine. I'm for a party presentation restriction. But it would be nice if the Supreme Court advertised that parties should present those requests. In McDonald, the Court was asked to reverse Slaughter-House, and they declined. In Raich, I can tell you, I asked the Court to reverse Wickard, if it was necessary to rule for us. We didn't think it was. But if it was, we said, "Reverse Wickard." They declined. 

 

      So, you can ask all day long. And that doesn't mean they're going to do anything. So, I'm a little unenthusiastic about the party participation rule as something that's going to tell us much about whether a Court is being originalist or not.

 

Hon. Neomi Rao:  Okay, we'll take a question from the back mic. Thank you.

 

Questioner 2:  Thank you. Just a great panel. Very interesting remarks from everyone. Two quick questions, and we touched on them. One, how originalist does the panel think Dobbs was? What did the Court get wrong, and what did the Court get right? And then, the scope of the party presentation rule, assuming it's originalist, how strong is it if the parties present completely non-originalist arguments, but the judge is convinced the Constitution requires something that none of the parties have said? Is the judge bound to get it wrong? Or can they stray from the party presentation? How strong, what's the limiting principle on party presentation? Thank you.

 

Hon. Neomi Rao:  Okay. And if we can keep our answers a little brief so we can get through a few more questions.

 

Prof. J. Joel Alicea:  I'll just very quickly address the first question, because I've written about it. I think that Dobbs is an originalist opinion in a couple of ways. One is that, as you've said, the parties did not ask the Court to overrule substantive due process doctrine in Dobbs. So, insofar as would adhere to party presentation principle as a matter of original meaning, then there's no problem with just applying Glucksberg as an originalist in that case, and reaching the outcome that the Court reaches.

 

      But, even apart from that question about party presentation, I actually just think that the historical evidence that the Court goes through, insofar as you are an originalist who thinks originalist-expected applications are relevant and potentially dispositive, as I am, I think the historical evidence that they compile in that opinion and the focus on 1868, which the Court repeatedly emphasized in that opinion, really precludes any plausible originalist argument in favor of a right to abortion in Dobbs.

 

      So, the fact that the Court did not march through each of the potential original meanings of various provisions of the Fourteenth Amendment, and every scholar who has given their own view of privileges or immunities before concluding that it's just not covered by the Fourteenth Amendment, the right to abortion, I think, doesn't invalidate the fact that they did prove that, as a matter original meaning, there is no right to abortion.

 

Hon. Neomi Rao:  Anyone else want to weigh in on that? 

 

Prof. Stephen E. Sachs:  On the second point, I am not sure how much of this is still governed by the original law, because there are also other sources of law. So, for example, the Supreme Court rule -- gosh, is it 15.2? It's the one where, so, if you don't make the argument in your bio, you've waived it, or things like that. The Courts have power, under both statute and inherent power, to make rules that require party presentation in various ways. And they have done so. And the result is that now there are pretty severe party presentation requirements.

 

      There's also a difference - and I think this is an originally correct difference, but, certainly, I think it's correct under existing rules — between forfeiture and waiver. And the way I explain it to my civ pro students is that a forfeited argument is sick unto death, and only the healing hand of the Court can revive it like the king's touch curing scrofula, whereas a waived argument has been taken out back and shot.

 

      And so, I think that there are some arguments where you don't raise your personal jurisdiction defense in time, under 12H(h)(1), and you've taken it out back and shot it. And you cannot get it back, and the Court cannot give it to you. That would be error. But they can forgive an awful lot of forfeitures. And so, one very interesting question is what the Courts should have done in the PCAOB case. For full disclosure, I was clerking then, but I have no responsibility for how it actually came out. And the question there was what do you do when there was an unargued question of whether the Securities Exchange commissioners were removable by the president at will? 

 

      And neither side wanted to touch that question: the petitioners, because they wanted to present the issue of a double for-cause restriction cleanly, the government, because they didn't want to say that the FCC was removable at will. And so, the Court just sort of assumed that they were not. I'm not sure, in retrospect, that that's how it should have gone, and that that kind of party presentation commitment was okay. Because I'm not sure that you can assume, contrary to fact, a statutory question that then allows you to get to a constitutional question that both sides are very interested in.

 

Hon. Neomi Rao:  Okay. We'll take a question from the front.

 

Questioner 3:  Thank you to all of you. I very much enjoyed the panel. I found myself very persuaded by Professor Alicea's broad framing of issues. But I also think it places a lot of weight on how the Court uses its discretionary power to shape its own docket. And I could imagine a world in which, in a truly originalist Court, views itself as having a duty to use its cert power to try to get rid of a lot of non-originalist precedent.

 

      And I can imagine a world in which even a truly originalist Court can use its cert power however it wants and doesn't have to think about that at all. And I think those worlds would lead to a vastly different on-the-ground level of non-originalist precedent governing the adjudication of cases. I know Justice Barrett's written a little bit about this as a professor. But I'm curious if any of you have thoughts on how an originalist Court should use its cert power.            

Prof. J. Joel Alicea:  So, I have not thought carefully about that. But I think that Ben Johnson has. He's written about this and is skeptical of the extent to which the Court has really broad discretionary power in determining questions presented and thinking about their docket in that way. So, I commend his scholarship to you on this, since I haven't given it a ton of thought.

 

Prof. Stephen E. Sachs:  All I would say is that I think that there is one requirement that when you're answering a legal question, you do so correctly. And then there's the discretionary question of which legal questions are worth it to answer. And I do think being originalist changes that calculus a little bit. If there are people rotting in jail, who, under your understanding of the Constitution, ought to be free, that ought to be a problem for you, even if you have the discretion to leave them there.

 

Hon. Neomi Rao:  Thank you. Question from the back?

 

Prof. Richard H. Fallon:  Could I say something very quick on that?

 

Hon. Neomi Rao:  Oh, yes.  Sorry, go ahead.

 

Prof. Richard H. Fallon:  I think the cert question is just absolutely fascinating. I think it's absolutely fascinating because it highlights the extent to which the Supreme Court today, for all practical purposes, is primarily a law-making tribunal. It's a lawmaking tribunal in the sense that it chooses cases in which it either thinks the law is likely wrong, so that it, the Supreme Court, would like to change it. Or it thinks the law is unclear and wants to change it by clarifying it.

 

      So, the reason the Court takes cases is to change the law. And it's a part of the Court's enormous lawmaking power today that it has the cert jurisdiction that it has to choose its agenda. And I think that we just don't understand the role of the Supreme Court in modern American life. This is one of the reasons that I'm interested in the extent to which the Court actually decides its cases on the basis of originalism. If we don't understand that it is, in very many and very important ways, a lawmaking tribunal.

 

      And I think that, although the process of nomination and confirmation has caught up with, in many ways, the enormous power that the Justices have, and has begun to think about who should be sitting on the Court and who we would want to be sitting on the Court, in light of that power, I think the question of how Justices would use the cert power is of colossal consequence. 

 

Hon. Neomi Rao:  We'll take a question from the back mic.

 

Gary Lawson:  Hi. Gary Lawson, Boston University. The last comments by Dick Fallon and Steve Sachs totally transformed my question. So, I guess I have to put this one at them now. What is it, exactly, that the Supreme Court or any other federal court -- all right, what is it that the Supreme Court or any federal court actually does when it exercises the judicial power? 

 

      Obviously, it doesn't interpret anything, either originalist or otherwise. It resolves disputes in certain classes of cases or controversies. Can we actually address any of the questions of this panel without knowing the original meaning of a case or controversy? Is it a set of facts and legal norms? Is it a set of arguments presented by the parties? Is the party presentation principle, actually, as a matter or original meaning, part of Article III?

 

Hon. Neomi Rao:  Who would like to start? And I think this will actually have to be our last question. So, if there are any other last-minute remarks you'd like to say wrapping up, too.

 

Prof. Stephen E. Sachs:  I am somewhat agnostic on the scope of cases and controversies. Jim Pfander has a detailed argument that it's sort of different than what we might have thought it was. It's not clear to me that party presentation comes from the idea of cases and controversies. But it might very well be a rule of common law that accompanies and sort of works well with our understanding of cases and controversies. I would just have to say I don't know.

 

Prof. J. Joel Alicea:  I certainly agree, insofar as you're suggesting, Gary, that there are historical questions about the original meaning of Article III that are essential to answering some of the methodological questions that we're discussing. I agree with that entirely, that this isn't a purely abstract question. It will cash out, to some extent, based on what we can find out in the history. 

 

Hon. Neomi Rao:  Randy.

 

Prof. Randy E. Barnett:  Actually, not an answer to this question. But this is our concluding remarks opportunity. I'm a little concerned that everybody who came in here to hear us address this question is going to walk out of here thinking, "Wow, they sure made that complicated." 

 

Hon. Neomi Rao:  I did warn against this.

 

Prof. Randy E. Barnett:  And, let me just say, I think you'd be right to so think. I would like to appeal to your common sense and suggest to you that the view that you came in the door with is probably right, notwithstanding everything you've just heard. And that is, we have a majority of justices who identify as originalists. We have less than a majority of justices who tend to practice originalism.

 

      And it would be better -- and we don't know for sure, because they're not really telling us, they're not showing us their work, whether they're reaching results that are consistent with the original meaning of the Constitution or not. And so, it's sort of "it depends." So, I think that if you came in the room thinking, "Well, it kind of depends on what you mean by 'an originalist Court,'" then you should walk out of the room with that same view.

 

Prof. Richard H. Fallon:  So, could I say I've agreed with Randy about an extraordinary number of things, I think, today. But I disagree with what he just said. Now, I think one of the big messages I would take from this is I think when the ordinary person hears about originalism, it seems intuitive. It seems clear. It's the simple-minded view that justices of the Supreme Court should decide cases based on — virtually all of their constitutional cases — based on the original meaning of the Constitution.

 

      And what comes out of here is that the kinds of originalism with which the justices of the Supreme Court and the members of this panel are overwhelmingly concerned is an extraordinarily complicated lawyers' version of originalism with party presentation principle. What's the party presentation principle? Stare decisis? Stare decisis? I thought the reason to have originalism was we were going to knock over stare decisis, prior cases when they weren't consistent with the original meaning.

 

      And then Steve tells us we have to know lawyers' law, going all the way back to the founding to know how originalism would work. So, for better or for worse, I think the message I would take is that originalism becomes more and more and more complicated all the time, the sort of thing that is only accessible to lawyers.

 

Prof Randy E. Barnett:  You better be careful, or a debate might break out here on this panel. I actually don't think we're disagreeing, Dick. I think that you've just sort of said something like what I said. You're disagreeing with the two people who are sitting on either side of you who have complicated this mess. I think you and I are in basic agreement that originalism is a relatively straightforward thing.

 

Hon. Neomi Rao:  We can't even agree on whether we agree.

 

Prof. Randy E. Barnett:  And then the people who came into this room thinking they knew that simple answer are going to walk out of this room, I believe, holding that same view. And it's right that they should. We actually agree about that, Dick.

 

Prof. Richard H. Fallon:  I disagree. 

 

Hon. Neomi Rao:  Well, now, just as things are getting lively, we do have to adjourn. If you're planning to stay for the Bork lecture, that's going to be starting very soon. So, you can just keep your seats. But if you could also join me in thanking our wonderful panel. 

 

 

4:30 p.m. - 5:30 p.m.
Annual Hon. Robert H. Bork Memorial Lecture

2023 National Lawyers Convention

State & East Rooms
The Mayflower Hotel
1127 Connecticut Avenue NW
Washington, DC 20006

Share

Event Video

Listen & Download

Description

The 2023 National Lawyers Convention will take place November 9-11, 2022 at the Mayflower Hotel in Washington, DC. The topic of the conference is "Originalism on the Ground." The conference will conclude with the annual Hon. Robert H. Bork Memorial Lecture, featuring remarks by Judge Thomas Griffith. The lecture's topic is "Toxic Political Polarization and the Judiciary."

Featuring:

  • Hon. Thomas Griffith, U.S. Court of Appeals, District of Columbia Circuit (ret.)

Speakers

Event Transcript

Dean Reuter:  We’re going to begin, please, if people could find a seat. Welcome back. My name is Dean Reuter still. Still Senior Vice President and General Counsel of The Federalist Society. You can’t hear me? Can you hear me now? Okay. Can you hear me now? The people up front can’t hear me so I hope it’s not too loud for the people in the back. But welcome to the final event of this year’s National Lawyers Convention.

 

      Before we begin, I do want to take a moment to have a moment of silence in observation of Veteran’s Day.

 

[Moment of Silence]

 

      Thank you very much. One business announcement: if you're getting CLE, remember to use the QR code to sign out of CLE. If you fail to do that, you’ll probably be claiming 250 hours of CLE sometime next week.

 

      I wanted to repeat some information I provided this morning since I see so many new faces in the audience. And that is people were asking about the annual dinner and who was in attendance, who wasn’t in attendance. I’m at liberty to tell you there were four justices in attendance at the annual dinner, so no decisions were made, but look for a cert grant in the orders list.

 

      And now I want to say just a brief word, if I could, about The Federalist Society itself and my gratitude for working at The Federalist Society. It’s one of the best jobs ever in one of the greatest organizations in town and in the country, and that is because of the people in this room. It is because of The Federalist Society members, which I think everyone recognizes as the true strength of the organization. Even when we were a smaller organization, it was about numbers and it was about networks, and it’s about our business model, where there are very few of us in the home office, but it’s all the members who get everything done. So thank you for being a member of The Federalist Society.

 

      I want to describe one problem The Federalist Society has never had, even when it was small. By way of demonstrating this, this is a little story. This story describes a different kind of convention than The Federalist Society, and a single speaker at this hypothetical convention was speaking, and there was only one person in the audience. Now as he was reaching the end of his remarks, this speaker said, “If you don’t mind, I’m going to skip the Q&A and head straight to the airport so I can catch my flight.” And the lone person in the audience said, “Actually, I do mind. I’m the next speaker.”

 

[Laughter]

 

      So thankfully, we’ve never ever had that sort of problem here at The Federalist Society.

 

      And now I will let you know that we’re very pleased, so pleased, to host the annual Robert H. Bork Memorial Lecture. Judge Bork, of course, is remembered for his outsized impact in many areas of law discussed throughout the panels held over the last couple of days and talked about through the year, actually, at The Federalist Society. His impact in the fields of administrative law and regulation, antitrust, and many more will never fade, and his commitment to originalism—the theme of this year’s convention—will never be forgotten. A friend of The Federalist Society, Judge Bork memory and legacy endure within this organization. And we’re so pleased to carry on the tradition of taking some meaningful time to recognize his contributions to us and to the country through this important lecture.

 

      Before we head into the next installment of this important lecture series, I’ll briefly direct your attention to the pamphlet that should have been on everyone’s seat. These pamphlets, made possible by the generous support of Mary Ellen Bork, are the published version of the remarks delivered at last year’s Bork lecture by the Honorable A. Raymond Randolph, who provided what I thought was an excellent biographical look at Judge Bork and his legacy, which is well worth reading.

 

      Now I’ll take a moment to welcome members of the Bork family. We’re very pleased to have his wife Mary Ellen Bork here and her brother. We welcome also his son, Bob Bork, and grandson, Robert Bork III. Thank you for being here.

 

[Applause]

 

      And of course, we are honored to host as our speaker for today’s lecture, the Honorable Thomas B. Griffith, for his address entitled, “Toxic Political Polarization and the Judiciary.” Judge Griffith served on the United States Court of the Appeals for the D.C. Circuit Court from his appointment in 2005 until he stepped down in 2020, and as a former judge, he’s uniquely qualified to discuss this important and timely issue. If you’re not already familiar with our esteemed final speaker, I’ll give you a brief introduction before yielding the stage.

 

      Former Judge Griffith currently serves as a lecturer on law at Harvard Law School, a fellow at the Wheatley Institute at Brigham Young University, and special counsel in the Washington D.C. office of the law firm Hunton Andrews Kurth. Most recently, he was a member of President Biden’s Commission on the Supreme Court. And he is the author of Civic Charity and the Constitution. Before being appointed to the D.C. Circuit, Judge Griffith was the general counsel at BYU, senate legal counsel, and a partner at Wiley Rein & Fielding, all at different times I assume.

 

      Long active in rule of law programs in former communist nations, he’s a member of the International Advisory Board of the CEELI Institute in Prague. He’s a graduate of BYU and the University of Virginia School of Law and is a member of the American Law Institute. Judge Griffith, thanks so much for joining us today. The stage is yours.

 

Hon. Thomas B. Griffith:  Thank you very much, Dean. Mrs. Bork, Bob Bork, Robert Bork III, members of the Bork family, I see some of my former colleagues here, Judge Bea and Judge Hardiman, there may be others that I can’t see, it’s an honor to be here. I’m honored to be able to speak, especially, in a lecture series that honors the memory of Judge Robert Bork. You know, we’re all indebted to Ed Whelan for his confirmation tales column. Forgive me in my self-indulgence in telling you my story. And I tell it not because it features me, although truth be told, that’s part of the reason I’m telling it, but I tell it to you because it features Judge Bork prominently.

 

      Although it was a far from pleasant experience, my Senate confirmation experience was smooth sailing compared to the tempestuous proceedings others have endured, and for that, I’m grateful. In fact, I was surprised that I was not asked some hard questions, which in hindsight seem indispensable to the Senate properly performing its constitutional duty to give the president advice and consent on his judicial nominations. For example, I should have been asked my views on how a judge ought to interpret the Constitution. Are you an originalist, a legal realist, a believer in the living Constitution? I should have been asked how a judge ought to read statutes. Do you favor Eskridge’s dynamic interpretation or are you a textualist? Or I should have been asked on my view of the role of regulations. Is Chevron deference an abdication of the judicial role or a properly deferential response to a delegation of legislative power from the Congress to the executive branch? I was asked none of those things. In fact, I don’t remember being asked a question along any of those lines. Except one. That question came early in the process, even before the president had nominated me.

 

      I was invited to the White House to interview with Judge Alberto Gonzales, then counsel to President Bush, and several of his colleagues in the west wing. The interview went very well, and I was told afterwards that it would be helpful to my chances if I could show that I would have the support of the Republican and Democratic Senate leaders I had worked for as Senate legal counsel, the non-partisan chief legal officer of the Senate. I went immediately to see the chairman of the judiciary committee, who was then Senator Orrin Hatch who, I was happy but not surprised to learn, was willing to be an enthusiastic supporter.

 

      Next, was a visit with Senator Harry Reid, then the whip of the Democratic Conference, who was likewise encouraging. Senator Reid insist that I meet with Democratic leader, Tom Daschle. I had come to know Senator Daschle well during my time as a staffer, and we both respected and liked one another. Now, as is often the case when meeting with a busy senator, especially when not part of his planned schedule, I had to wait for a while in the reception of his office. Upon learning that I was learning to see Senator Daschle, his chief of staff kindly invited me into his own office for a pleasant reunion in which we recalled projects we had worked on together. Senator Daschle then briefly joined us, greeted me with a warm hug, and voiced pleasure that I was under consideration for an appointment to the D.C. Circuit. It was all very, very heady stuff. But there was another person in the room who I did not know personally. He had not been on Senator Daschle’s staff while I served the Senate. I did know, however, that he was the architect of the Democrat strategy to filibuster some of President Bush’s judicial nominees, including the nominee whose withdrawal from consideration created an opening for me.

 

      The grey hairs among us will recall that was Miguel Estrada. Yep. I’m what you get when you really want Miguel Estrada on the D.C. Circuit but Senate Democrat wield the filibuster. In short, I’m an argument for or against the filibuster. Feel free to tell me your views later in private on that. So when Senator Daschle left the room, the staffer started asking me questions to probe who was this guy? Predictably, he asked me which judge had most shaped my thinking about the law. “John Marshall,” I said, assuming that was a safe answer. But that was not the tough question. He added, “Other than John Marshall.” I paused for a moment because that was the tough question because the answer was Robert Bork, and I hesitated to confess this to the architect of the Democrat’s filibuster strategy.

 

      Judge Bork was an anathema to many progressives. The smoke from his confirmation battle lingered still in the Senate hallways. So with more than a little anxiety and imagining that I was about to write my own chapter in Profiles in Courage, I mustered strength and answered, “Truthfully, Judge Bork. I agree with his views about the role of a judge.” Well, there was a slight pause in the conversation that made me uneasy. I was certain that I had just thrown away my nomination hopes. But I was wrong. Sensing my anxiety, the staffer assured me that my answer was acceptable. “Don’t worry, Tom,” he said. “We understand that President Bush gets to appoint judicial conservatives to the bench.” Well, emboldened by that response, I declared myself an acolyte of Robert Bork throughout the confirmation process. It must’ve worked; I was confirmed by a wide margin.

 

      Now, I became aware of Robert Bork during my first year of law school at UVA. I actually remembered the moment when I pulled Volume 47 of the Indiana Law Journal from a shelf in the library and began reading “Neutral Principles and Some First Amendment Problems.” I don’t want to make too much of the moment. No heavenly choir or rushing wind accompanied my reading. But I don’t want to make too little of it either. I found Judge Bork’s approach to the Constitution and to the role of judges in our democratic republic immensely satisfying. In those pages, I found, for the first time I can remember, an articulate rebuke to much of what I had been learning in law school about how judges should do their work under the Constitution.

 

      Bear with me, the old folks who are going to be very familiar with what I’m about to do, I'm going to give you a summary of Judge Bork’s views, cobbled together from his writings with some editorial license. I do this for the benefit of the youngsters in the audience.

 

      This used to be a canonical creed amongst conservatives. Less so now. Here we go. The United States was founded as a Madisonian system, which means that it contains two opposing principles that must be continually reconciled. The first principle is self-government, which means that in wide areas of life, majorities are entitled to rule, if they wish, simply because they are majorities.

 

      The second is that there are nonetheless some things majorities must not do. Some areas of life in which the individual must be free of majority rule. In these latter areas, majorities cannot rule no matter how democratically they decide to do so. These are the areas properly left to individual freedom, and coercion by the majority in these aspects of life is tyranny.

 

      The structure of the Constitution places the all-important function of defining these otherwise irreconcilable principles of majority power and minority freedom in a non-political institution: the federal judiciary. Placing this function with the courts creates the seeming anomaly of judicial supremacy in a democratic society. If the judiciary really is supreme, able to rule when and if it sees fit, the society is not democratic. For that reason, it is as important to freedom to confine the judiciary’s power to its proper scope as it is to confine that of the president, Congress, or state and local governments. Indeed, it is probably more important for only courts may not be called to account by the public.

 

      Okay, that’s my summary. I’ve just tried to reduce, in a couple of paragraphs, the heart of Judge Bork’s views about the role of a judge. Judge Bork relied heavily on the seminal article by Professor Herbert Wechsler, “Toward Neutral Principles in Constitutional Law” which was originally delivered as the Oliver Wendell Holmes lecture at the Harvard Law School. According to Wechsler, the deepest problem of our constitutionalism -- the deepest problem of our constitutionalism is laid bare when courts function as a naked power organ. This occurs, according to Wechsler, when a judge who is supposed to applied the law, let’s his judgment turn on the immediate result. That is, whether the outcome advances a cause he personally favors as a citizen.

 

      To avoid this problem, Wechsler insists that judges must resolve the cases before them according to neutral principles, by standards that transcend the case at hand, rather than impose their own value determinations. In every case, judges must derive, define, and apply generally applicable neutral principles gleaned from authoritative legal text.

 

      Okay, that’s the end of the recitation of abstract, dry ideas. But they're not dry. They're the living essence of Judge Bork’s view of the role of a judge. In short, according to Judge Bork, the structure of the Constitution, which places the lawmaking function with “We the people” through elected representatives, demands the judges be neutral.

 

      Now, the day after my confirmation, the confirmation of my nomination to the D.C. Circuit, I was the happy recipient of many congratulatory messages. I found out that some of my friends had sons and daughters who were in law school. I hadn’t heard from them in years. It was wonderful. One of these happy congratulatory messages, not about a child in law school, but just a good friend calling, came from a former law partner of mine who had clerked on both the D.C. Circuit, which I was about to join, and the Supreme Court. And he was a person who over the years I had valued his judgment. “Tom,” he asked, “can I give you some advice about being a judge?” I was eager to learn. I anxiously wanted to hear what he had to say. So here’s what he had to say. He said, “The first day of my clerkship on the D.C. Circuit, my judge told me, ‘This is how we go about our work. First, we learn the facts of the case as best we can because these real people, and they deserve to know that they're heard. That’s the first thing we do. The second thing we do is we think long and hard about the fair outcome, the equitable disposition, the just result, and once we’ve figured that out, we go find law to support our conclusion.’”

 

      Well, because the call’s purpose was congratulatory and not an invitation to engage in an extended discussion of the role of the judge under the Constitution, I thanked my friend for his counsel. But as I hung up the phone, I took a vow that I would do my best to heed his advice, his first bit of advice, to learn the facts of the case as best I could. And that I would take a vow that I would never heed his advice to decide cases by my own carefully developed sense of the common good.

 

      But with my friend’s experience in mind, I took a different approach to my clerks’ first day in chambers. I handed them a binder of readings, the first entry of which was 47 Indiana Law Journal 1. Something like the first chapter of Exodus.

 

      Which brings me to the present moment. Now, I was not on the campus at Yale Law School in April 1982 for the first event of The Federalist Society, but soon thereafter, I became an avid supporter, and over the years have spoken at dozens of chapter events on law school campuses across the nation, on numerous panels at the National Lawyers Convention, and I have even done some heavy lifting behind the scenes to protect The Federalist Society. What Leonard Leo and Gene Meyer and Lee Otis and others have done to transform the American legal landscape is breathtaking. It’s breathtaking.

 

[Applause]

 

      But I have some concerns. Back in the day, it was dedication to the idea of judicial conservatism that inspired us. We would work ourselves into a frenzy, jumping up and down, arms clad in a circle while chanting, “Neutral principles! Neutral principles! Neutral principles!” Yet, from some of the talks I hear at Federalist Society gatherings these days, I wonder did I step out of the room at a key moment and miss the explanation that we would talk about neutral principles so long as progressives were in control but once we got our people on the bench, once we had judges who were political conservatives, we would abandon judicial conservatism.

 

      Now I understand the appeal of judicial engagement to pursue one’s sense of the common good. I’m not sanguine at all about the state of our nation. But I’m here to urge us to resist that temptation. You will recognize the following from Professor Vermuele’s influential article “Beyond Originalism,” a short quote: “Originalism has now outlived its utility and has become an obstacle to the development of a robust, substantively conservative approach to constitutional law and interpretation. It is now possible to imagine a substantive moral constitutionalism that takes as its starting point moral principles that conduce to the common good; principles that judges should read into the majestic generalities and ambiguities of the written Constitution. The sweeping generalities and famous ambiguities of our Constitution,” says Professor Vermuele, “afford ample space for substantive moral readings that promote peace, justice, abundance, health, and safety.”

 

      My friend, Chief Judge William Pryor, has ably pointed out the danger in this approach. I simply add my amen and amen to Judge Pryor. It seems that Professor Vermuele’s model jurist is not Judge Bork or Justice Scalia but Justice Douglas. Indeed, Professor Vermuele’s sweeping generalities and famous ambiguities sounds a look like Justice Douglas’s “penumbras formed by emanation.”

 

      Common good originalism is what judicial conservatives have been fighting all this time. The only difference between this approach and the living Constitution espoused by progressives is the political result the proponents seek. Although, I might cheer some of the results that emerge from such an approach, that is not the role of the judge that Judge Bork envisioned or that I believe the Constitution requires. If we’re willing to sacrifice principled legal thought for the sake of what is, make no mistake political expedience, then I think we’ve given up the fight for an independent judiciary. We will have encouraged the courts to function as the naked power organ Wechsler and Bork warned against, and thus we will wreak havoc on our democracy. On those courts where the progressives are in the majority, and they will be—the pendulum ever swings—they will quote Professor Vermuele to impose their own vision of the common good based on their own moral principles.

 

      Professor Vermuele’s approach reminds me of the oft-quoted colloquy in Robert Bolt’s play A Man for All Seasons. Justice Scalia would quote this to his students at the University of Virginia in a rousing finale to the course. That the grey hairs among us remember the scene. We grew up with it. Thomas More’s family, spurred on by his zealous future son-in-law, Will Roper, urges the arrest of Richard Rich because he is a “bad man.” Now, forgive my lame attempt at acting but I’m going to recite the colloquy here.

 

      Margaret: Father, that man’s bad.

 

      More: There’s no law against that.

 

      Roper: There is. God’s law.

 

      More: Then God can arrest him.

 

      Alice: While you talk, he’s gone.

 

      More: And go he should, if he were the devil, until he broke the law.

 

      Roper: Now you’d give the devil the benefit of the law?

 

      More: Yes. What would you do? Cut a road through the law to get after the devil?

 

      Roper: Yes. I’d cut down every law in England to do that.

 

      More: And when the last law was down and the devil turned on you, where would you hide, Roper, the law’s all being flat? This country is planted with laws from coast to coast. Man’s laws not God’s. And if you cut them down, and you're just the man to do it, do you really think you could stand upright in the winds that would blow then? Yes, I’d give the devil benefit of law for my own safety’s sake.

     

      As an aside, I read this colloquy to my law clerks the day my opinion was released in House Judiciary Committee v. McGahn. Look it up. You’ll see why I read it.

 

      Years ago, I was honored to moderate the Rosenkranz debate at the National Lawyers Convention. The disputants were Hadley Arkes, my dear friend and soulmate in so many ways but one and Judge Alex Kozinski. The question, as I recall, was whether judges should use the natural law. Hadley went first and typically, he was eloquent and hilarious. Judge Kozinski followed. As I recall, his reply was brief. It went something like this: “Hadley, I don’t disagree with a single thing that you said about the natural law. I have only one response to your argument that judges should use the natural law: Stephen Reinhardt. You want to invite Stephen Reinhardt to use the natural law in his decisions?” I’m sorry, my dear friend Hadley, but in my view, Judge Kozinski won the debate that day, and I know what you're going to say, I'm going to avoid it. He’s going to say, “You haven’t read my book yet.” Okay, okay. You haven’t sent it to me yet. But anyway.

 

      The issue isn’t whether there’s natural law. I’m a Christian. Of course there is. The issue, as Judge Sutton constantly reminds us is, who decides. And the project of judicial conservatism, as I have understood it and tried to practice it, has been to keep the scope of the judiciary’s power within the confines the Constitution requires so as to preserve democratic values.

 

      But this is not the only threat to Judge Bork’s view of the role of a judge. Although my embrace of Judge Bork wasn’t a stumbling block to my confirmation in 2005, the times have changed, and now we see a full-throated attack on this approach from progressives. I doubt that my public embrace of Judge Bork would’ve been given a pass in my confirmation proceedings had I been nominated in 2019 instead of 2004. I witnessed this current hostility time and again as one of the few conservative members of President Biden’s Commission on the Supreme Court. We were the five or six who made the enterprise bipartisan. There were five or six of us out of a group of 36. Now some criticize that imbalance. I think it was Josh Blackman who noted that conservatives were overrepresented on that commission in comparison to the typical faculty lounge.

 

      While on the commission, repeatedly I would hear some of my fellow commissioners decry the Roberts Court as illegitimate. For many, it was a mantra that proceeded almost every comment. They seemed to subscribe to the view of Michael Klarman in his foreword to the Harvard Law Review issue covering the October 2019 term of the Supreme Court. He titled his article, without any nuance at all, “The Degradation of American Democracy—And the Court.” If you haven’t read Professor Klarman’s article, here’s my summary, which was first offered in my response to his foreword, also published in the Harvard Law Review. Professor Klarman’s thesis, and what I would hear from many of my colleagues on the Supreme Court commission, is that conservatives have declared war on democracy. The justices on the Supreme Court, he argues, defend the interests of the Republican Party, not because of any principled legal reasoning, but because of their personal values and political calculations. Klarman’s solution to preserve democracy is straightforward: Democrats should win the presidency and the Senate, entrench democracy against future Republican attacks with a series of bold moves like ignore the constitutional provision mandating two senators for every state,  create new states to expand their advantage in the Senate and Electoral College, replace the Electoral College with a direct popular vote, and consider packing new seats on the Supreme Court and the lower federal courts with judges appointed by Democratic presidents.

 

      Needless to say, Klarman’s form of constitutional hardball would radically reshape our political system. Professor Klarman’s attack upon the independence of the judiciary is especially troubling. In his view, it is “probably inevitable” that liberal and conservative judges will not act as neutral arbiters of law but will instead “legally rationalize the outcomes they prefer on controversial issues.” In discounting the possibility of an impartial judiciary, in abandoning that ideal, Professor Klarman and so many progressives embrace the unlikeliest of allies. I quote from Professor Klarman’s article, “One of the truest things President Trump has said in office is that there are Obama judges and Trump judges.” Klarman asks “Can anyone honestly think differently?”

 

      Well, actually, I do. Having served alongside judicial appointees of every president from Carter to Trump, I have seen firsthand that judges can and do put aside party and politics in a good-faith effort to interpret the law correctly. The judges I have known and with whom I have worked closely are committed to applying the law and not imposing their political preferences. I am not troubled by the fact that some judges read the New York Times instead of the Wall Street Journal. Most of them read both. Nor is it helpful to refer to “Republican” justices, a phrase Professor Klarman and many of my colleagues on the Supreme Court commission used dozens of time. The historical fact of an appointment by a Republican president didn’t matter to the justices who decided Hamdan, Bostock, Obergefell, or NFIB v. Sebelius. It never mattered to Chief Judge Sutton either.

 

      It is no doubt cathartic to impugn the motives and the character of judges who have different political or philosophical commitments, but it does great damage to public confidence in the judiciary, the crown jewel of our constitutional institutions.

 

      Now let me tell you a story that came out of my time on President Biden’s Commission on the Supreme Court, and it came from Walter Dellinger, the late Walter Dellinger, who was a frequent guest at Federalist Society events, even though he had very different views from many of us. There was some -- I can’t remember the exact nature of the colloquy, but I was giving this -- this was sort of mantra on the commission. “What do you mean illegitimate? They were nominated by a president, confirmed by the Senate, appointed by a president, they took the oath of office. That’s legitimate. Stop saying they're not legitimate.” That was like my standard line throughout. And at one point in the proceedings, Walter Dellinger came to my defense and told the story -- you may recall that when he was the acting solicitor general, he argued the Clinton v. Jones case. He argued that the lawsuit against President Clinton should be postponed until after his presidency, as a form of presidential immunity from litigation. He lost that 9-0. Walter told the story before the commission of where he was and how he learned of that loss. He was somewhere in China, I can’t remember if it was in Beijing or where, but he was somewhere in China, speaking to a group of Chinese law students when the word came down that he had lost in front of the Supreme Court of the United States, representing the president of the United States by nine to nothing. His students could not imagine that. Could not imagine that. So he, the losing litigant, explained to them what a great thing this was. What a great thing this was. That the idea of judicial independence is a fragile possibility in the best of times. Unfortunately, we don’t live in the best of times.

 

      In the final opinion I wrote on the D.C. Circuit, I warned against the dangers of reflexively imputing political positions to judges based on the party who appointed them. The D.C. Circuit sitting en banc, had voted to deny General Michael Flynn’s petition for a writ of mandamus compelling dismissal of the criminal prosecution against him. I joined the majority but wrote separately to emphasize that despite the media’s hyperbolic coverage and the inflammatory description served up by the conflict entrepreneurs of cable, the issue before the court was actually quite narrow and apolitical. We’re not asked to decide whether General Flynn’s prosecution was justified, nor whether political favoritism played an impermissible role in the government’s decision to stop pursing that prosecution. Instead, we were asked to answer a simple question: should the court of appeals intervene and grant the government’s motion to dismiss before the district court had actually issued a decision? Following established precedent, we declined to do so.

 

      I wrote to challenge the view that I knew would surely follow by some on cable that this decision was motivated by partisan impulses. Now, if you’ll forgive me for quoting me, it’s not long. “In cases that attract public attention, it is common for pundits and politicians to frame their commentary in a way that reduces the judicial process to little more than a skirmish in a partisan battle. The party affiliation of the president who appoints a judge becomes an explanation for the judge’s real reason for the disposition and the legal reasoning employed is seen as a cover for the exercise of raw political power. No doubt there will be some who describe the court’s decision today in such terms. But they would be mistaken. The questions presented are far removed from the partisan skirmishes of the day. Their resolution in this case involves nothing more and nothing less than the application of neutral princes about which reasonable jurist on this court disagree.” I then cited 47 Indiana Law Journal 1 as a somewhat self-indulgent, but grateful tip of the hat to the great man.

 

      What I wrote holds true for the vast majority of cases the federal courts hear. Judges may split along ideological lines sometimes quite predictably, but partisanship is rarely, if ever, the explanation for that division. And where it might be, let’s not applaud that departure from the ideal. Let’s call it out as a mistake.

 

      Justice Barrett has taken issue with those who claim that the justices are partisans in robes. Her evidence that they’re not: “Read our opinions,” she challenges the critics. Inspired by that challenge, I now tell my students that I will not listen to their criticism of Obergefell from the right or Dobbs from the left until they have sworn by affidavit that they have read all of the opinions in the case twice. I’m exaggerating but I do tell them I’m not going to talk to you about it unless you tell me you’ve read all of the opinions. Such a careful reading shows diligent judges struggling with vexing legal issues in good faith. Justice Kennedy was not intent on destroying the traditional family. Nor was Justice Alito seeking to harm women. Each was trying to discover what the law required and on that, reasonable people can disagree.

 

      These cases reveal the hard work that the justices put into understanding the views of the party and each other in an effort to reach the correct legal outcome. They demonstrate the justices’ willingness to compromise and to sometimes decide cases more narrowly than they might otherwise for the sake of consensus. And they reveal that even as the justices work through difficult and contentious issues, they strive to engage in civil discourse and treat one another with respect.

     

      We all know of the relationship of mutual respect and affection between Justices Ginsburg and Scalia. But have we read Justice Thomas’s note to Justice Breyer upon his retirement? Or have we read Justice Kagan’s tribute to Chief Justice Roberts last year at the American Law Institute? Do you know about the deep friendship between Justices Sotomayor and Barrett, which Justice Barrett described so movingly at last spring’s Rex E. Lee award luncheon?

 

      Among the American people, the judiciary remains the most respected of the branches of the federal government. Why? Why is that? Might it be because the judiciary is the constitutional institution that engages in reasoned discourse most often? That is a model that Professor Klarman and progressives should embrace and not excoriate. Just to be clear, I am no Dr. Pangloss. We do not live in the best of all possible worlds. Indeed, as I have written and as I include in almost all my public remarks these days, I believe that the republic is in peril on a number of fronts. I decry those who undermine confidence in the administration of our national elections by their baseless claims of fraud and conspiracy.

 

      Judge Luttig, Judge McConnell, Ben Ginsberg and I along with other conservatives wrote about this serious threat to the Constitution in our report “Lost, not Stolen: the Conservative Case that Biden Won and Trump Lost the 2020 Presidential Election.” In fact, I am not confident that we will meet Benjamin Franklin’s oft quoted challenge at the close of the Philadelphia Convention to keep the republic the delegates had just created. As I see it, the greatest danger to the republic is not misguided policy proposals but the rot of contempt that infects our body politic and has become the animating spirit of much of our public discourse. On that view of things, Professor Klarman’s jeremiad is no cure for the infection that ails the heart of our democracy. Indeed, the tone and temper of his complaint compound the problem.

 

      America’s experiment in representative government has faced serious crises before. But the best models of how to navigate treacherous shoals have done so with what scholar Matthew Holland calls “civic charity,” a settled intention to treat our fellow citizens as partners, even as friends in a common enterprise, not as enemies.

 

      Okay, so let’s start with the Philadelphia Convention of 1787 that created the Constitution. In July, the delegates faced the very real prospect of failure. Yet, by mid-September, they had produced the charter that would be the basis for our enduring success as a nation. In his letter transmitting the Constitution to Congress, the indispensable man, George Washington, attributed this surprising turn of events, what one popular account of the Convention called the “miracle at Philadelphia.” Washington attributed that to “the spirit of amity and of that mutual deference and concession which the peculiarity of our political situation rendered indispensable.” Derek Webb does a deep dive into the meaning of Washington’s explanation in his article “The Original Meaning of Civility: Democratic Deliberation at the Philadelphia Constitutional Convention.” Derek is busy working on a book version of that article. I look forward to it when it comes out.

 

      According to Derek, this spirit of amity Washington referred to was a commitment to civic friendship, even among political rivals from widely different geographical backgrounds. That commitment was expressed in the practices of the Convention. For instance, the Framers regularly dined together in Philadelphia’s taverns, and they carefully designated their deliberative processes so that they would listen to one another. Attendance was mandatory and while a delegate held the floor, the rules barred side conversations and even reading. The mutual deference to one another and the concession they practiced led to difficult compromises on contentious issues. But the miracle at Philadelphia was not a deus ex machina; it came about only because people made an effort to understand one another and were willing to give up some things they valued for the sake of unity. The Constitution they created calls upon us to commit ourselves to the same principle: compromise for the sake of unity that created the Union in the first place.

 

      At the very least, we need to approach our deliberations and discussions with civility, right? That’s the easy part. But the Constitution requires more than that. As Arthur Brooks wryly observes, “If I were to tell you that my wife and I are civil to each other, you would say get some counseling.” We must be willing to compromise, even and especially over critical matters if we are to continue this experiment in representative government. As Yuval Levin notes, “The American Constitution is intended to create common ground. Its structure compels Americans to be a little more accommodating of one another. It gives us practical experience in living and acting together.”

 

      The Constitution calls upon us to develop a temperament that doesn’t come naturally to most of us: humility. We must recognize that we might be wrong about what the common good requires, and that our fellow citizens might be right. The canonical expression of this constitutional temperament is Judge Learned Hand’s speech from 1944, “The Spirit of Liberty,” a speech that Justice Scalia would quote frequently. Judge Hand writes, “The spirit of liberty is the spirit which is not too sure that it’s right, which seeks to understand the minds of other men and women. Most important of all, we need to see one another as friends, partners in a shared pursuit of the common good rather than enemies. That we must make the choice to see each other as friends and not enemies is the teaching not only of the great religious traditions but some of our greatest American heroes.

 

      Michael Gerson observed, “The heroes of America are heroes of unity. Our political system,” Gerson wrote, “is designed for vigorous disagreement. It is not designed for irreconcilable contempt.” This idea surfaces again and again in key passages from American scripture: Winthrop on the Arabella, Jefferson’s first inaugural, King on the steps of the Lincoln Memorial, Obama’s red state/blue state speech. But most famously, at the moment of the greatest peril to our national unity, Abraham Lincoln implored, and we can all recite this, “We are not enemies but friends. We must not be enemies. Though passion may have strained, it must not break our bonds of affection.”

 

      This high-minded idealism has sustained the United States in the past and is, I believe, needed to pursue a more perfect union. We must rededicate ourselves to the virtue of civic charity and commit ourselves to the view that we are not enemies but friends. Without that commitment, we could make this government of the people, by the people, for the people perish from the earth. A healthy deliberative democracy depends, to a large degree, on accepting the premise that once political opponents are not evil, but they are fellow citizens who hold their views in good faith and deserve respect, especially when we disagree about matters of fundamental importance.

 

      The enterprise of reasoned debate, which the Framers of the Constitution knew was required to keep the republic they had created becomes a fool’s errand when the presumption of good faith is abandoned and the other side consists only of villains and demons. In that world, there is no reason to persuade, much less to listen. Arguments become nothing more than an instrument of political power, and the only sensible objective is to crush the other side. That is why it is so troubling that in our current political moment, contempt has replaced disagreement.

 

      NYU social psychologist, Jonathan Haidt, warns, “There is a very good chance that we will have a catastrophic failure of American democracy because, “says Haidt, “we just don’t know what a democracy looks like when you drain all trust out of the system.” I fear that this is where we are today.

 

      To an American nation deeply divided by toxic political polarization, former Utah Supreme Court Justice Dallin Oaks recently offered the most elegant explanation I have seen of what is required for citizens to heal this divide. “On contested issues,” he urged, “we should seek to moderate and to unify.” In that straightforward and simple directive, I believe Oaks captured the animating spirit that created the Constitution in 1787 and is necessary for its survival today.

 

      So what does it mean to support and defend the Constitution in this environment? At the very least, it means we will support and defend the rights protected by the Constitution and the structures of government it created. And on those counts, there is no group I know of that is more dedicated to those ends than The Federalist Society. But to support and defend means much more than that. It means that we will support and defend the values that gave life to the process by which the Constitution was created. Remember those values in Washington’s words? The “spirit of amity and of that mutual deference and concession which the peculiarity of our political situation renders indispensable.”

 

      Shortly after I joined the D.C. Circuit, I was invited to attend a Heritage Foundation event that honored Judge Bork. I readily accepted. Only later did I learn that I was expected to sing for my meal. Not literally, but I was asked to give a toast to Judge Bork. Now, many of you are well versed in giving toasts. I’m not. I'm a Latter-day Saint. I don’t drink. Who asks a Latter-day Saint to give a toast?

 

[Laughter]

 

      Ed Meese does.

 

[Laughter]

 

      So it was a risky decision on General Meese’s part, and I was nervous, not only because I was unfamiliar with the genre, but because Judge Bork would be seated at the head table. I’ll close my remarks today with the words I used to conclude that toast. “When I sit as a member of the D.C. Circuit, I pull my robe from a locker across a narrow aisle from a locker that bears a brass nameplate that says ‘Bork.’ Then I walk into a courtroom in which a Rembrandt-like portrait of Judge Bork hangs. He is watching, a brooding omnipresence. I am still an acolyte.”

 

      May God bless the memory of Robert Bork, and may God bless you, and may God bless the United States of America. Thank you very much.

 

[Applause]

 

Dean Reuter:  Judge Griffith, thank you so much for those wonderful and very timely remarks. I hope they reverberate well beyond the walls of this hall. With that, the proceedings of this Convention are concluded. I hope you will join us across the hall for our reception and return next year, may be here, may be at the Washington Hilton. For now, we are adjourned. Thank you very much.

     

 

     

 

 

5:30 p.m. - 7:00 p.m.
Closing Reception

2023 National Lawyers Convention

Palm Court Ballroom
The Mayflower Hotel
1127 Connecticut Avenue NW
Washington, DC 20006

Share

Back to top